Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Theorizing Context
|
Sunday, January 15, 2023
Theorizing Context
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization 20th Anniversary Symposium Lawrence Lessig We
still need a way to theorize about context: That’s my plea. Here’s an example
to suggest what I mean. Consider
two opinions by Justice Scalia. The first, familiar to all; the second, the
most revealing of all. In
the first, United States v. VMI (1996), Scalia dissented from the
Court’s rendering more vigorous its protection against sex discrimination. The
framers of the 14th Amendment, Scalia tells us, took for granted that the
amendment would not change the sex-based inequality of its time. Their “fixed
notions,” as the Court criticizes them and Scalia describes them, saw women in
a particular place within society, and believed the law could regulate to keep
women in that place. Scalia doesn’t deny that those “fixed notions” have
changed. He simply denies that that change is relevant to how the case should
be resolved. The Constitution, he instructs, is to prevent us from
“backsliding.” It is not the role of the Court to use its more modern,
enlightened views, to push us forward. But
it is this passage in that opinion that is most revealing: Much of the Court’s opinion is
devoted to deprecating the closed-mindedness of our forebears with regard to
women’s education, and even with regard to the treatment of women in areas that
have nothing to do with education. Closed-minded they were — as every age is,
including our own, with regard to matters it cannot guess, because it simply
does not consider them debatable. The virtue of a democratic system with a
First Amendment is that it readily enables the people, over time, to be
persuaded that what they took for granted is not so, and to change their laws
accordingly. That system is destroyed if the smug assurances of each age are
removed from the democratic process and written into the Constitution. So to
counterbalance the Court’s criticism of our ancestors, let me say a word in
their praise: They left us free to change. We’re
not bound, on this account, to embrace 19th-century views about women. But on
this account, until amended, the Constitution is. We can, of course, pass laws
that are sex neutral; but the Constitution, in Scalia’s view, can’t force sex
neutrality into the law, because the framers of the 14th Amendment viewed sex
inequality as not “debatable.” Sex inequality was part of the furniture of
their moral universe. In Scalia’s view, that furniture is nailed to the floor.
The only thing that can rearrange that furniture is an amendment to the
Constitution. Until amended, the job of the Court is simply to read the text in
light of the undebatables at the time the text was written. Both the text and
those undebatables continue to bind until explicitly changed. Now
contrast this opinion with a less famous, but in my view, more interesting case
(jurisprudentially, not substantively): Sosa v. Alvarez-Machain (2004).
The issue in Sosa was the application of the Alien Tort Statute of 1789.
That statute was drafted in a context filled with undebatables. Among those
undebatables was a conception of the common law. The question the Court had to
answer in Sosa was whether the common law it would apply was the common
law of our framers, or the common law as it was understood by us today.
Scalia’s answer is almost impatient in its certainty: Because today’s federal common law
is not our Framers’ general common law, the question presented by the
suggestion of discretionary authority to enforce the law of nations is not
whether to extend old- school general-common-law adjudication. Rather, it is
whether to create new federal common law. The Court masks the novelty of its
approach when it suggests that the difference between us [members of the Court]
is that we would “close the door to further independent judicial recognition of
actionable international norms,” whereas the Court would permit the exercise of
judicial power “on the understanding that the door is still ajar subject to
vigilant door keeping.” The general common law was the old door. We do not
close that door today, for the deed was done in Erie. Federal common law is a
new door. The question is not whether that door will be left ajar, but whether
this Court will open it. We
could spin volumes arguing about what the “Framers’ general common law” was,
and how or whether it was different from “today’s federal common law.” The
point to keep clear, however, is simply that Scalia saw them as different. He
saw, that is, that they had a conception of general common law that was
different from ours, or at least his, and that their conception (or so he
assumed) would lead to one answer in Sosa, while ours would lead to
another. But
the question that VMI Scalia should press is why? Why should Sosa
Scalia follow “today’s federal common law” rather than the “Framers’
general common law”? Was there an amendment somewhere that rendered their
undebatables no longer binding? Is there a reason why views of the law can be
updated, sans amendment, but views about equality cannot? I
think the key to understanding the issue these two cases raise is to add a
third idea to the mix. Yes, an idea can be undebatable. And yes, if it can be
undebatable, then it can become debatable. But we should recognize that in addition
to that binary, there is a third possibility: an idea can become undebatable
again, but in an opposite way. Specifically,
with sex equality: it could well have been undebatable in the 19th century and
before that women had their place, and it was society’s job to keep them there.
Then sometime early in the 20th century, triggered both by the Suffragette
Movement and by women’s extraordinary role during World War II, that idea
became debatable. A libertarian outrage welled up within women within society,
asking, “who the hell are you to tell me who I must be?” For decades, there
were plenty who felt entitled to answer that question, firmly. But eventually,
I take it most would agree, the question became unanswerable. Eventually, it
became undebatable that women did not have “their place” in society, and
whatever place they wanted to occupy was not one to be enforced by the state.
The Framers of the 14th Amendment had an undebatable; that undebatable had
become undebatable in the opposite way. Ginsburg crafted VMI taking for
granted this new undebatable. Scalia denied that she was permitted to do
so. Yet
in Sosa, we could map a parallel dynamic: The “Framers’ general common
law” was their undebatable; the jurisprudence at the turn of the 20th century
rendered it debatable; by Erie, it had become undebatable in the
opposite way. Erie then launched generations of thinking, reordering the
furniture of jurisprudence for American lawyers generally — including,
prominently, the realist Scalia, educated at a hotbed of realism, the Harvard
Law School. Scalia couldn’t see the law any differently from how Brandeis had
rendered it; he was impatient with the idea that maybe he should. I
point to this — what I’ll call — inconsistency to suggest something more
general: What Scalia did in Sosa is unavoidable. Not from the
perspective of fidelity to meaning, but rather, from the perspective of
fidelity to role. No functioning institution of government can spit in the wind
of “what everyone knows is true.” Rather, any functioning institution of
government must accept the taken for granteds of the time, and govern, subject
to those taken for granteds. That’s
not to say that every truth is a taken for granted truth. We all have beliefs
that we embrace, even though we know not everyone embraces those beliefs. You
might have a view about abortion different from mine. That might anger me, or
make it less likely we’ll be friends. But there’s nothing abnormal about that
difference. Views about abortion are contested beliefs. And contested beliefs
define what makes us different from people in other political parties, or
people in different cultures. But
as well as contested beliefs, there are uncontested beliefs. The most important
of these live far in the background, never even noticed as we go about our
work. These are the beliefs that define who we are as “normal” or
“well-socialized” sorts. These are the things Holmes described as our “can’t
helps” — the beliefs that we can’t help but hold, because of who we have
evolved to be. You might have a different view about abortion and still be
welcome within our society; but if you have a different view about quid pro quo
sexual harassment or pedophilia, that doesn’t just make you different. It makes
you alien. Deviating from uncontested beliefs makes you deviant; deviating from
contested beliefs makes you different. The
story here is more complex than I’m suggesting. I’ve felled many trees trying
to unpack that complexity — see Fidelity & Constraint (2019). But I
don’t think either I or anyone whose work in this area I’ve seen has yet done a
great job in helping us think about how these views, background but taken for
granted, should matter to constitutional interpretation in general, and
theories of fidelity in particular. And
specifically, how changes in these background views should count for purposes
of fidelity. Because my sense is that most theories of interpretive fidelity
try to ignore this dynamic. Most proceed as if we could have a practice of
fidelity without making these changes explicit. Versions of originalism have
moved further and further from the text in the pursuit of original meaning. The
most recent turn includes canon of interpretation of the text, not explicit in
the text but understood. Yet that is just the beginning of understanding
context adequately. And though I’ve been writing in this field for 30 years
now, still, it feels, we are not far from that beginning. If
we did have an adequate theory of context, I think two surprising conclusions
would follow from it. First, that the sort of change that Sosa Scalia
thought he obviously had to accept is indeed a change of fidelity. It is, in
other words, exactly the sort of change the law should allow and embrace, as an
expression of fidelity. But second, that fidelity is particular to the judicial
role. The reason it is right to accept these new undebatables, and to
incorporate them into the law, is not a point about epistemology (though for
some epistemologies, it would be); it is a fact about institutions. World views
change without anyone voting on it. They change without most even recognizing
that the change has happened. And as they change, they leave many things
uncertain and contested; indeed, they create many new things that are uncertain
and contested. But no theory of interpretive fidelity can ignore how changes in
the undebatables should be reckoned. Were
we to have a better theory of context, the theory I am pleading we need, that
point would be too obvious to remark. As things are, it feels like little more
than an annoyance. The shape of context can be ignored; that is our
undebatable. Yet
I plead as an alien: if we’re to understand our law across time, which is,
across context, it cannot be ignored.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |