Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Response to the symposium on Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed
|
Tuesday, November 29, 2022
Response to the symposium on Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed
Andrew Koppelman
Thanks to Richard
Epstein, Christina
Mulligan, James
Hackney, Matt
Zwolinski, Ilya
Somin, Jamie
Mayerfeld, Jennifer Burns,
and Jonathan Adler for
their thoughtful responses to my book, Burning
Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed. It’s an honor to be able to engage with such
an impressive group. The book is a critical history of libertarian philosophy. It argues that modern libertarianism began as
a corrective to the Depression-era vogue for central economic planning. It
showed how individual liberty and free markets could improve life for everyone,
especially the poorest. I trace its evolution
from Friedrich Hayek’s moderate pro-market ideas to the romantic fabulism of
Murray Rothbard, Robert Nozick, and Ayn Rand, and Charles Koch’s aggressive promotion
of climate change denial. Today it has
become a toxic blend of irresponsible anarchism, cruel disdain for the weak,
and rationalization for environmental catastrophe. The notion of a minimal
state has attracted a new form of parasite: the dishonest businessman who wants
to deceive his customers or poison his neighbors without being bothered by the
police. Unsurprisingly, the libertarians who participated in this
symposium are unpersuaded. He doesn’t respond to the book’s critique of his work. He agrees with my criticism of what he calls
“hardline” libertarianism. He
acknowledges the existence of market failures and the need for central planning
to deal with public goods and other “high transaction cost settings.” He pushes back on the Gene Cranick story, in which a fire
department watched a house burn down because the owner had forgotten to pay his
annual fee. Epstein claims that under
well-established legal principles such disasters are unlikely. I agree with him about that: what is most
interesting about Cranick’s story is not the episode (though the county’s
irrational aversion to a tax-supported fire department is revealing), but the
response it elicited from right and left.
Epstein’s response is libertarian-ish to the extent that he fantasizes
about compensating uninvited private fire departments through “arbitration or
judicial determination.” That may be an
option under “standard rules of restitution,” but it is revealing that the
option is never exercised, because America doesn’t do fire protection that way. The Cranick story shows what can happen if
public policy shifts in a more libertarian direction. Privatized fire protection can create its own perverse effects. (Jennifer Burns is right that its defenders
rely on “a flawed account of incentives.”)
Before public provision was adopted, fire protection was effectively paid
for by bounties from insurers. Rival
private fire departments would sometimes fight with one another for the
privilege of extinguishing fires. Competition
is not invariably benign. Houses were
marked indicating which insurance company would pay the first company to get
water onto the fire. Houses without insurance
marks were sometimes deemed “false alarms” and allowed to burn. Fred McChesney reports:
“the most celebrated incident of violence occurred during a fire at a
Cincinnati planing mill in 1850. As the story goes, a dozen companies arrived
at the fire and a riot ensued for the right to extinguish it. As the firemen
brawled, the fire completely demolished the mill.” The deeper issue is whether it is wrong to disrespect the
distribution of wealth that markets generate.
Insurance against fire is rarely unaffordable. But the debate about the Cranick fire took
place in 2010 amid the Obamacare battle, and the debaters on both sides
understood that the real question they were arguing about was whether the huge
and growing number of people who couldn’t afford health insurance ought to be
left to their fate. That’s the moral
equivalent of standing back and watching a house burn. The law of restitution was not going to be
any help with that issue. (Epstein’s own
solution, as I explain (69), makes unsustainable demands on private charity.) That particular fight, which I describe in my
earlier book The
Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform, led me
to the deeper dive into libertarian philosophy that produced this book. Christina Mulligan is even more sympathetic to
privatization than Epstein, telling a horror story in which public provision
leaves open the possibility of viciously harsh punishment of nonparticipants. Here, too, it is relevant that this doesn’t
actually happen. In her account, as in
Epstein’s, the obvious solution of paying for a public good out of public tax
revenues (typically enforced by liens on property for nonpayment of taxes)
disappears from view. The larger problem is the way in which libertarians imagine
the conditions for liberty. Mulligan
protests that the libertarians she has known “deeply recognized human
interdependence and believed private ordering was a superior way of caring for
each other than government apparati.” I
also know people like that, including some of the participants here. I like and admire them, but I don’t always
trust their judgment. Libertarians are
typically drawn to the hypothesis that a nongovernmental solution is always
better. It is an hypothesis worth
testing, and I say that libertarians have made and continue to make important
contributions by insisting upon it (pp. 52-53). Sometimes it is correct. Sometimes it is a disastrous mistake. Ilya Somin, my old friend and sometime
collaborator, falls into that trap.
He acknowledges my dissection of the classic libertarian writers, Hayek,
Rothbard, Nozick, and Rand, but laments my “neglect of more recent and more
sophisticated thinkers.” Mulligan
similarly notes “the vast terrain covered in so little space.” At 237 pages, the book is necessarily
compressed. I wrote it because there
existed no short introduction to libertarianism for the general reader that was
not written by enthusiasts. The “missed
opportunity” Somin describes would have been a different book than I was attempting. Readers who want more luxuriant detail should
read Brian Doherty’s wonderfully entertaining Radicals
for Capitalism: A Freewheeling History of the Modern American Libertarian
Movement, but it was published in 2007, too old to do what Somin
asks. All I can say is that the writers
I cover are the trunk of the tree, one that continues to expand, and a
historical overview appropriately focuses on the central lines. I will say that contemporary libertarians, including
Somin, make the same mistakes as their predecessors whom I do describe, preeminently
exaggerated trust in unregulated markets and exaggerated distrust of
government. Somin is particularly
troubled by my “neglect of modern libertarian critiques of democratic
government, particularly those focused on voter ignorance and bias.” Some modern libertarians, prominently
including Somin himself, have argued that this fact is a reason to reject
legislation in favor of “private-sector solutions to public goods problems and
externalities.” I acknowledge the
possibility of such solutions (see 69, citing Ostrom, on whom Somin relies),
but I say that “whether this is so in any particular case cannot be resolved
without attention to the local evidence.”
Neither can the question of whether any particular branch of the
administrative state is corrupt or incompetent.
A lot of officials are doing their jobs very capably. My broad response to the more recent body of
scholarship that Somin cites is this: “Libertarians
who are confident that the state can do nothing right have produced first-rate
scholarship about abuses of regulatory power. That doesn’t mean they ought to
be in charge of government.” (53) The real gap between me and Somin is what I say next: “More
fundamentally, the networks of mutual trust that facilitate such cooperation
don’t develop in nations where government is distrusted. Across prosperous
democratic nations, and over time, trust in government and interpersonal trust
are tightly correlated.” Somin is
committed to a picture in which government cannot be trusted to do anything
right: given the effect on policy of voter ignorance and bias, “the quality of
those policies is likely to be greatly reduced.” For reasons I elaborate in the book, that
picture is not only destructive to cooperation in markets; it is at some remove
from reality. Despite voter ignorance
and bias, Congress did manage to enact protections against death
in the workplace and foul
air, protections that the market was never going to supply, and which the
Supreme Court has lately been gutting in the name of liberty. Jonathan Adler is a scholar who is drawn to libertarian
solutions to market failures, but he is less categorical than Somin in his embrace
of such solutions. For that reason, he and
I are not so far apart as he thinks. He is
troubled by my claim that property rights are “conventions” that can be
“designed with their likely distributional consequences in mind.” (98) He
responds that “property rights cannot be simply ‘designed’ from the ground up
to generate particular distributional consequences,” and that “the contours of
private property are not infinitely malleable if it is to facilitate a Hayekian
market order and safeguard liberty.” I
don’t disagree. The passage that
troubles him is a response to the claim of Murray Rothbard and Robert Nozick
that redistributive taxation violates property rights. I argue that “institutions that guarantee a
fair share for the least well-off, such as taxation to support free public schools,
are properly part of—not an exception to—the system of property rights.” (98) Those institutions are human creations, but
they need stability if people are going to plan their lives, economic and
noneconomic. Adler also thinks that I
should have “far more humility about regulatory interventions” than the book
offers. But I repeatedly acknowledge
that regulation can sometimes be corrupt, foolish, and counterproductive. What I deny – and again, he doesn’t disagree –
is that this is always or even usually true.
My “broad generalizations” that trouble him are broad condemnations of libertarian
antistatism. Mulligan claims that libertarianism is politically dead
and the book comes too late. As I’ve
noted elsewhere,
however, although much of the Republican Party’s agenda is pretty far from
libertarian, the last time it held the Presidency and Congress its principal
accomplishments were enormous tax cuts for the rich and the evisceration of
regulatory agencies. Its other thwarted
aspiration was even more tax cuts, paid for by taking health care away from
more than 20 million people. Matt Zwolinski acknowledges my criticisms of libertarianism,
which happen to be heavily indebted to his own work. (In some parts of my argument I am gratefully
popularizing objections devised by him.)
He worries that I may in the end be too harsh on radical libertarianism,
which offers “a lens through which
to see the world that helps us get a certain class of important questions right –
questions that we might have mis-answered, or not even noticed at all, had we
been looking through a different lens.”
I heartily agree. It generates
hypotheses that demand to be investigated.
Libertarianism has an admirable side, which he and John Tomasi describe
at length in their admirable forthcoming book. James Hackney notes affinities between my conception of liberty
and that of C.B. Macpherson, who wrote an important critique of negative
libertarianism in 1971. Macpherson
stands in a long line of liberal theorists who focus on what the members of
society are actually able to do and be, rather than their formal entitlements –
as Hackney puts it, “the freedom to be fully human and for every
individual to realize their developmental power.”
I cheerfully place myself in that tradition. Jennifer Burns is right about the
importance of Milton Friedman, whom I discuss briefly at 64-66. He is enormously influential, but in the
apostolic line of succession he is a consequentialist libertarian following
Hayek. I don’t think my picture of Hayek
is “fairly static.” I admire The
Road to Serfdom, but I note that he “eventually laid aside his caution of
centralized schemes and became a daffy armchair constitutional designer.”
(61) But Burning Down the House
is primarily a book of critical political philosophy rather than history, and
so nuances of influence are necessarily neglected. Jamie Mayerfeld worries that I “may sometimes exaggerate the
distance between Hayek and hardline libertarianism.” He is right that the distance shortens in
Hayek’s later writings. As I say (and as
Chandran Kukathas has shown in his magisterial book Hayek and Modern
Liberalism), Hayek is “a bit of a mess as a political philosopher.” (71) Cleaning up the mess will lead us to a liberal
political philosophy that is more sophisticated than any of the
libertarians can offer, one that owes a lot (with some
qualifications) to John Rawls and Martha Nussbaum. But that is another story.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |