Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Does it really take a Theory to beat a Theory?
|
Saturday, January 14, 2023
Does it really take a Theory to beat a Theory?
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization 20th Anniversary Symposium Mark Tushnet For quite a while I’ve been irritated by the aphorism that
“it takes a Theory to beat a Theory” in constitutional law and interpretation.[1]
It strikes me as the sort of false profundity that gets thrown around in
first-year college dormitories. And it also seems to have links to the silly
historical tradition of attempting to treat law as a discipline akin to the
physical sciences. This post could be treated as a promissory note for a longer
law-review style essay were I interested, as I am not, in developing them into
that form (where the arguments would admittedly be more qualified and have some
nuances that the post will omit). Start with the importation of the phrase into legal
scholarship. My sense of the matter is that it came into law from the physical
sciences via law-and-economics, a subdiscipline with its own pretensions (at
least in its early years) to science. According to Larry
Solum, whose account accords with my memory, its first use was by Richard
Epstein.[2] It's not clear to me that even in the physical sciences it
takes a Theory to beat a Theory.[3]
Without trying to borrow trouble by “relying on” authorities in other fields, I
think that one version of the current view is that theory-change occurs in the
physical sciences through a combination of the identification of anomalies that
the Theory in question has trouble dealing with, a crisp alternative narrative,
association with prestigious authorities, and, importantly, longevity.[4] The aphorism has (to me) a strange subtext: “Sure, my Theory
might be flawed, though my colleagues and I are trying to work out the kinks,
but it takes a Theory to beat a Theory. We have one, you don’t, so we win.” I
see a couple of problems with that. (1) Some Theories might not even pass a
threshold of plausibility, which seems to me to be the state of play with
respect to original-subjective-intent originalism and
original-expected-applications originalism. (2) Some Theories might fall of
their own weight, so to speak. As I understand it, that’s the standard
pre-Kuhnian account of the displacement of Ptolemaic stories about the solar
system by Copernican ones. Ptolemists (if that’s the right noun form) were
confronted with observational anomalies and dealt with them by adding epicycles
to their core theory. The epicycles “worked” in dealing with the observations
but the theory just seemed too Rube-Goldberg-esque to be “right.” That’s
especially true if one desideratum of a Theory is that it consist of a
relatively small number of propositions—a characteristic I’ll discuss later.[5] But even if in the physical sciences it does take a Theory
to beat a Theory, it’s not clear to me that it’s true in purely normative
disciplines. Outside of academic novels like David Lodge’s, no one really asks
whether Nozick’s normative theory beats Rawls’s, or whether Bentham’s beats
Kant’s. So, what sort of discipline is (constitutional) law? Here’s
my candidate characterization: Constitutional law is an exercise in practical
governance guided by norms, written and unwritten, whose goal is the betterment
of the material and moral well-being of those for whom it is a constitution.[6]
Constitutional Theory A is better than (“beats”) constitutional Theory B if it
does better at achieving that goal. Constitutions, for present purposes, involve institutional
design, and especially the allocation of authority between legislatures and
courts (or, if you want, the allocation of authority among the political
branches and the courts). And Constitutional Theories of the sort referred to
in the aphorism are theories about interpreting the Constitution.[7] Theories dealing with constitutional interpretation are
necessarily second-order. That is, they deal not with the general question,
“What’s the best way to interpret these words?,” but rather with the more
focused question, “What way of interpreting these words will contribute best to
a system in which courts and the political branches share responsibility for
promoting human betterment?” So, for example, standard examples like “What’s
best way of interpreting a grocery list you’ve been given?,” aren’t quite apt
because (in the first instance) there’s no system into which that
interpretation fits. Or, put in a slightly different way, in the first instance
the standard example doesn’t take into account the possibility that the grocery
list’s author will adjust her behavior in response to your interpretation. And,
transferred to the context of constitutional interpretation we run into
problems associated with entrenchment: Entrenchment makes it difficult (the
degree depending upon the stringency of the amendment rule) to adjust the
overall system to respond to judicial interpretations (that is, to the Theory
the judges adopt). We can modify the standard example to insert a “system” into
it. So, for example, one possible answer to the question about interpreting the
grocery list is, “What interpretation will contribute best to maintaining
harmony within the family on an on-going basis?” And here the second-order
issues arise.[8] Maybe
the best first-order Theory will do better than any other Theory here, but the
simple fact that it is a Theory and indeed the best first-order Theory (without
for the moment any competitors) doesn’t tell us anything about the question we
should be interested in. A worse first-order Theory or, perhaps more
interesting, no Theory at all but only “decision according to law” eclectically
defined might be better than the best first-order Theory. How could we go about determining which of two candidate
Theories is better (how do we know when one Theory beats another—or whether “we don’t need no stinking
Theory,” which I’m going to characterize occasionally as a Theory, is
better than a particular Theory)? Here are three interrelated possibilities.
First: experiment. Use Theory A for a while, then switch to Theory B,
and assess the human condition at the end of each period.[9]
Second: comparison across systems. See how constitutional systems in
which Theory A prevails do compared to systems in which Theory B prevails
(subject to all the usual qualifications about the difficulties of comparisons
across systems, particularly with respect to outcomes as general as “human
well-being”). For a while we might have compared Canada under “living tree”
interpretation to the United States with [pause] something else, but the
increasing interest in originalism in Canada might make direct contemporary
comparisons even more complicated. Finally: historical. Examine how
things went when judges used Theory A, then how they went when they used Theory
B. I pursue the historical approach in the remainder of this
post, but have an important caveat (similar to the kinds of concerns associated
with the comparative approach). I think it highly likely that the marginal
contribution of interpretive Theory to human well-being is ordinarily quite
small.[10]
To me, this suggests, with some important qualifications, that the intelligence
devoted to controversies about Theory might be more productively used in some
other law-related enterprise. Sometimes I think that “Theorists” are like
Reverend Casaubon in Middlemarch seeking “The Key to All Mythologies.”
Perhaps that’s too harsh if we take ideas about comparative advantage into
account: Theorists might be spinning their wheels to no real effect but maybe they’re
better at doing Theory than they would be doing something else law-related like
attempting to come up with statutory language whose enactment into law would
make people better off. So, no real benefit from Theory as done by Theorists
but no real harm either—and maybe harm would result if Theorists attempted to
do something else. Now for a sketch of a historical inquiry, based upon my work
on the Hughes
Court. Not to hide the ball: The Hughes Court’s justices didn’t have
anything we would recognize today as Theory.[11]
We can retrospectively impose Theory on what they did, as my examples will show.
But, it would be a mistake to do that and say, “Aha! There’s a Theory at work
here (particularly if we clean up some things around the edges).” I suggest
that the Hughes Court’s justices were doing ordinary lawyers’ work, not Theory
(or proto-Theory, if you prefer). I offer a couple of examples, written by
Chief Justice Hughes (who was no slouch as a lawyer), out of many that could be
deployed.[12] Wood v. United
States (1936) dealt with the question of juror disqualification
for implied bias in criminal cases because the juror was an employee of one of
the litigants. The Court had held in 1909 that people who were employed by or
received pensions from the United States couldn’t serve as jurors in federal
criminal cases. At the time this wasn’t a serious problem in the District of
Columbia but with the expansion of government employment during and after World
War I (and the extension of the federal pension system), it became one as a
really large proportion of the District’s population was disqualified. Congress
responded in 1935 with a statute specifically allowing jury service by federal
employees and pension recipients. The question in Wood was whether this
statute violated the Sixth Amendment’s guarantee of jury trial or principles of
due process and fundamental fairness: What constituted a “jury” within the
Sixth Amendment’s meaning? Hughes characterized the 1909 decision as relying on
pre-constitutional and early constitutional experience to come up with a
definition of “jury”—and disparaged the accuracy of the decision’s
characterization of that experience, relying upon what he called the
government’s “elaborate research” showing to his satisfaction that British
common law practice allowed Crown employees to serve as criminal jurors and
that early U.S. experience didn’t systematically depart from that practice.
(This, in the face of statements by Coke and Blackstone that such employees
were indeed disqualified—because they didn’t acknowledge that many “menial”
employees were so “remote” from prosecution that it was unrealistic to believe
that they would be biased in the government’s favor. Wood’s lawyers “pressed”
their reliance on Blackstone “too far,” according to Hughes.) The Court was
“unable to accept” the 1909 decision as “determinative” in light of the English
precedents and other precedents. Beyond that was the 1935 statute. Congress had in essence
offered its own definition of what a “jury” was. All the Sixth Amendment
required was that the “essential elements” of jury trial “as recognized … when
the Constitution was adopted” be preserved. A 1930 decision holding that a
defendant could consent to trial by a jury of eleven listed three “essential
elements,” and Hughes observed that the list didn’t include anything about juror
disqualification. He then relied on a “principle of construction” drawn from Seventh
Amendment cases for the rule that the ”essential elements” should be determined
with reference to “the fundamental consideration that ‘New devices may be used
to adapt the ancient institution to present needs and to make of it an
efficient instrument in the administration of justice….’” What was at stake were questions about implied bias, for
which “the Constitution lays down no particular tests and procedure is not
chained to any ancient and artificial formula.” Hughes then explained in some
detail why it was unreasonable to think that a person who was a mere government
employee or received a government pension would be any more biased in favor of
the prosecution (in a case involving an ordinary crime like shoplifting) than
would any other person in the District of Columbia. He concluded by referring
to “the spectacle of the exclusion en masse from that service of a body of
citizens otherwise highly desirable in point of intelligence and character,
solely by reason of their employment by the Government, and the imposition in consequence
of a heavier burden upon other citizens….” I’ve gone through the Wood opinion in some detail for
two reasons. It’s a completely ordinary case, and it might look like it’s an
originalist opinion (or at least has enough originalism in it to be treated as
an example of originalism as “our law”).
The better reading of the opinion, I think, is that it’s “eclectic” (a term
I’ve used before) or “pluralist” (the term seemingly in current favor). A
couple of points: Hughes doesn’t treat the originalist materials as evidence of
something like an original public understanding. This is clearest in his
discussion of Blackstone: he doesn’t say that the framers didn’t rely on Blackstone
but says instead that Blackstone was simply wrong or incomplete. Hughes looks
for the reasons behind the practices he describes and, finding the reasons good
ones on the merits, goes with them. His identification of the essentials of a
jury—how he construed the term “jury,” if you like—was expressly purposive (“efficient
instrument”) and present-oriented (“present needs”). For me, the ordinariness
of all this shows that the “construction zone” jargon is unhelpful—if the term
“jury” has to be construed, what doesn’t (other than the Constitution’s
mathematical terms)?[13]
And, of course, there’s the looming question of practicality that impelled
Congress to enact the 1935 statute, a question more or less directly alluded to
in Hughes’s concluding phrase referring to the “heavier burden”
disqualification would impose. For me, then, Wood shows a very good
lawyer working with the available materials—text, practice, precedents,
“authorities” like Blackstone, practicalities—to come up with what he and his
colleagues regarded as a sensible result—an ordinary and uncontroversial
exercise in “reasoned judgment” rather than Theory (or perhaps an illustration
of the proposition that “reasoned
judgment” is a Theory). Blaisdell,
the Minnesota Mortgage Moratorium case, is my second example. The most obvious
criticism of Blaisdell is that the Court there held constitutionally
permissible exactly the kind of legislation that the Constitution’s drafters
and ratifiers had in mind when they endorsed the Contracts Clause. That’s an
original-expected-applications point, which these days shouldn’t count as an
objection. And Hughes expressly rejected original-expected-applications
interpretation. Another criticism is that Blaisdell recognized some sort
of “emergency power” exception to constitutional limitations. Hughes went out
of his way to reject that proposition: “While emergency does not create power,
emergency may furnish the occasion for the exercise of power”—which has to be
correct. A third criticism is that Blaisdell treated the Contracts
Clause as outdated and for that reason alone inapplicable to the problem at
hand. Justices Stone and Cardozo appear to have held that view and they pressed
Hughes to say something along those lines in his opinion. Hughes incorporated
some of their ideas into his opinion but not their observations about how the
Contracts Clause didn’t fit well with a modern economy. What Hughes did was this: deploy the more or less ordinary
techniques of common-law reasoning to show that, properly construed, the
Contracts Clause didn’t stand in the way of what Minnesota did. The Court,
Hughes wrote, had to construe the terms “impair” and “obligation”: “The
inescapable problems of construction have been: What is a contract? What are
the obligations of contracts? What constitutes impairment of these obligations?”
His opinion addressed these questions by examining the Court’s prior cases
dealing with claimed Contracts Clause violations—essentially every one of which
had found a constitutional violation. For Hughes, though, “broad expressions
contained in some of these opinions went beyond the requirements of the
decision, and are not controlling”—dicta don’t count. Good lawyer that he was,
Hughes was able to find in each one of them a negative pregnant: this one was
unconstitutional because it was permanent (implying, Hughes said, that imposing
a time limit would make it constitutionally OK), that one was unconstitutional
because it completely deprived the obligee of any remedy (implying that giving
the obligee something would salvage constitutionality), and so on. The precedents
established that a properly qualified suspension of mortgage payments was
constitutionally permissible.[14] I could go on; in a more complete version I’d discuss Jones
& Laughlin, another Hughes-at-his-lawyerly-best opinion, and the
eclecticism of the paragraphs of Footnote Four. That would be tedious in the
blog format so I move to what I conclude from all this about whether it takes a
Theory to beat a Theory. For generations—really, I think, until the end of the last
century—constitutional law and the nation got along just fine without a Theory.
Judicial practice of constitutional interpretation involved the application of
the ordinary tools of legal reasoning (distinguishing, analogizing, and the
like) to the materials of constitutional law (text, history, practice,
precedent, policy). Sub-“methods” weren’t strongly ranked. Originalist
materials would sometimes play a large role, as in Wood, sometimes
almost no role at all; precedent would sometimes play a large role, as in Blaisdell,
sometimes almost no role at all. Judges would deploy the materials in ways they
believed “made sense” given the nature of the problem at hand—or, perhaps
better, the best judges figured out how to present their arguments to make them
as rhetorically persuasive as they could.[15] One might say, perhaps, that generations of practice show
that the Court had no Theory at all—and so much the worse for Theory. Or,
perhaps one might say that there was a Theory at work, and that Theory was:
interpret the Constitution the way a good lawyer would.[16] Now, though, the definition of Theory matters. I have the
sense that in current discussions of Theory, eclecticism or pluralism just
doesn’t count as a Theory—indeed, I’ve picked up hints that pluralism is
inconsistent with the Rule of Law.[17] What then is a Theory of the sort that could beat another
Theory? Here’s a stab at a “definition”: A Theory is a relatively compact set
of general principles whose application by judges of different backgrounds,
ideological commitments, policy preferences (and more) will converge on
outcomes that are roughly similar though there might be disagreements on
(sometimes important) matters of detail and disagreements around the edges. Why define Theory this way? Perhaps because converging on
outcomes (in the sense I’ve identified) is a desirable feature of adjudication
because (perhaps) it provides some safeguard against idiosyncratic exercises of
judicial whim/preference/judgment.[18]
And, the definition has the advantage of at least getting in the ballpark of an
explanation for the apparent view that Footnote Four/John Hart Ely isn’t a
Theory, nor is a Dworkinian/Rawlsian interpretive approach: both seem to rest
on the kinds of preferences or judgments that Theory aims to guard against. Yet, I think, Theory runs into trouble in seeking that goal.
Perhaps an algorithmic (or, to use an older term “mechanical”) Theory would
provide sufficient safeguards. And, though the official position appears to be
that no Theory is really algorithmic, I do sense a hope on the part of
Theory-proponents to make Theory as algorithmic as possible.[19]
If Theory isn’t fully algorithmic, though, the risk of judicial
whim/preference/judgment sneaks in at the places where something other than an
algorithm does the work.[20] That doesn’t mean that the desired convergence won’t occur.
Convergence can occur if almost all judges share the same whims (though then
they probably aren’t best described as “whims”)/preferences/judgments or
if idiosyncratic judges can’t figure out how to exploit the interstices of the
algorithm (in terms I’ve come to use, if the judges aren’t talented enough). So,
Theory will do what it’s designed to do either if the selection process
produces generally like-minded judges or if produces a pool of generally less
talented judges.[21] Now, though, we can return to “the past.” One reason for
thinking that past judicial practice should count as Theory is that the former
condition—selection produces generally like-minded judges—was satisfied. Not
that they were like-minded with respect to politics or the like, but they were
like-minded with respect to what they would describe as the qualities associated
with being a good lawyer. This isn’t to say, of course, that their
like-mindedness is freed from the possibility of normative criticism, but only
that their practice satisfied what I take to be the requirements of Theory. They might describe what judicial selection looked for was
the capacity to display (good) “reasoned judgment.” As I’ve noted, that’s disparaged today (mostly,
I think, by people who lack that capacity), but it used to be praised as the
“artificial reason of the law,” to use a phrase chosen by Charles
Fried to describe what judges do (even when they’re doing constitutional
law). One concluding thought: Perhaps the selection process used
to create a pool of judicial candidates who had the capacity for good
reasoned judgment but no longer does so. Instead, perhaps that process
generates a pool of generally less-than-highly-talented candidates. If that’s
the case, maybe it really should take a Theory (other than the Theory of
reasoned judgment) to beat a Theory. I suspect, though, that that’s not a
conclusion with which contemporary proponents of Theory would be comfortable. Mark Tushnet is William Nelson Cromwell Professor of Law
emeritus at Harvard Law School. You can reach him by e-mail at mtushnet@law.harvard.edu. [1]
The most recent trigger for my irritation was Ruth
Marcus’s long essay on originalism in the Washington Post, and in
general these days the relevant Theory is some form of original-public-meaning
originalism. [2]
Solum also quotes George Stigler and Thomas Ulen, which supports the route via
law-and-economics. [3]
I’ll explain later both what I think the aphorism’s purveyors mean by Theory
and why I capitalize the term. [4] If
that’s correct, I’d wonder what would count as the kind of anomaly that would
be built into the account of Theory-change in law—perhaps an obviously
“correct” judicial decision that cannot be fit within the Theory’s account
[subject to a point to come about pre-Kuhnian accounts of Theory-choice in the
physical sciences]. [5] It
seems to me that at the moment the “problem” of correct or non-overrulable
non-originalist precedents is threatening to impose similar epicycles on
original-public-meaning originalism, as do the metaphors of the “construction
zone” and “liquidation,” but even if my sense of that is mistaken my overall
argument wouldn’t be materially weakened. [6]
I’ve thrown in “moral betterment” there to take account of what seem to me the
valuable aspects of what’s now going by the name of “common-good
constitutionalism” but what used to be called “constitutionalism” [unmodified]. [7]
Incidentally, it doesn’t have to be the case that the best Theory of judicial
constitutional interpretation is the best Theory of legislative/executive
constitutional interpretation, because of institutional differences between
courts and the political branches, including the degree to which legal
knowledge is available and regularly relied upon within the branches and
differences between the reasonably direct political responsibility of actors in
the political branches and judges’ indirect political responsibility. What
follows focuses exclusively on judicial constitutional interpretation. [8]
These are explored in some detail in Adrian Vermeule’s System of the
Constitution. [9]
Maybe that’s what’s going on today—an experiment in the social value of [some
form of] originalism. [10]
This is a line of argument I associate with Fred
Schauer. [11]
Which, as I’ll suggest, might mean that we ought to rethink what counts as a
Theory [that will beat another Theory] [12] In
some sense my Hughes Court book consists entirely of examples that support the
argument I’m sketching here. [13]
And yes indeed, the term “domestic Violence” is subject to construction—it’s
just that “intrafamilial violence” isn’t an available construction. [14]
Most commentators overlook the fact that a few months later the Court held
unconstitutional an Arkansas moratorium statute because it lacked the
conditions the Court found significant in Blaisdell. [15]
That’s what my analysis of Hughes’s opinion in Jones & Laughlin
would try to show. [16]
I’m quite confident that that’s the answer Hughes, Cardozo, and Holmes would
have given were they asked, “What’s your theory of constitutional
interpretation?,” if they could have overcome their bafflement at the very form
of the question. [17]
Which has the interesting implication, I think, that the United States wasn’t a
Rule-of-Law system from its founding until quite recently [or even now] unless
one accepts the banal-as-stated “originalism is our law” view of past practice. [18] I
think here of the mistaken but common-in-the-literature characterization of
decisions by Jerome Frank and William O. Douglas. [19]
The fad over corpus linguistics seems to me to have that flavor—and has links
to the previously mentioned hope that law could become more like the physical
sciences. I’m sure someone is already working on or has published an article,
“The Contributions of AI to Constitutional Theory,” and I’ll bet we’ll see
ChatGPT versions of Supreme Court opinions. [20]
As I understand things, that’s one of the reasons that corpus linguistics
doesn’t do what its strongest proponents hope it will. Again as I understand
it, the formulation of the queries to the data bases is replete with judgments
[preferences/whims]—as is, of course, the interpretation of inevitably
complicated results of the queries. [21] A
possibility that Judge Posner acerbically raised in his characterization of
Supreme Court justices as perhaps being somewhere in the top ten thousand of
high quality U.S. lawyers.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |