E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Jeffrey Rosen “At least four distinct narratives about
the nature and purpose of constitutional law are visible within the Taft
Court,” Robert Post writes in his landmark and extraordinarily illuminating contribution
to the Holmes Devise. Post describes a Court bitterly divided over questions of
constitutional meaning and interpretation. It’s striking, however, that none of
these four narratives can be described as originalist or textualist in the contemporary
sense. Common
law constitutionalism, associated with Justice James McReynolds, held that the
courts should speak for the customs and traditions of the American people,
which were embodied in common law rather than ordinary statutes. James
McReynolds was a traditional Southern Democrat who was suspicious of federal
power and devoted to states’ rights and individual liberties for white men. (McReynolds
was also a notorious racist and anti-Semite who declared that he “distrusted all Jews” and “that Jewish lawyers looked on
law as if handed down from Zion.”) McReynolds
believed that law inheres public sentiment, and public sentiment is reflected
in custom rather than ordinary legislation. He therefore looked for legal
guidance to the traditions, customs and habits reflected in the common law,
rather than in statutes or the constitutional text. McReynolds
defended unenumerated rights of property and contract—which he believed were
rooted in morality as well as history and tradition— as a bulwark against the
intrusions of the nascent administrative state. Majoritarianism,
associated with Oliver Wendell Holmes, held that courts should defer to the
dominant view of the majority, as expressed by legislatures rather than the
common law. Holmes “flatly rejected,” Post argues, “the
equation of law with custom and tradition.” His experiences in the Civil War,
where he was wounded three times and nearly died, imbued him with a deep
skepticism of moral absolutes of any kind. Convinced that truth was whatever a
majority determined it to be, he concluded that deference to legislatures was
necessary to prevent society from breaking into open violence. The purpose of
law was to allow majorities to prevail over minorities, and the purpose of
courts was to allow the dominant group to express its views through
legislation. Judges should invalidate laws only in the rare circumstances when
they clashed with what Holmes called “the literal meaning and plain intent of a
constitutional text.” As a result, Holmes upheld laws he reviled on policy
grounds. “The more powerful interests must be
more or less reflected in legislation; which, like every other device of man or
beast, must tend in the long run to aid the survival of the fittest,” Holmes
wrote in a passage that Post calls the “kernel” of his jurisprudence. Holmes
added, “if my fellow citizens want to go to Hell
I will help them. It’s my job.” Democratic constitutionalism, associated with Louis
Brandeis, held that courts should protect individual rights and liberties, in
addition to deferring to democratic majorities, in order to promote human
flourishing and democratic self-government. Brandeis agreed with Holmes that
courts should rarely invalidate social and economic legislation under the
Fourteenth Amendment, but for very different reasons. “Holmes thought courts
ought to defer to statutes because legislation best reflected the dominant
opinion of a community, which was the expression of its sovereignty,” Post
writes. “By contrast, Brandeis believed that courts ought to defer to legislation
because statutes were the result of a democracy that empowered persons to
become ‘free citizens of a free country [who] may perform their duties as
citizens.’” If Holmes viewed democracy as a flawed but necessary tool to
maintain social order, Brandeis viewed it as a vehicle for personal as well as
political self-government and human flourishing. This difference was obvious in
their First Amendment jurisprudence, where Holmes protected free speech on the pragmatic
grounds “that the best test of truth is the power of the thought to get itself
accepted in the competition of the market” while Brandeis protected free speech
on the idealistic grounds “that the greatest menace to freedom is an inert
people; that public discussion is a political duty; and that this should be a
fundamental principle of the American government.” An opponent of the curse of
bigness, in business and government, Brandeis was also a Jeffersonian fiercely
devoted to individual liberty as well as states’ rights. The
neoliberal constitutionalism associated with William Howard Taft held that
courts should protect rights of property and contract, the necessary engines of
economic prosperity. Unlike the Jeffersonian
Brandeis, Taft’s heroes were John Marshall and Alexander Hamilton; and like the
Federalists, Taft exalted national economic development over states’ rights. As
Post writes, “Taft and Brandeis differed in many ways in their perspectives on constitutional
law, but the most fundamental point of disagreement is that Taft understood the
Constitution to establish “the security of private property and free contract”
in order to safeguard “the chief agent in the material progress of the human
race.” Taft’s belief that the Supreme Court’s role was to protect property
rights from impulsive majorities was grounded in utilitarian (rather than
strict constructionist or originalist) reasoning. He did not primarily rely on
constitutional text, history, tradition, natural law, or common law traditions.
(In this sense, he protected private property for different reasons than
McReynolds.) Instead, Post writes, he “believed that judicial review and
constitutional law were necessary to protect the inducements for the ‘industry
and self-restraint’ that created civilization.” Like some of his conservative
colleagues, such as George Sutherland and Pierce Butler, Taft “envisioned
Americans as joined together in dedication to ongoing economic expansion” and
“conceived of that commitment as deeper and more vital than the public’s
investment in any statute that might emerge from the superficial give and take
of the legislative process.” Post’s brilliant typology reveals that none of the four
leading justices on the Taft Court considered themselves originalists or
textualists as those terms are used on the Supreme Court today. Brandeis was
committed to democracy, Holmes to majoritarianism, McReynolds to traditional
morality, and Taft to protecting private property and a vibrant national
economy. Modern originalists are leapfrogging over the Taft era to resurrect an
older, anti-Federalist tradition of strict construction and textualism that
dates back to Spencer Roane and John Taylor’s response to McCulloch v.
Maryland. Whether that anti-Federalist tradition is, in fact, consistent
with the original understanding and public meaning of the Constitution is a subject
for another symposium. Jeffrey Rosen is President & CEO of the National
Constitution Center and a professor at the George Washington University Law
School. His new book is The Pursuit of Happiness: How Classical Writers on
Virtue Inspired the Lives of the Founders and Defined America. jrosen@constitutioncenter.org