Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Constitutionalism: For and Against
|
Thursday, July 06, 2023
Constitutionalism: For and Against
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Martin Loughlin, Against Constitutionalism (Harvard University Press, 2022). Martin Loughlin I should begin by explaining the relevance of practice to my argument. Joseph Fishkin suggests that I too readily identify constitutionalism with a particular expression of American constitutional practice. This expression is one that he and others have criticized, but he emphasizes that US history is much more complicated. This I readily concede. But it was never part of my objective to present an account of the history of constitutional practice. The book was not intended to offer a nuanced account of developments in the USA, nor in Germany, India, South Africa, France or other regimes discussed. It is not a study in comparative constitutional practice but an attempt to identify constitutionalism as a specific ideology, that is, a way of imagining political order. It examines the influence this type of symbolic representation of a political regime exerts in today’s world. The USA must form a central element of this study because, as I argue, constitutionalism is the unique contribution it has made to the modern theory of government. But my aim in considering US constitutional history is solely to indicate how the main features of this ideology are derived from its dominant modern discourse. No history of a regime can be convincingly presented as a coherent narrative, let alone one of continuing progress. But this is precisely what ideologists seek to do. They draw on the power of the imagination to account for the regime’s historical evolution in order to guide action in the face of present choices and future possibilities. They present a symbolic representation of the ideals that are assumed to bind the nation. Is this not the way the American Creed does its work? This is how the essential precepts of constitutionalism confer meaning on the American system of government, providing official endorsement to a story of individualism, freedom, equality, and democracy. But it is also capable of masking a more complicated history, one of imperial ambition, institutionalized racial hierarchy, and structured inequality. In response to that type of claim, Yasmin Dawood raises a challenging counterfactual: where would the United States have ended up without constitutionalism? I accept that the 1787 settlement was a logical consequence of bringing together 13 former colonies into a federal scheme. And I accept Jack Balkin’s point that federal systems require more judicial review than unitary systems. But since I adopt the interpretative method of seeking to understand what is going on rather than searching for some ideal normative theory, what might have been cannot be part of my exercise. As I suggest in the book, if the arrangement works for Americans then, however peculiar it might seem to outsiders, it is not for us to denounce those practices. That said, things might indeed have turned out differently. The Bill of Rights, for example, was not part of the initial scheme, Jefferson and his disciples persistently argued (unsuccessfully) against making a fetish of the Constitution, and the more restrained methods of review advanced by Thayer, Holmes and Frankfurter might, in different circumstances, have gained more traction. Gowder extends his critique by making a more general claim. He suggests that my argument that the course of contemporary trends is ‘a consequence of some ideological structure called “constitutionalism”’ is obfuscation. ‘It’s just good old-fashioned power’. Or, as his essay title states: ‘It’s Power, not Theory, that Keeps the Left from Having its own Constitutionalism’. To my mind, this claim rests on a somewhat simplistic appreciation of power and the way it operates. This brings me to a common theme across various essays: that my concern is not with constitutionalism as such but with juristocracy. It is said that I identify ‘constitutionalism (and juristocracy) with strong judicial review’ (Balkin), that ‘the judiciary is so central to the argument that at times Loughlin uses the word “constitutionalism” interchangeably with “constitutional judicial review”’ (Fishkin), and that ‘the main problem is not constitutionalism so much as an overly powerful judicial branch’ (Dawood). I understand the point, but it is misconceived. Strong judicial review, or juristocracy, is by now a well understood phenomenon and is obviously a significant feature of the contemporary trend I have been criticizing. But it is an error to reduce my argument about constitutionalism to one against juristocracy because, once again, it is born of the attempt to conflate an ideology with a practice. Another common theme of the essays is that although I seek to defend constitutional democracy against constitutionalism, the former is not as well developed as the latter. As Balkin accurately notes, the problem is that the book ‘pivots on a distinction between constitutionalism, which is an ideology or belief system, and constitutional democracy, which is a political ordering’. This is not to say that constitutional democracies do not have underpinning ideologies: the British constitution rests on a set of narrative tropes that legitimate the regime,[4] and Pierre Rosanvallon’s studies have examined change in French political ideologies since the Revolution.[5] But my point is that constitutional democracies are variable regimes with differing ideological underpinnings, whereas the ideology of constitutionalism, though nurtured in the US, has become universal. That, perhaps, is too simple; a key part of my argument, after all, is that the contemporary processes of constitutionalization are now working to reshape constitutional democracies as constitutionalist regimes. Balkin thinks so, arguing that the lack of a detailed account of constitutional democracy is ‘the book’s greatest weakness’. Julie Suk skilfully pursues this point by packaging constitutionalism not as ideology but as practice. Claiming that some constitutional courts have operated to bolster democracy, she emphasises that ‘juristocracy exists on a continuum, as does constitutional democracy, … sometimes described by the language of “strong-form” and “weak-form” judicial review’. I’m tempted at this point to invoke Maitland’s argument that lawyers are skilled at drawing distinctions in kind where others see only differences of degree. But Suk’s point deserves a more considered reply. I begin by endorsing Sandy Levinson’s defence of my position: that I am ‘not against the idea of “a constitution” per se’, which must contain clear rules about who has authority to govern, on what terms, and how they are called to account. I would go further in that the constitution should include a statement of basic rights that government must protect. Indeed, I think that once a documentary constitution is adopted, courts have an important role to perform in ensuring that governmental bodies keep within the jurisdictional limits of their lawful authority. So how does constitutional democracy differ from constitutionalism? Whatever constitutional democracy is, notes Balkin, ‘it’s not a system in which judges are very powerful or in which the constitution is central to national identity’. Once again, he identifies a critical issue: the sixth precept, that the constitution is as expression of ‘collective political identity’. The theme is taken up in more detail by Sandy Levinson. Levinson surmises, correctly, that I am sceptical of the notion of ‘constitutional identity’. It is advanced by his colleague, Gary Jacobsohn, who (in Levinson’s words) argues that since ‘a constitution instantiates the fundamental commitments and values (i.e., “identity”) of a given society’ to ignore the concept is to ‘engage in wilful ignorance of an important feature of many arguments about constitutional meaning’. This is surely an accurate synopsis, since Jacobsohn maintains that this concept ‘reflects an understanding of the constitution as the foundation for both legal and social relations within a polity’.[6] But Jacobsohn’s claim, I suggest, makes sense only in the purview of constitutionalism. The concept of ‘identity’ has only recently appeared in political discourse. The term ‘collective political identity’ seems first to have been adopted in Lucien Pye’s book, Aspects of Political Development, published in 1966. It is a metaphor that weaves together myth, ritual, and symbol to establish a notion of collective identity. But although Pye used the term to confer a sense of the continuity over time, the collective body he was referring to is ‘the nation’. The leap Jacobsohn makes from ‘national’ to ‘constitutional’ identity is symptomatic of the ideological shift that constitutionalism purports to effect. It is analogous to the manoeuvre Laurence Tribe makes when he asserts the existence of an invisible constitution, one that ‘floats in a vast and deep – and, crucially, invisible – ocean of ideas, propositions, recovered memories, and imagined experiences that the Constitution as a whole puts us in a position to glimpse’.[7] As Levinson notes, that makes sense only if we embrace the idea of the ‘total constitution’ and assume that the Constitution is constitutive of the state. This is a claim that, as I try to show (AC ch.3) is unwarranted. I come now to my final theme. Gowder explains that the conversion of constitutional democracies into constitutionalist regimes is attributable to ‘the rise of contemporary inclusive liberal states in which the traditional sources of social solidarity, like shared racial, ethno-national and religious identity, are ruled out’. This is why constitutions acquire the task of ‘supplying a foundation for shared social meanings in addition to just setting forth the rules of the game’. Dawood makes similar observations. Constitutional democracies, in short, are suffering an identity crisis, one that arises because their traditional sources of authority are being dissipated. My defence of constitutional democracy is, for Gowder, troublesome. It smacks, for the reasons he gives, of ‘old-fashioned nationalism’. I recognize the dangers and do not pretend to have the answers. All I can say here is that the issue must be squarely faced. Constitutional scholars have for too long hidden behind a vague formula of ‘liberal democracy’, pretending that constitutionalism is a synonym for constitutional democracy and assuming this composite to be ‘a good thing’. The crisis we now face requires a choice to be made between untrammelled cosmopolitan constitutionalism and a renewed national constitutional democracy. There are many ways in which global developments leading to the dominance of a new ideology of neoliberal economism are having profound social, political, and cultural effects that challenge the authority of national systems of government. These developments now require a decision to be made. However contestable the concepts may be, the question remains: does democracy or liberalism provide the ultimate grounding of legitimate governmental ordering? Others may decide differently, but I fail to see how civilized existence can be maintained when the individual is treated as an autonomous agent removed from the social matrix within which he or she has been formed but to which remains obligated. I conclude, then, by thanking Jack Balkin and his colleagues for giving me this opportunity to engage with them on the book’s themes. My main purpose in writing it was to try and jolt constitutional scholars from a widely held yet unreflective assumption, especially in comparative studies, that constitutionalism must be a good thing. The essays presented here have forced me not only to reflect more deeply about some of the claims I make but also to recognize that there is already a vibrant community of scholars who had no need of my prompting. [1] See Mary L. Dudziak, Cold War Civil Rights: Race and the Image of American Democracy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2011). [2] ‘A Testament of Hope’ in A Testament of Hope: The Essential Writings and Speeches of Martin Luther King Jr, ed. J.M. Washington (New York: Harper Collins, 1992), 313-30, 314. [3] Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (London: Allen Lane, 1977), 32. [4] See, e.g., Martin Loughlin, ‘Ruling Britannia’, IMAGINE Paper No. 27 (2022). SSRN-id4287368. [5] See, e.g., Pierre Rosanvallon, The Demands of Liberty: Civil Society in France since the Revolution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2007). [6] Gary Jeffrey Jacobsohn, Constitutional Identity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2010), 8. [7] Laurence H. Tribe, The Invisible Constitution (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), 9.
Posted 9:30 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |