Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Social and Economic Legislation during the Taft Court
|
Sunday, February 18, 2024
Social and Economic Legislation during the Taft Court
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Robert Post, The Taft Court: Making Law for a Divided Nation, 1921–1930 (Cambridge University Press, 2024). David Bernstein In this
symposium, my designated task was to review and discuss Part V of Robert Post,
The Taft Court: Making Law for a Divided Nation, 1921–1930 (Cambridge
University Press, 2024) This Part delves into social and economic legislation
during the Taft Court era. This section is notably well-crafted, showcasing
Professor Post’s erudition and extensive research, and is a significant
contribution to the relevant literature. However, I do not entirely agree with
Post's interpretation of the cases he discusses. Post's narrative
heavily leans on the overarching theme that the Supreme Court in the 1920s
participated in a society-wide desire for a "return to normalcy."
This shift followed the substantial and unprecedented government intervention
in civic and economic life accompanying the United States' entry into World War
I. The experience with an expansive government during the war heightened
American skepticism towards statist progressive ideas that had become dominant
before the conflict. Additionally,
many Americans were repelled by the wholehearted support that numerous
progressives had shown for the new federal wartime Leviathan and their desire
to make it a permanent fixture. Post cites a letter from William Allen White as
an illustration of the "innocent confidence of progressives." I think the big thing to do now is quietly organize a hundred
or so fellows who are dependable and who may take such steps as are necessary
after the war to serve all the economic and social campaigns that the war
brings to us. I think price fixing should be permanent, but not done by Wall
Street. I think the government should tighten its control either into ownership
or operation of the railroads. I think that labor arbitration should be a
permanent thing, and that we should federalize education through universal
training, making it a part of the system of education. To many Americans in the post-war
era, this attitude would not have appeared "innocent." Instead, it likely
appeared as if enthusiastic supporters of a federal government exerting control
over the economy, including regulating wages and prices nationwide, had
revealed progressives’ true intentions. Contrary to their pre-war claims of
seeking significant reform within the existing system, it seemed they actually sought
radical, even revolutionary, changes to the American economy and government
system. In the portion of the book I was
tasked with reviewing and commenting on, Post overlooks the additional influence
of events in Europe on this dynamic. The fact that European nations had become
entangled in a brutal war without a clear purpose seemed to affirm America's
superiority to Europe. Both in the past and today, many progressives looked to
Europe as a model for their more interventionist and nationalist government
policies. The emergence of the USSR, Communist revolutions in Germany and
Hungary, and the sympathy expressed for Communism and anarchism in the US, especially
among immigrants, heightened the apprehension of foreign ideas, including
progressive concepts associated with Continental thinkers. The theme of a "return to
normalcy" provides a crucial perspective on the Taft Court era, especially
considering President Harding's successful 1920 campaign on that very platform.
Harding's victory reflected widespread dissatisfaction with the war and its
impact on what we now call civil and economic liberties. Notably, it was
Harding who appointed the Justices who steered the court in a more libertarian
direction during the 1920s. The inclination toward a
"return to normalcy," seeking a shift back to pre-War levels of
government regulation, is a key factor in understanding the overall approach of
the pre-Depression Taft Court. This desire is particularly evident in the
Court's skepticism toward novel or contentious applications of government
regulatory power. The apprehension of government
overreach, intensified by the government's actions during the war, contributed
to the Court's effort to systematize its jurisprudence on the liberty of
contract. Previously perceived as somewhat arbitrary and inconsistent, the
Court aimed to provide clarity. In the case of Adkins v. Children’s Hospital
(1923), Justice George Sutherland outlined acceptable infringements on liberty
of contract beyond traditional police power concerns. These included
regulations related to rates and charges for businesses with a public interest,
contracts for public work, payment of wages, and hours of labor for health and
safety reasons. Sutherland emphasized that, aside from these exceptions,
"freedom of contract is the general rule, and restraint the
exception," justifiable only in exceptional circumstances. Looking more broadly, instances of
perceived government overreach during World War I shed light on why the Supreme
Court was willing to resurrect and broaden doctrines limiting government power
that appeared to have been overshadowed by the progressive movement.
Traditionalist conservative Justices advocating natural rights notions had no representation
on the Taft Court after 1911. Law review commentary in the 1920s that advocated
limits on government authority was philosophically incoherence. As extensively detailed by Barry
Cushman, the Taft Court Justices typically labeled as "conservative"
a held a spectrum of generally moderate but progressive political views before
joining the Court. Barry Cushman, The Secret Lives of the Four Horsemen, 83 Va.
L. Rev. 559, 559-60 (1997); see also Logan E. Sawyer III, Creating Hammer
v. Dagenhart, 21 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 67, 88 (2012). Despite
this, and likely in part in response to the significant expansion of government
authority during the war, these Justices aimed to uphold traditional
limitations on government power while largely accommodating the growth of
progressive regulation. Conversely, their counterparts, including Justice Louis
Brandeis, were more radical Progressives reluctant to concede that the
Constitution imposed significant and judicially enforceable constraints on the
scope of government authority. This
analysis is at least consistent with Post’s return to normalcy theme. His
framework, however, is less useful in explaining the outcome of specific cases.
As Post acknowledges, the Court continued to uphold some rather novel and
intrusive exercises of the police power, while invalidating other exercises of
government regulatory authority, some of which seemed rather anodyne. Post’s analysis improves
significantly upon the once-robust literature that sought to explain the
Court’s rulings by reference to the Justices’ alleged, but never documented,
devotion to Social Darwinism. Nevertheless, Post still clings to
some mythology inherited from Progressive-era critics of Lochner.
Quoting an article by Felix Frankfurter from 1916, and also citing Ernst
Freund, Post states that Progressives had repudiated Lochner v. New York
(1905) because “[t]he majority opinion was based upon ‘a common understanding’
as to the effect of work in bakeshops upon ... those engaged in it. ‘Common
understanding’ has ceased to be the reliance in matters calling for essentially
scientific determination.” Post believes that the Court’s return to normalcy
included a return to this “common understanding” vision of what constitutes
appropriate regulatory action, and what is an undue and thus unconstitutional interference
with normal ordinary economic activity. The
problem is that this is an incorrect, or at least incomplete, understanding of Lochner.
Justice Peckham’s opinion in Lochner indeed suggested that the Court
should uphold the hours legislation at issue in that case if to the “common
understanding” baking was an unhealthful occupation in need of special
regulation. But the Court also would have upheld the law if scientific evidence
before the Court had suggested that regulating bakers’ hours served a
legitimate health purpose. The problem, however, was that the
only party that provided any evidence about the health of bakery workers was Lochner,
and that evidence showed that baking was not unhealthful relative to other
common professions. Peckham alluded to this evidence without directly citing to
it when he wrote, “In looking through statistics regarding all trades and
occupations, it may be true that the trade of a baker does not appear to be as
healthy as some other trades, and is also vastly more healthy than still
others.” In one of the more remarkable
interpretive miscues in Supreme Court history, critics nevertheless almost immediately
accused Peckham of engaging in formalism and ignoring what they saw as the
obvious fact that baking was unhealthful. See, e.g., Roscoe Pound, Common Law
and Legislation, 21 Harv. L. Rev. 383 (1908). For generations,
historians and law professors even accused Peckham of making up the statistics
he alluded to. If they had bothered to look at the briefs in the case, they
would have seen exactly where he got them. Conversely, Justice Harlan's
dissent is often presented as an example of how a judicious judge, even one
supporting liberty of contract in principle, should have assessed the facts.
Harlan cited several studies indicating the unhealthfulness of baking. The
problem, however, is that none of these studies were part of the record, lower
court opinions, or briefs. Harlan's references did not even come from his own
research, but from a pamphlet published by the bakers' union. Considering how the Supreme Court
functioned, it's uncertain whether Peckham reviewed Harlan's dissent before
delivering his opinion. Notably, Peckham did not make any direct reference to the
dissent in his own opinion. On a related note, historian Nicholas Mosvick has
compellingly argued that Justice McKenna, who frequently cast the deciding vote
in labor regulation cases, paid particular attention to whether there was
empirical evidence backing a specific labor law. Nicholas Mosvick,
Rehabilitating Lochner: A Study in the limitations of a Constitutional
Revolution, 18 Tex. Rev. L. & Pol. 151, 162-64 (2013). Peckham's
reference to scientific evidence played a crucial role in inspiring Louis
Brandeis to submit his famous brief on the detrimental effects of long hours on
women’s health in Muller v. Oregon (1908). Returning to Lochner, aside
from Justices Peckham and Brewer, the relevant Justices typically showed
significant deference to purported health regulations, including maximum hours
laws. Besides the scientific evidence presented by Lochner, two additional
factors likely influenced the Lochner majority. First, although the
state asserted that the law in question was a health law, it was placed in the
state labor code, not the health code, and a union representative was part of
the panel responsible for enforcing the law. Second, the hours law in question
was notably strict, lacking provisions for overtime, and violations carried
criminal penalties instead of civil ones. For example, a baker offering triple pay to
employees for an extra hour of work to complete an important holiday order
could face imprisonment. These factors, combined with the studies presented by
Lochner, probably persuaded the swing Justices to align with the majority. In
short, it’s incorrect to suggest that Lochner ignored facts and evidence
about the underlying law in favor of a singular reliance on common knowledge. With that said, let's delve into
Post's discussion of two major liberty-of-contract cases: Jay Burns Baking
v. Bryan (1924) and Adkins v. Children’s Hospital (1923). While Post
discusses additional police power cases, including in a chapter on "businesses
affected with a public interest," I wll concentrate on these two cases for
brevity’s sake. Jay Burns Baking involved a
Nebraska law aimed to prevent consumer fraud by mandating loaves be baked in
half-pound increments, with a strict one-ounce tolerance for over- or
under-weight bread. Initially, I suspected that this law had special-interest
origins. I speculated that modern factory bakeries favored these laws, finding
compliance easier, while mom-and-pop bakeries opposed them. Despite my suspicion,
after investigating with a research assistant through a search of baking
industry journals, we found no supporting evidence. Our conclusion was that
bakers' support or opposition to such laws had no clear correlation to any
discernible factor. According to Post, the Court, in
rendering its decision, was aware that since the war, bakers had easily adhered
to tolerances even stricter than those imposed by Nebraska. This information
was detailed in Brandeis's extensive dissent discussing wartime regulations.
Nevertheless, a 7-2 majority invalidated the law, deeming it an undue
interference with occupational liberty, partly because compliance was seen as
burdensome. Post suggests that the Court overlooked existing evidence because
the majority deemed it unreasonable for the state, based on common knowledge,
to interfere in this manner. I disagree
with Post that the majority should have considered Brandeis’s analysis
definitive. As Post acknowledges, Nebraska presented only a “perfunctory”
defense of its law. Brandeis’s analysis of wartime regulations was based on
information almost entirely outside the record. As with Harlan’s dissent in Lochner,
it’s far from clear that the Supreme Court should consider evidence that is not
in the record. Among other things, Justices going off on their own evidentiary
expeditions without an opportunity for the parties to weigh in has obvious
potential for abuse. Post
concludes that the controversy over whether unwrapped bread could meet the
law's weight requirement wasn't central to the legal dispute. In my
understanding, the evidence from the parties suggested two ways for bakers to
comply: wrapping loaves in wax paper or using lower-quality flour and leaving
the bread unwrapped. Contrary to Post's treatment of this issue as
inconsequential, wrapping bread negatively affects the crust texture.
Essentially, Nebraska gave bakers the choice of baking lower-quality bread or
selling only wrapped loaves. Brandeis's dissent doesn't counter this point. Justice Butler’s majority opinion
highlighted the strong demand for unwrapped bread and affirmed bakers' right to
provide it. This reasoning alone justified invalidating the law. Butler also
argued that the one-ounce tolerance the law provided, intended to prevent
deceptive practices, was too strict. He suggested it was unreasonable to assume
consumers would mistake a significantly smaller loaf for a one-pound loaf. Brandeis did not present contrary evidence. Professor Barry Cushman has
previously disputed Post’s interpretation of Jay Burns Baking, which
Post expressed in an earlier law review article. Barry Cushman, Some Varieties
and Vicissitudes of Lochnerism, 85 B.U. L. Rev. 881 (2005). Post
acknowledges Cushman’s argument, but rejects it. Most pertinent, Cushman points out that Justice
Butler himself wrote a later unanimous opinion upholding a bread-weight law
that provided for greater (3 ounce) tolerances. This shows, Cushman argues,
that the Jay Burns Baking decision was based on the specific flaws the
Justices saw in Nebraska’s law, not some inchoate yearning for normalcy or
reliance on common knowledge. I side with Cushman, and would add
one more point. Jay Burns Baking was a 7-2 ruling, with only Brandeis
and Holmes dissenting. Brandeis and Holmes, of course, thought that the police
power in the economic realm was virtually unlimited. So despite Brandeis’s
extensive dissent, it’s more likely the dissenters, rather than the majority, who
were relying on strong ideological presuppositions, in this case favoring
judicial deference to regulation, rather than focusing on the facts of the
case. Adkins
v. Children’s Hospital, meanwhile, was a much closer 5-3 ruling,
with Justice Brandeis recused (and who surely would have been a fourth vote to
uphold the law). In Adkins, Justice George Sutherland wrote the opinion
invalidating a DC minimum wage law that applied to only to women as a violation
of the right to liberty of contract. Post adopts the traditional progressive
perspective on women-only minimum wage laws. He emphasizes the rationale that
women, being in a weaker bargaining position than men, required protection from
receiving inadequate wages. However, this view overlooks the complex political
and economic dynamics surrounding such laws. While
some advocates of women-only minimum wage laws aimed to improve employment
standards for women, others had less noble intentions. Supporters included
male-only trade unions seeking to limit competition from women, opponents of
immigration who believed married immigrant women were being forced to work by
their husbands, paternalists focused on preserving women's health (especially
reproductive health), moralists concerned about the potential moral risks of
low-wage, long-hour jobs leading women into immorality and prostitution,
"family wage" advocates hoping to shield men from what they
considered as "destructive" competition from women workers,
"maternalists" aiming to promote and preserve women's maternal roles
in the family, and eugenicists who believed that working women weakened the
race. Paul
overlooks the less savory motivations for sex-specific minimum wage laws. He also
only briefly discusses feminist opposition to these laws, notably by Alice Paul
of the National Women’s Party, in a few endnotes. This context, however,
significantly influenced Adkins’s outcome. Many women’s rights
advocates, including Alice Paul, opposed gender-specific minimum wage laws but
supported laws applicable to all workers. Justice Sutherland, was not a
strict opponent of government regulation, see, e.g., Euclid v. Ambler Realty
(1926), but in his pre-Court career, he had been a political ally of Alice
Paul and a strong advocate for women’s rights. He led the push for the
Nineteenth Amendment in the Senate and helped draft the proposed Equal Rights
Amendment. Paul resisted attempts to secure additional support for the
amendment by adding a provision exempting sex-specific protective labor laws. These facts help account not just
for Sutherland’s joining (and writing) the majority in Adkins, but also
for his rejecting minimum wage supporters' claim that women workers needed
special minimum wage laws because they were vulnerable to exploitation by employers
in ways men were not--that, unlike men, women were unable to enter a fair
bargain for wages. Sutherland proclaimed, But the ancient inequality of the sexes, otherwise than
physical, as suggested in the Muller Case has continued ‘with diminishing
intensity.’ In view of the great--not to say revolutionary--changes which have
taken place since that utterance, in the contractual, political, and civil
status of women, culminating in the Nineteenth Amendment, it is not
unreasonable to say that these differences have now come almost, if not quite,
to the vanishing point. In this aspect of the matter, while the physical
differences must be recognized in appropriate cases, and legislation fixing
hours or conditions of work may properly take them into account, we cannot
accept the doctrine that women of mature age, sui juris, require or may be
subjected to restrictions upon their liberty of contract which could not
lawfully be imposed in the case of men under similar circumstances. To do so
would be to ignore all the implications to be drawn from the present day trend
of legislation, as well as that of common thought and usage, by which woman is
accorded emancipation from the old doctrine that she must be given special
protection or be subjected to special restraint in her contractual and civil
relationships. One can certainly
dispute, as the dissenters did—Holmes: "it will take more than the
Nineteenth Amendment to convince me that there are no differences between men
and women, or that legislation cannot take those differences into account”—whether
women’s attainment of civic equality meant that they should no longer be
treated as presumptively necessitous in the economic marketplace. Nevertheless,
I believe that any discussion of Sutherland’s opinion in Adkins should
emphasize his feminist background. See David E. Bernstein, Revisiting
Justice George Sutherland, the Nineteenth Amendment, and Equal Rights for
Women, 20 G’town J. L. Pub. Pol’y 143 (2022). Beyond
that, Sutherland was troubled by two aspects of the law. First, the law put the
burden of supporting a worker on the employer rather than on the public, even
if the employee was not worth the mandated wage. This is not a very strong
argument, especially because the law did not require employers to retain any employees
whose work was not worth the relevant wage. Post emphasizes this part of
Sutherland’s opinion, suggesting that the redistributive aspect of Adkins
was the key to the Court’s hostility to the law. He associates this hostility
with the Court’s purported opposition to class legislation—opposition that I
believe has been grossly exaggerated, at least with regard to liberty-of-contract
cases brought under the Due Process clauses. See David E. Bernstein,
Class Legislation, Fundamental Rights, and the Origin of Lochner and
Liberty of Contract, 26 Geo. Mason L. Rev. 1024 (2019). I suspect, meanwhile, that a second
aspect of the law was the key factor in, if not Sutherland’s opinion, at least
his ability to get a five-vote majority, and in particular, to get Justice
McKenna’s swing vote. As previously noted, Post sees the law’s basic purpose as
ensuring that women workers earned enough to live on. Yet, the wages set by
DC’s minimum wage law varied dramatically among enumerated job categories: These orders fix the sum to be paid to a woman employed in a
place where food is served or in a mercantile establishment, at $16.50 per
week; in a printing establishment, at $15.50 per week; and in a laundry, at $15
per week, with a provision reducing this to $9 in the case of a beginner. If a
woman employed to serve food requires a minimum of $16.50 per week. The government
could not explain why women’s cost of living varied depending on which industry
they worked in. As Sutherland wrote, “it is hard to understand how the same
woman working in a printing establishment or in a laundry is to get on with an
income lessened by from $1 to $7.50 per week.” While Post gives short shrift to
this argument, it does, in fact, undermine the government’s claim that the
basis for the law was to ensure that women earn a living wage. Rather, it seems
more likely that the law as implemented tried to ensure that women could not
undercut, or compete, with male workers, to whom the law did not apply. It’s
unlikely coincidental that the lowest wage set was for laundry workers, a field
dominated by women. Another objection raised by
Sutherland to the law was that the power of the government to create a minimum
wage also implies the power to create a maximum wage. Generations of historians
have been dismissive of this objection, suggesting that it was a dystopian
fantasy on his part. These historians ignore that the US government ultimately
did later fix wages several times, beginning with the National Industrial
Recovery Act. In at least two instances, during World War II and via President
Nixon’s wage controls, such wage-fixing reduced workers’ wages below market
level. Before
I conclude, I should mention one significant quibble I have with Post’s
editorial choices. There is a great deal of interesting side discussions in the
endnotes. My own preference is for endnotes to be primarily just endnotes, with
little to no additional text. If material is important enough to be included,
it’s important enough to be in the main body of the book, not hidden in endnotes.
And in this case, it would be a particular shame if readers neglected the
notes, as they are rich with important details. At the least, I wish the
editors of the Holmes Devise had chosen to use footnotes instead of endnotes,
so one would not have to constantly consult materials many pages away from the
text to get the full story. To sum
up, I agree with Post that a backlash against perceived out-of-control
government during World War I was a significant factor in the Supreme Court’s
own backlash against what had seemed, by 1917, to be a retreat from any
meaningful review of most purported police power regulations. I disagree,
however, with the implication that the Taft Court Justices who were in the
majority in cases like Jay Burns Baking and Adkins were inclined
to ignore the government’s case for the laws in question in favor of a Lochner-like
reliance on common knowledge amounting, perhaps, to unexamined prejudices. As I
have noted, the Lochner opinion itself paid due attention to relevant
empirical evidence. And I think a fair reading of Jay Burns Baking, Adkins,
and other cases suggests that the Court was sensitive to the specific relevant
context, language, and practical effects of each law. David Bernstein is
University Professor of Law at Antonin Scalia Law School, George Mason
University. You can reach him by e-mail at dbernste@gmu.edu.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |