Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Exporting American Constitutional Politics
|
Tuesday, July 04, 2023
Exporting American Constitutional Politics
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Martin Loughlin, Against Constitutionalism (Harvard University Press, 2022). Joseph Fishkin Loughlin’s Against
Constitutionalism is a thoughtful, provocative book. Loughlin has obviously read and thought
deeply about a great deal of constitutional theory, especially European
constitutional theory, from the eighteenth century to the twenty-first. Readers like me who are students of American
constitutional law will find the discussions of American constitutional thought
relatively brief and familiar, but the discussions of European constitutional
thought rich and often surprising, while still terse and well-paced. I learned a great deal from this book. However, I must say that the framing
of the book struck me as odd. The book’s
title proclaims that it is an attack on “constitutionalism.” That is a bold target! However, Loughlin immediately proceeds to
define the word “constitutionalism” in a very particular way, rendering it
almost a term of art. What Loughlin is actually
against is a specific constellation of ideas, which he closely identifies with a
brand of constitutional practice and theory he views as distinctive to the
United States, both at the founding and across time. (He attributes the recent global spread of that
particular constellation of ideas—to Germany, to India, even to certain
transnational institutions—largely to the unfortunate influence of United
States.) What Loughlin is actually against
is forms of constitutionalism that treat constitutions as “objects of worship”;
that imagine that constitutions express deep authentic truths about the
“collective political identity” of a governing regime or even its people; that
fetishize the text of a written constitutional document; that prioritize
individual liberty too much; and (perhaps most importantly) allocate the exclusive
(or near-exclusive?) responsibility for enforcing the constitution to an
unelected judiciary, which operates as a constraint on democratically elected
representatives. That last institutional
point about the judiciary is so central to the argument that at times Loughlin
uses the word “constitutionalism” interchangeably with “constitutional judicial
review.” Loughlin fully acknowledges that
constitutions play a variety of essential roles in democratic government; he is
not against any of that. But Loughlin
insists on reserving the key word in the book’s title—“constitutionalism”—for the
specific constellation of ideas I’ve just outlined. This leads to the slightly awkward
proclamation that the book is an argument for “constitutional government
against constitutionalism” (preface, emphasis added). Any American critic of our present
juristocracy (and I count myself as one) will find plenty to agree with in
Loughlin’s overall critique. A judiciary
with too much unchecked power is a problem for democratic accountability and
even democratic citizenship, in both theory and practice. Fetishizing obscure bits of text with methods
inaccessible to ordinary citizens makes the problem much worse, and lends what
is already a juristocracy a quasi-religious sort of authority whose fundamentally
antidemocratic nature Sandy Levinson has fruitfully explored. To my mind, the
question of how extensively to prioritize the protection of individual liberty
is considerably more difficult, and a question that frankly depends on exactly which
individual liberties the courts are prioritizing. But it is definitely true, as Loughlin’s
critique suggests, that the intersection of an economic-libertarian
constitutional orientation with juristocracy and a fetishizing of written text
is a toxic combination. If that’s
“constitutionalism,” then let us all be against “constitutionalism.” The biggest problem with Loughlin’s
book is that it identifies this specific form of constitutionalism far too
tightly with American constitutional practice.
American constitutionalism—and here I use that word in the more
ordinary, non-term-of-art sense—is a rich pageant of contrasting approaches and
schools of thought, not only in theory but, more importantly for my point here,
in our actual constitutional practice, both inside and outside the courts. The oddity of reading Loughlin’s account is that
he sounds very much like a deeply committed, possibly slightly
over-enthusiastic U.S. libertarian, who wants to proclaim that the constitution
has always been a charter for judges enforce limited government for the purpose
of protecting individual liberty. To
Loughlin, that is what the U.S. Constitution has always been, from the founding
to the present: a sword for judiciaries to wield against the redistributive
enactments of democratic government, in the name of upholding libertarian ideas
of contract and property. The American constitutionalism
Loughlin describes is very much the constitutionalism of the present U.S.
Supreme Court majority. It would also be
extremely familiar to a reader from the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries
(the Lochner era). That was a time, like
our own, in which a reactionary faction in American politics controlled the
courts and fought to limit the innovations in progressive government favored by
its political opponents. Loughlin
locates some arguments for this particular type of “constitutionalism” in the
Federalist Papers, which he regards as a kind of ur-text of (the bad kind of)
constitutionalism, even though various of the key elements—big ones, such as
judicial review—are relatively inchoate in the Federalist Papers. Reading this book, one would be
very surprised to learn of the long tradition in American politics of
progressive and reformist politicians of various stripes using constitutional
argument—sometimes textual argument, often structural argument, but really
all the modalities of constitutional argument—to attack the libertarian,
juristocratic, anti-democratic strains of constitutionalism that are Loughlin’s
real target in the book, separately and in combination. What sense can Loughlin’s account
of American constitutionalism make, for instance, of Reconstruction? Loughlin recognizes the centrality of
Reconstruction to American constitutionalism (see his discussion of Bruce
Ackerman’s work (p. 146–47)). Loughlin agrees
with Ackerman that Reconstruction shows that constitutional politics is a
component of a governing regime, not some independent force emanating from a
written document. But Loughlin never
squarely discusses the fact that the Reconstruction Republicans built their
entire project of constitutionalism around legislative power and
legislative duty, not courts. It was not
the courts that would enforce the Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth
Amendments, but the Congress. These amendments would be held in place not by
being written into a document for lawyers to interpret, but through the
political power of the Republican Party.
And that was not a new idea in American constitutional politics during
Reconstruction. As Willy Forbath and I
recount in The Anti-Oligarchy
Constitution, Whig constitutionalism earlier in the nineteenth century was
similarly focused on the Constitution as a source of legislative duty,
not court-enforced constraint. Many Republicans in Congress during
Reconstruction thought that they had a constitutional duty not only to enact
statutes guaranteeing equal rights to Black Americans, but to radically
reconstitute the entire political economy of the South, displacing the economic
and political power of the white planter oligarchy and distributing land and
education to the freedmen so as to create the economic and political conditions
for a multiracial democracy. From the
late nineteenth through the early twentieth centuries, arguments about
constitutional duty impelled debates in our politics about antitrust and
concentrated economic and political power; the rights of labor; monetary
policy; even the structure of government itself. Proponents of the constitution as a bulwark
of libertarian rights against government were certainly among those
participating in those debates. But
constitutional arguments were equally central to the claims of their opponents,
including eventually the New Dealers, who argued for distinctly anti-libertarian
constitutional visions of our political economy and the power and duties of
government. Thus, in my view, the periodicity
of the “constitutionalism” Loughlin attributes to the United States seems off,
and the story more complex and interesting.
The court-enforced Constitution fully displaces other
institutional forms of constitutional argument such as legislative
constitutional duty only in the mid-twentieth century, as the Court becomes
identified with Brown v. Board and civil rights, and as the discipline
of economics displaces political economy.
Even after this twentieth-century change, Americans have continued to
engage in robust democratic forms of constitutional politics outside the courts—the
Nixon backlash against school busing being a seminal example; in the decades
that followed, conservative constitutional politics against the Warren Court
helped build the modern Republican Party.
Today, for the first time in almost a century, progressive constitutional
politics in opposition to the conservative Supreme Court is beginning to become
an important area of democratic constitutional activity and political
organizing. But this book is not really about
the United States. Even though American
constitutionalism is far richer than the “constitutionalism” Loughlin is
against, it still seems important to understand what features ended up in the
model Americans have exported elsewhere.
I take Loughlin’s point that a particular configuration of
constitutional ideas—even if not that representative of the full richness of
American constitutional politics, law, theory or practice—has become a major part
of the constitutional regime in quite a few very different countries and even
transnational entities such as the EU. My hunch—and it is no more than
that—is that to the extent that bodies like the EU have adopted forms of
constitutionalism that are relatively impenetrable to democratic activism, and
instead driven by expert and elite consensus, the explanation may lie outside
the United States. After all, the core
elements of expert/elite governance that American progressives brought to their
project of state-building over a century ago were largely imported from
Germany. The EU is an elite creation
with deep, obvious, and well-known democratic deficits. Is it really a shock that the EU may have
adopted forms of constitutionalism that don’t provide a lot of ongoing
opportunities for the people to reshape their constitutional trajectory? Do we need the United States to explain this? And I wonder as well how the future
trajectory of American constitutional politics may affect the export
market. The strain in American
constitutional culture that is the closest to the constitutionalism Loughlin decries—the
American constitutional lawyer’s “fetishism” for the Constitution’s text and
insistence that “its meaning can be disclosed through skillful legal analysis”
rather than through (say) politics (141)—is fast being overtaken by
events. The U.S. Supreme Court’s long
run of popularity that began in the Warren Court era appears to be reaching its
end. That was the political scaffolding
underneath a particular late-twentieth-century flavor of American
constitutionalism; in its absence, the political demystification of the Supreme
Court’s work is advancing rapidly. The
American public increasingly recognizes the court as the political branch that
it has always been, rather than viewing it as more of an apolitical
Guardian. Indeed, many Americans have
always seen it that way and for good reason. So, am I ready for our country to
export this particular further turn in American constitutional politics to the
rest of the world? To Israel? To Hungary?
This blog post is probably not the best place to explore the cognitive
dissonance of American progressives who advocate some of the same court-curbing
measures in the United States we decry in Israel. But I guess the most interesting point, to
me, is that the constitutionalism Loughlin is against in Against
Constitutionalism represents something like one side of a dialectic. In a democracy, there is only so far that
courts can go in enforcing their own interpretations of a constitution that are
far apart from the views of their citizens before the courts inadvertently
create an opening for politicians and whole political parties to position
themselves to capitalize on that disjuncture.
Those politicians and parties then engage in forms of constitutional
politics that make the courts a character in the drama of constitutional politics,
and by character I mean villain. As
constitutionalism (in Loughlin’s sense) has spread across the world, it may
also have planted the seeds of the political forces that ultimately keep it in
check. Joseph Fishkin is a professor of law at UCLA. He can be reached at fishkin@law.ucla.edu.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |