E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Two books sit on my desk. Each takes the same narrative trope:
recovery. There exists a tradition that has been lost. Suppose we could just
recover our footing, our memory, our allegiance to a better, more authentic
past. In that case, we could reclaim or, more accurately, achieve a
constitutional arrangement worthy of our national experiment. We could, as a
people, embrace the co-constitutive nature of our governing code. The path back
to the garden is as fraught with danger as the profound as the snake that led
to our expulsion, but the garden exists not just in memory but in landmarks;
faint though some of them are, it is our duty to map them.
I expected the books to argue, but the conversation was more polite
than imagined. Despite their proximity, they did not spontaneously combust. At
the level of value, if not at the level of politics, each had something to say
to the other. "I will argue that the best of our traditions is that courts
should defer to public determination… so long as the public authority acts
rationally and with a view to legitimate public purposes: the ends of peace,
justice, and abundance."[1] I suspect that
Professors Fishkin and Forbath would agree with that construction and the claim
that a commitment to peace, justice, and abundance is precisely the aim of the
constitutional politics they advance.
Fishkin and Forbath describe constitutional politics as one of
democratic opportunity understood through the lens of political economy. This
requires three fundamental commitments, first, opposition to mutually
reinforcing concentrations of wealth and political power. Second is a belief
that democratic politics are possible only if it is premised on a commitment to
shared abundance. They would phrase it more modestly as an "objective
level of material comfort and security." Finally, they commit to equality
measured by access to the "full range of opportunities the nation
offers."[2] The equality of
inclusion, they maintain is critical to the constitutional politics they outline.
Because this is a project of recovery, none of these commitments that make up a
"democracy of opportunity" are new. They are, instead, statements
about the historical moments that illuminated a popular (and elite)
understanding of what the constitution both permitted and required.
The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution reconstructs the history of
constitutional politics and demonstrates the pernicious impact of yielding a
monopoly on constitutional meaning to any institution. The defeat of the
progressive constitutional understanding is reflected in the surrender of
constitutional meaning to the courts. Judicializing politics distorted what was
at stake and what was possible. As crucial as the limitation they propose on courts
second-guessing the legislative branches, the more profound question arises in interrogating
the relationship between legislative power and legislative duty. The sources of
the government's legislative power figure heavily in their analysis. They argue
against the crabbed reading that has dominated arguments in the constitutional
politics of the modern era. They read the new birth of freedom that framed the
immediate post-civil war period as a re-inscription of the roots of democratic
constitutionalism in which they ground their argument.[3] The power/duty
line is important for them. It remains a troubling question perhaps raised most
recently in the case of McGirt v. Oklahoma.[4]
This question has had its most aggressive expression in some of the
litigation around climate change and resource use.[5] In many ways,
those cases really ask: What is government for? That is profoundly a question
of constitutional politics. It is precisely the kind of question that Fishkin
and Forbath raise repeatedly and demonstrate that it is for the people to say.
Significantly, they demonstrate that it was the question that animated
constitutional politics from the beginning. It now has its expression across
substantive domains. Lynn Stout resurrected the argument in the domain of
corporate law in The Shareholder Value Myth:
How Putting Shareholders First Harms Investors, Corporations, and the Public[6] Omarova and
Hockett have done this in the area of finance.[7] Fishkin and
Forbath catalog the other areas.
These demonstrations triggered the reaction that has delivered us to a
period where discussion of the common good is reduced to an aggregate of
utility functions at best. What Fishkin and Forbath do most forcefully is to
show how the enshrinement of individual rights is used to reduce the capacity
of the government to act in defense of the basic needs of the individual. They
are not enemies of rights talk, but they are clear about how it obscures, and
in some cases declares out of bounds, actions by the government that are
critical to individual flourishing. The irony hangs like a dull fog that the
historical detail they assemble helps us see through.
The importance of concerted mobilization to promote durable legal
change is an important element of their analysis as is their incisive treatment
of class and race. But the social landscape in which some of the most important
advances were made is radically different today. The new terrain means that the
structure and expression of constitutional politics will be different as well.
I want to hear more about that.
Gerald Torres is Professor of
Environmental Justice, Yale School of the Environment and Professor of Law,
Yale Law School. You can reach him by e-mail at gerald.torres@yale.edu.
[1] Adrian Vermeule, Common Good Constitutionalism 15
(2022).
[2] Lani Guinier discussed this idea in The Tyranny of
the Meritocracy (2016).
[3] Charles Lund Black, A New Birth of Freedom: Human
Rights Named and Unnamed. (1997).
[4]McGirt v. Oklahoma, 591 U.S. ___ (2020), which is commonly thought of
as a significant win for Native people and a ringing endorsement of the
lawfulness of treaty obligations. What is sometimes lost in the celebration was
the reinforcement by Justice Gorsuch of the power of Congress to act under its
plenary authority. See also, Missouri v. Holland, 252 U.S. 416 (1920).
[5] “Exercising my ‘reasoned
judgment,’ I have no doubt that the right to a climate system capable of
sustaining human life is fundamental to a free and ordered society.” Judge
Aiken, Juliana v. U.S.; Gerald Torres, The
Public Trust: The Law’s DNA, 4 Wake Forest J. of Law & Policy 281
(2014) (with Nate Bellinger).
[7] Robert Hockett & Saule
Omarova, Private Wealth and Public Goods: A Case for a National Investment
Authority, 43 Journal of Corporation Law 437 (2018)