Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts We Are All Constitutional Libertarians Now
|
Wednesday, October 19, 2022
We Are All Constitutional Libertarians Now
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on James E. Fleming, Constructing Basic Liberties: A Defense of Substantive Due Process (University of Chicago Press, 2022). Carlos A. Ball It
is the best and the worst of times to write a comprehensive book defending the
doctrine of substantive due process. It is the latter because the Supreme
Court, weeks before the publication of Jim Fleming’s Constructing Basic
Liberties, made mincemeat of fundamental rights doctrine (and of stare
decisis) in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization (2022). It is
the best of times for the same reason—a thoughtful defense of the doctrine
seems needed more than ever after Dobbs.
In
the book, Professor Fleming carefully and methodically sets forth the structure
and coherence of contemporary substantive due process doctrine, tracing it back
to Justice Harlan’s dissent in Poe v. Ullman (1961). He defends what he
calls a moral conception of the Constitution, one that embodies abstract moral
and political principles constructed (the verb used in the book’s title)
through the familiar (and, in Professor Fleming’s view, entirely legitimate)
process of common law constitutionalism that reasons by analogy from one case
to the next. The protection of basic fundamental rights that fall within the
meaning of constitutional “liberty,” Fleming insists, calls for neither
unrestrained judicial review nor the implementation of any particular theory of
political morality, including the libertarianism of John Stuart Mill. Instead, the doctrine calls for the gradual,
careful, and reasoned expansion of basic liberty protections—limited to those
that are essential to personal self-government—by analogizing to protections
already in place. This is why and how the marital privacy recognized in Griswold
v. Connecticut (1965) led to the general right to use contraceptives in Eisenstadt
v. Baird (1972) that led to the right to choose an abortion in Roe v.
Wade (1973) (as later limited by Planned Parenthood v. Casey (1992))
that led to the right to engage in sexual conduct in private in Lawrence v.
Texas (2003) that led to the constitutionally protected right to same-sex
marriage in Obergefell v. Hodges (2015). Constructing
Basic Liberties contains powerful criticisms of originalism as a theory of
constitutional interpretation. These criticisms are needed now more than ever
following Dobbs’ moral vacuity in holding that the Constitution is
silent about the ability of women, once pregnant, to have any say on whether to
give birth on the ground that the men who adopted the Fourteenth Amendment—and
who excluded women from the spheres of politics, self-governance, and rights—would
have so thought if asked. Professor
Fleming also explains why substantive due process doctrine protects rights to
personal autonomy, such as those involving contraception and sexual intimacy,
but not those implicating economic liberties, including the right to contract. Economic
liberties are sufficiently protected, he explains, through political and
legislative processes. There are politically powerful forces defending and
promoting capitalism and free trade in this country, making vigorous judicial
intervention on their behalf neither necessary nor appropriate. Our country has
many problems, but a lack of political and legal commitments to capitalist
principles and practices does not appear to be one of them. (I will note that even
the hallowed grounds of pitching
mounds in major league baseball parks are now stamped with corporate logos.) Constructing
Basic Liberties also effectively responds to the “unenumerated rights”
critique of substantive due process raised by those who, ironically enough, do
not hesitate before defending unenumerated rights in other contexts, including
that of the Free Exercise Clause. The conceptual and interpretative distance
between the word “liberty” and the constitutional right to engage in sexual
conduct with another adult in private, for example, would seem to be no greater
than that between the words “free exercise” of religion and, for example, the constitutional
right of religious business owners to deny goods and services to customers
based on their sexual orientation, gender identity, and even religion. There
may be valid arguments in favor of the proposition that the Constitution
recognizes the free exercise right and not the substantive due process one, but
a difference in textual enumeration is not one of them. In each instance, there
is a recognition of an unenumerated right (the right to have consensual sex or the
right to turn away customers) through the judicial application of general and
abstract constitutional principles to particular circumstances. Professor
Fleming has another objective in his book: to convince us that the post-Griswold
applications of substantive due process doctrine do not constitute judicial enactments
of Mill’s libertarian harm principle (as Chief Justice Roberts claimed in his Obergefell
dissent). Here Professor Fleming points both to the Court’s lack of explicit
reliance on the principle in rulings such as Casey and Obergefell and to the fact that the Lawrence
Court used the notion of harm as a shield rather than as a sword, that is to limit
rather than to expand the right to engage in sexual conduct in private. Lawrence
tells us that when sexual conduct in private risks harming social institutions
(such as that of marriage in the case of adultery) or individuals (such as in
the case of sex with minors), the state can restrict it. I
do not find the sword vs. shield distinction persuasive here. Unlike Professor
Fleming, I believe the libertarian harm principle normatively explains much of
the Court’s contemporary protections of personal liberties related to family,
parenting, sexuality, and reproduction. It is true that the Court, from Griswold
to Obergefell, did not explicitly rely on Mill and his famous principle.
But considerations of harm (or their absence) played implicit roles in most of
those cases. For example, given that opponents of same-sex marriage repeatedly
claimed that the marriage bans were needed to prevent
harm to children, the Court could not have decided Obergefell in the
way it did without, at the very least, implicitly rejecting the harm claims. (It
should also be noted that the Obergefell Court explicitly relied on the
harms to children of same-sex couples engendered by the marriage bans to strike
them down.) Even Professor Fleming, in distinguishing same-sex marriage bans
from polygamy prohibitions, points to possible harms to children and to women engendered
by the ways in which polygamy is practiced in North America as the main reasons
for denying constitutional protection to the practice. Although it may be true
that the courts, after the turn of the century, have generally deemed LGBTQ
people to be “worthy” (to use Professor Fleming’s term) of liberty protections
under the Constitution, while concluding the opposite of polygamists, those
assessments of worthiness are partly linked, whether explicitly or implicitly,
to questions of harms to third parties arising (or not) from the conduct
subject to regulation. In
rejecting a libertarian/Millian understanding of the Due Process Clause,
Professor Fleming argues that the Court has evinced a richer or thicker understanding
(in a moral sense) of “liberty.” Rather than defending constitutional “liberty”
in what Professor Fleming deems to be the purely libertarian sense of “cultivating individuality” through the protection
of innumerable activities, the Court has protected only those activities that are
essential to ordered liberty, that is that are “significant for personal
self-government or deliberative autonomy.” This understanding of constitutional
liberty, Professor Fleming insists, is not libertarian because it is not about
promoting autonomy for its own sake or for realizing one’s individuality.
Instead, he explains, “the cases engage in a project of extending rights
already protected for some to others in order to enable them to pursue the same
noble purposes and moral goods.” Those purposes and goods include the attainment
of marriage’s civic objectives and the promotion of equal citizenship, as
expanded to include women and LGBTQ people. As
a descriptive matter, Professor Fleming presents a well-reasoned account of the
Supreme Court’s fundamental rights cases recognizing liberty rights. At the
same time, I wonder whether there is much light between a libertarian account
of liberty that focuses, as Professor Fleming claims, on cultivating
individuality and a moral account of liberty that focuses, as he prefers, on personal
self-government. At the end of the day, both ways of understanding liberty are
consistent with the libertarian objective of prioritizing individual choices
over social conceptions of the common good as reflected in our laws. Similarly,
both ways of understanding liberty prioritize negative rights and the right to
be left alone over positive rights. (The fundamental right to marry is an
interesting exception since the rights claimants in those cases, when
challenging the state’s refusal to recognize their relationships, do not ask to
be left alone, but instead insist that they are constitutionally entitled to
have their relationships regulated as
marital.) In fact, much of contemporary constitutional litigation involves
repeated accusations by challengers, sometimes from the political left and
sometimes from the political right, that the government, in the dispute in
question, threatens rather than enables freedom. Under the relentless scrutiny
of constant constitutional litigation, government action, implicating almost
every conceivable policy area, is frequently seen as suspect or illegitimate, regardless
of whether the state seeks to achieve paternalistic or egalitarian or
redistributive or educational or health or safety (or fill-in-the-blank) objectives. Professor
Fleming in this book and in an earlier
one (co-authored with Linda McClain) defends a constitutive or formative understanding
of individual rights protected by the Constitution aimed at “inculcating civic
virtues, encouraging responsible exercise of rights, and fostering the
capacities of persons for responsible democratic and personal self-government.”
From this perspective, the recognition and enforcement of constitutional rights
allow for greater participation in deliberative processes and democratic self-governance.
At the level of theory, there is much to be said for this conception of constitutional
rights. Yet, as a practical matter, the repeated use of constitutional
litigation by activists across the political spectrum, as a means of attaining
judicial vetoes of government policies they dislike, inevitably ends up
prioritizing individual autonomy considerations at the expense of deliberative
processes and the people’s ability to govern themselves. Our Constitution, as
currently constructed (to use Professor Fleming’s preferred verb) through judicial
interpretation, seems better equipped to promote personal self-governance than polity
self-governance. As
a progressive, I like the libertarian outcomes of due process constitutional
litigation that prioritize individual autonomy and choice in matters related to
family, parenting, sexuality, and reproduction. Conservatives, for their part,
like the libertarian outcomes of constitutional litigation outside of
the Liberty Clause. (If it were not for the continued stigma of Lochner,
many more on the right would undoubtedly call for such outcomes within
the Clause as applied to economic regulations and the protection of the right
to contract.) For
example, many conservatives embrace libertarianism by pushing for unrestrained
electioneering expenditures by corporations and wealthy individuals under the
Free Speech Clause. (The Supreme Court granted them their wish in Citizens
United v. FEC (2010)). And they do the same in relentlessly pushing for the
Second Amendment to be constructed in ways that protect the right of individuals
as young as 18 to choose to possess firearms at the expense of government
efforts to reduce gun violence. (The Supreme Court granted them their wish in District
of Columbia v. Heller (2008)). And, to provide a third example (there are
countless more), many conservatives promote libertarianism by vigorously pushing
to have the First Amendment constructed in ways that provide religious business
owners with the right to use criteria such as sexual orientation and gender
identity to choose with whom to contract in the economic marketplace. (The
Supreme Court is likely to grant them their wish
by next summer.) In other words, despite Professor Fleming’s noble attempts to
distinguish between libertarian theory and politics, on the one hand, and the methodical
and piecemeal judicial construction of constitutional liberties, on the other,
the reality is that we are all (at least some of the time) constitutional libertarians
now. There
is a part of me that welcomes and very much appreciates Professor Fleming’s vigorous
defense of substantive due process doctrine in his new book. This is
particularly true after Dobbs has threatened the continued viability of
that doctrine in ways that no other case has done in recent memory. But those of
us on the left side of the political spectrum should also keep in mind the
costs for progressive objectives writ large that continue to accrue from a
libertarian/hyper-individualistic understanding of the Constitution. Such an
understanding offered (for fifty years) a right to choose a pre-viability
abortion unencumbered by overt government coercion, but not a right to
government subsidies for those who could not afford the medical procedure. A
libertarian understanding of the Constitution (or at least one that is
consistent with libertarian outcomes) has given us a right to sexual intimacy
in private, but it has also stymied efforts, for example, to expand Medicaid
coverage through Obamacare and to limit the ability of corporations and wealthy
individuals to influence elections in the weeks before votes are cast. And such
an understanding has given couples a right to marry regardless of gender, but
it has limited, for example, the ability of society to use democratically
enacted laws to protect us from the horrors of gun violence. And, by next
summer, the
Court is likely to use the Free Speech Clause as a vehicle through which to
prioritize the liberty interests of business owners in the marketplace over the
equality interests of groups protected by anti-discrimination laws. The
publication of Professor Fleming’s excellent and thought-provoking book, when
coupled with the Supreme Court’s evisceration of substantive due process
doctrine in Dobbs, presents us with crucial challenges and opportunities.
Many will continue to fight for vital yet limited gains that can be made to fit
the types of libertarian constitutional understandings that seem to prevail
most often before the Supreme Court. But perhaps others will take this as a
moment to push for paradigm shifts that rely less on constitutionally protected
rights to personal autonomy (whether they are found in the First, Second,
Fifth, or Fourteenth Amendments) and more on the attainment of redistributive
and egalitarian objectives through democratic deliberation and collective
self-governance. For this reason, I entirely agree with Professor Fleming’s
suggestion to liberals and progressives, made at the end of his book, that they
pay more attention to legislatures, especially at the state and local levels,
than to courts in order “not only to protect their rights but more generally to
promote their substantive constitutional visions or political conceptions of
justice.” Carlos A. Ball is a Distinguished
Professor at Rutgers Law School. His most recent book is Principles
Matter: The Constitution, Progressives, and the Trump Era. He can be
reached at cball@law.rutgers.edu.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |