Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Assessing Libertarianism Requires Engagement with Modern Libertarian Political Thought
|
Monday, November 14, 2022
Assessing Libertarianism Requires Engagement with Modern Libertarian Political Thought
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization Symposium on Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022).
Ilya Somin Andrew Koppelman’s Burning
Down the House makes some worthwhile points, and I agree with more of it
than I would have expected. But it is also something of a missed opportunity.
Koppelman attempts a critical analysis of libertarian political thought and its
impact on public policy. But he overlooks major aspects of both. Let’s start with a
few points of agreement. Early in the book, Koppelman recognizes that free
markets have made enormous contributions to human freedom and welfare (he calls
it “the Great Enrichment”). He also notes the validity of F.A. Hayek’s classic
critique of economic central planning, on the ground that governments lack the
knowledge needed to plan economic production competently. Perhaps most
strikingly, he points out that many on the left fail to recognize the
contradiction between their support for diversity and their sympathy for socialism;
the latter is likely to stifle the former. As Koppelman puts it, “[m]any on the
left repudiate capitalism because they don’t grasp the anti-socialist logic of
their present views.” If I have a quarrel
with this part of the book, it is that it overstates the extent to which much
of the rest of the left has internalized these points. Koppelman insists that
mainstream modern left-liberals – including even self-described “democratic socialist”
Bernie Sanders have mostly accepted Hayek’s key insights, and mostly reject
central planning. In reality, much of the left still advocates centralized
control of large parts of the economy – most notably health care and education
– and Sanders’ supposedly new version of socialism includes policies that
collectively would amount to a government takeover of the majority of
the US economy. Much of the
political right – especially in its
Trump-era incarnation, with its love of “industrial policy” – is
guilty of similar sins. Koppelman is overly optimistic when he writes that appreciation for the (limited) virtues he sees
in market processes has “prevailed across the political spectrum.” Koppelman is also
right to point out that some prominent advocates of libertarianism – most
notably Ayn Rand and Murray Rothbard – have made a variety of weak and
sometimes even downright silly arguments. Many of these weaknesses have been
covered before, including by other libertarians. But Koppelman’s listing of
them is particularly helpful and accessible. Finally, Koppelman
is to be commended for his outreach to advocates of an ideology that he is
deeply opposed to. Several participants in this symposium (including myself)
are people chosen despite (or perhaps because!) of the fact that they are
likely to reject key elements of Koppelman’s thesis. Such openness is
commendable, especially at a time when ideological polarization leads many
to stick to their ideological safe spaces. Sadly, Koppelman’s
relatively thorough dissection of Rand and Rothbard is coupled with neglect of
more recent and more sophisticated thinkers. As a result, he overlooks crucial ways in
which libertarians have addressed many of the points he raises. When it comes
to effects on public policy, he overlooks many of the areas where libertarian
ideas have had their biggest impact, while greatly overstating their effect in
a few fields where he finds it particularly objectionable (most notably on
environmental and welfare policy). With the exception
of a brief discussion of Richard Epstein’s work, Burning Down the House includes
strikingly little consideration of the last forty years of scholarship by libertarian
political theorists, legal scholars, economists, and policy analysts. The most
recent libertarian scholarship he subjects to sustained analysis is Robert
Nozick’s Anarchy, State, and Utopia, published in 1974, a great (though
flawed) work that is nonetheless far from the last word on its subject. It is
as if a critique of left-liberalism overlooked nearly everything published by
serious left-wing thinkers since John Rawls’ Theory of Justice (1971).
Indeed, Rawls himself gets more air time in Burning Down the House than
any post- Nozick libertarian. This focus weakens
many parts of the book. Here, I cover just a few examples related to my own
areas of expertise. To my mind, the Koppelman’s single most
significant omission is the neglect of modern libertarian critiques of
democratic government, particularly those focused on voter ignorance and bias. After
all, regulation and redistribution by democratic processes is the principal
left-liberal alternative to libertarianism. Prominent
libertarian scholars such as Bryan Caplan and Jason Brennan have shown that the vast majority of voters
are both ignorant of basic facts about politics and government, and highly biased
in their evaluation of what they do know (I have made a few contributions to
this literature, myself). The problem is
not that the voters are stupid or that information is not available to them,
but that the low chance that any one vote will influence the outcome of an
election actually makes ignorance and bias rational behavior for most voters, most of the time. Particularly since the rise of Donald Trump
and his egregious exploitation of public ignorance on a variety of issues,
left-liberal scholars have also focused more on the dangers of public ignorance, and some have begun to see that the challenge
is harder to overcome than democratic theorists previously believed. If the policies of
democratic governments are heavily influenced by voter ignorance and bias, the
quality of those policies is likely to be greatly reduced. This poses a particularly
serious challenge for Koppelman and others who call for carefully calibrated
policies that deftly balance competing considerations. Throughout his book,
Koppelman recognizes important advantages of markets, but then says governments
can use targeted interventions to correct various injustices and market
failures, without unduly stifling enterprise, burdening liberty, or massively
wasting resources. In a world of widespread political ignorance and bias, this
happy medium becomes highly unlikely. Voter ignorance helps explain why
governments routinely adopt dysfunctional policies that inflict great harm for
little or no benefit, including protectionism, persecution of various minority
groups, migration restrictions that inflict enormous harm on natives, as
well as potential migrants,
and much else.
In addition to pointing out the cognitive limitations of ballot-box voters,
libertarian thinkers have also emphasized that people generally make
better-informed and more objective decisions when they make choices in markets
and civil society. That’s because, unlike individual ballot-box votes, such
decisions usually do have a high chance of making a difference. For that
reason, we generally take them more seriously, and make more effort to curb
biases. If you are like most
people, you probably spent more time seeking out information the last time you
decided which TV set or smartphone to buy, than the last time you decided who
to back in a presidential election. That’s because the TV you choose is likely
to be the one that actually ends up in your house. But when you turn on the TV
and have the misfortune of seeing the president or some other powerful
politician, your odds of determining who that person is and what policies they
pursue are infinitesimally small. Both economic theory and extensive historical
and experimental evidence indicates that people make better decisions when they
make individually decisive choices by “voting with their feet” than when they
vote at the ballot box. I summarize much of that evidence in my recent book Free to Move: Foot Voting, Migration, and Political Freedom. In the course of
defending paternalistic efforts to protect people from their cognitive biases, Koppelman
recognizes that “government decision
makers are subject to their own biases and distortions of judgment.” He responds that “this is not a complaint specifically about
paternalism. It is an argument against any legislation at all.” Precisely so!
Voter ignorance and bias – combined with that exhibited by many government officials (who also often have weak incentives to get
things right) – is a strike against a
wide range of government interventions. Any defense of such policies must
consider the extent to which these problems undercut its value. And it must
also explain why people won’t make better-quality decisions on the subject if
allowed to do so through foot voting, rather than ballot-box voting. Another vital branch
of libertarian scholarship that Koppelman overlooks is the study of
private-sector solutions to public goods problems and externalities. This has
been a major focus of libertarian thought at least since Nobel Prize-winning
economist R.H. Coase’s pathbreaking work in the 1960s. More recently, Elinor
Ostrom won the Nobel in large part for her work on private production of public
goods, and other libertarian
thinkers have extensively studied private planned communities and other
institutions that produce public goods and address externalities that many
previously assumed can only be dealt with by government intervention. Libertarianism’s
supposed neglect of public goods and externalities problems is a major theme of
Koppelman’s book. Yet he does not seriously consider the extensive modern
libertarian literature on these very issues. Finally, despite his
discussion of property rights focused on the classic writings of John Locke and
Robert Nozick, Koppelman also overlooks the vast bulk of modern libertarian
property scholarship. He thus neglects the ways in which libertarian thinkers –
beginning with Bernard Siegan’s classic work in the 1970s – have played a leading role in
documenting the immense harm caused by exclusionary zoning, cutting off
millions of people from job, educational, and housing opportunities. As Siegan
explained, these problems can be greatly alleviated simply by lifting
restrictions on the construction of new housing. This idea has since been taken
up by economists and housing experts across the political spectrum, and helped
give rise to a major zoning reform movement, which has led to important policy
changes in several states, most recently in California. The enormous scale of the harm caused by zoning should give pause to
Koppelman and others who believe government should be given broad discretion in
controlling property and land-use decisions. Koppelman’s
excessively narrow focus also shows up in his discussion of libertarian impacts
on policy, where he stresses the supposed effects of categorical rejection of
redistribution, and climate denialism. He claims that “the Republican Party
became increasingly Rothbardian: reflexively opposed to all taxation and
regulation.” In reality, even in its most libertarian-friendly period under
Reagan, the GOP never came close to rejecting “all taxation and regulation.” At
most, it advocated tighter restrictions on these policies. In its more recent
Trumpian “national conservative” incarnation, the Party has embraced
large-scale protectionism, industrial planning, and massive migration
restrictions. It has also dropped most previous attempts to cut entitlement
programs, with Trump openly proclaiming his opposition to cuts, and indifference to the growth of budget deficits
and government spending. The
idea that even moderate libertarian ideas on regulation and redistribution and
spending have great influence in today’s GOP is questionable, outside of a few
relatively narrow policy areas; extreme Rothbardianism has almost none. F.A.
Hayek, whom Koppelman describes as the leading founder of modern
libertarianism, wrote that nationalism “frequently provides the bridge from conservatism
to collectivism.” He could have been describing today’s Republican Party. On climate change,
Koppelman has a point when he notes many libertarians are tempted to embrace
denialism. But this has little to do with the influence of the philanthropist Koch
brothers (to whom he largely attributes this trend), and much more with a
reluctance to admit the existence of any problem that might be used to justify
large-scale government intervention. Advocates of other ideologies also often
tend to deny inconvenient facts (though this in no way excuses the phenomenon
among libertarians). Still, our failure
to more effectively combat global warming has far less to do with libertarian
denialism, than with the enormous costs of cutting fossil fuel consumption in the
absence of a comparably cheap and reliable alternative. European nations have
been even less successful in cutting emissions than
the US, despite the fact
that libertarian political influence in most of these countries is minimal.
Environmentalists’ stifling of nuclear power – the most readily available cheap
alternative to fossil fuels – has also exacerbated the problem. On environmental
policy, as on other issues, Koppelman would have done well to engage with
relevant modern libertarian scholarship, such as Jonathan Adler’s work on
market-based approaches to climate change, and economist Terry Anderson’s prominent
book Free Market Environmentalism. The exaggerated
focus on redistribution and climate change leads Koppelman to overlook multiple
policy areas where libertarian ideas have had much greater impact. Examples
include Milton Friedman’s key role in the abolition of the draft, his remarkably successful advocacy of
anti-inflationary monetary policy (adopted by numerous central banks), the rise
of school choice in the US and Europe (another idea effectively popularized by
Friedman), and the extensive role of libertarians in promoting stronger constitutional
protection for property rights (where Richard Epstein and other libertarian
thinkers have had a big impact). I have already mentioned the issue of
exclusionary zoning. And this list is far from exhaustive. None of the modern
libertarian ideas discussed above is unassailable, and most have generated significant
counter-arguments. For example, libertarian criticisms of voter ignorance have
generated responses both from those who claim the problem isn’t really that bad
(a view less common on the left since the rise of Trump!), and those who agree
that it is severe, but propose non-libertarian solutions. There is also an
ongoing debate over whether the libertarianism’s impact on the policy issues I
listed has been a beneficial one. But sustained
critical engagement with modern libertarianism cannot neglect these issues. It
has to address the best of modern libertarian thought, and systematically
consider those issues where libertarian ideas have had their greatest impact. Ilya Somin is a law
professor at George Mason University and author of Free
to Move: Foot Voting, Migration and Political Freedom, and
Democracy
and Political Ignorance: Why Smaller Government is Smarter. You can reach him by e-mail at isomin@gmu.edu.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |