E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
In
Constructing Basic Liberties, Jim Fleming seeks to justify and
reinvigorate substantive due process at a moment when the Court is seeking to
destroy important branches of it. “[O]ur commitments to liberty,” Fleming shows,
have been built out “over time on the basis of experience, new insights, and
moral learning.” (p. 44) This “process of common law constitutional
interpretation,” Fleming argues, underlies “the coherence and structure of our
practice of substantive due process.” (Id.; see also p. 165) How
bold of Fleming to execute a defense of Roe, Lawrence, and Obergefell—each
grounded in substantive due process—just as the Court is upending American law
and life with Dobbs.
In
Dobbs, as well as in dissents in Obergefell, the Justices who are
determined to savage modern substantive due process law equate it with Lochner. But why is “Lochner!”
such a powerful epithet?
“Lochner!”
became a term of denunciation, Jamal Greene shows, as both liberals and conservatives united in their
repudiation of the case. Answering the Lochner objection and showing how
the modern substantive due process precedents differ from Lochner and
the old substantive due process precedents is critical. Fleming offers a
powerful explanation. In
this post, we highlight features of an account that complements Fleming’s but
also diverges in important respects from his, which is set forth in our 2021 N.Y.U.
Law Review article, Answering the Lochner Objection:
Substantive Due Process and the Role of Courts in a Democracy. The
extension of Lochner to contemporary substantive due process doctrine begins
with Justice Black in Griswold, but it can be most powerfully traced to John
Hart Ely’s famous 1973 critique of Roe in The Wages of Crying Wolf,
published in the Yale Law Journal, and his foundational 1980 book, Democracy
and Distrust, elaborating his democracy-reinforcing theory of judicial
review.
Ely
had an important big idea—that judicial review (in a case like Brown v.
Board of Education) could be “democracy-reinforcing” by restricting
legislative sovereignty and repairing the infrastructure of representation. Ely
grasped that democracy could not be reduced to majoritarianism, and that
prejudice could produce deliberative blockages that would exclude, in the
language of Footnote Four of Carolene Products, discrete and insular
minorities.
But
Ely never saw how the democracy-reinforcing theory of judicial review he
proposed might extend to the substantive due process cases he attacked. As we have explored at greater length, Ely had blind spots, characteristic of
the legal academy at the time, that led him to underestimate the forms of bias
that women and LGBTQ people faced and the different ways that the organization
of the family can constrain democratic participation. The family is a
fundamental institution of life, no less than are institutions of education or
the media. Ely did not fathom this possibility. Indeed,
he seemed to view as perfectly natural the all-male worlds in which he moved. His
blind spots were surely widespread in the legal academy of his day. When Ely was teaching at Yale at the time
he published The Wages of Crying Wolf,
the law faculty included only one tenured woman. When Ely was teaching at
Harvard at the time of Democracy
and Distrust’s publication, there were only two women on the tenured
faculty—the first of whose tenure was
significantly delayed.
Had Ely had more women colleagues, one might have explained to him how the due process and equal protection
rights he questioned were also rights that promoted the equal participation of
marginalized groups. But without being confronted with the views
of women colleagues, Ely seemed to barely question the legitimacy of all-male
legislatures deciding questions about women’s autonomy. Ely went
out of his way to question abortion rights on both liberty and equality
grounds. He disparaged the case for judicial scrutiny of abortion restrictions:
“Compared with men, women may constitute such a ‘minority’; compared with the
unborn, they do not. I’m not sure I’d know a discrete and insular minority if I
saw one, but confronted with a multiple choice question requiring me to
designate (a) women or (b) fetuses as one, I’d expect no credit for the former
answer.” Ely, supra, at 934–35. Yet
he never paused to explain how all-male legislatures were constitutionally
adequate to represent either group. (Ely, pp. 934-35)
In
short, Ely disparaged or ignored women’s equality claims. At the time Ely wrote
The Wages of Crying Wolf, women in the Yale student body had been
mobilizing against Connecticut’s criminal abortion statute. And they were
supported by one of Ely’s faculty colleagues, who co-authored with them an article that became an authoritative history of
the Equal Rights Amendment. Women in the school and the state succeeded in
getting a federal
court to invalidate the Connecticut abortion law in Abele v. Markle on equality-inflected grounds. Yet Ely dismissed Roe by crying “Lochner!” without
even mentioning the Connecticut decision that preceded Roe. Two decades
later, Ely explained, “I don’t think a principled opinion along these lines
could have been written at the time” Roe was decided. This is a puzzling
statement, seemingly explained more by his own biases and the demographics of
the legal academy. As Fleming points out (p. 179), in 1992 Ely found his way to
endorsing Casey, which protected the abortion right on
equality-inflected grounds.
Ely’s target
was Roe, but he rejected other substantive due process liberties as well.
As Fleming explains (p. 136), Ely was more sympathetic to the equal protection
claims of “homosexuals” than of women, but he did not recognize how sexual liberty
claims for gays and lesbians could be democracy reinforcing. Again, we note, he
espoused these views at a time when the Yale and Harvard law faculties on which
he served included no out gay members.
As
we discuss at greater length in our published account, prevailing norms and biases of the
legal academy seem to have shaped the ways that Ely identified the institutions
and practices that are democracy reinforcing. He did not take sufficient
account of the ways in which the claimants in cases like Griswold, Roe,
Bowers, and Lawrence were members of marginalized groups seeking
to break into the democratic process. Women and LGBTQ groups developed forms of
protest—speak outs and coming out—to contest the stigmatization and
criminalization of the conduct the law prohibited. Courts provided venues in
which to circumvent deliberative blockages created by decades of
criminalization and to open conversations about legitimate uses of the criminal
law in private life. Ultimately, both women and LGBTQ people asserted liberty- and
equality-based claims to engage in the conduct that the law had long banned. As
our article develops at greater length, courts
protecting substantive due process rights in cases from Griswold to Obergefell
were intervening in conditions of political inequality and stigma and were
supporting the democratic participation of marginalized groups. When analyzed
with attention to the background conditions confronting those who asserted
constitutional liberty claims, we can see, contra Ely, the Court’s modern substantive
due process decisions are, like equal protection decisions protecting racial
minorities, examples of democracy-reinforcing judicial review. We
observe in closing that in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization,
Justice Alito invoked the specter of Lochner as justification for
adopting the Glucksberg standard to reverse Roe and to discredit modern
substantive due process cases. It will take decades to reckon with Dobbs.
As we do, we need to end the practice of unexamined citations to Lochner! Without determining the scope of Lochner!’s
meaning, an unexamined appeal to Lochner! can threaten liberties that enable
Americans from all walks of life to more fully participate in our democracy.
This
is the great contribution of Jim Fleming’s book.
Douglas
NeJaime is the Anne Urowsky Professor at Yale Law School. He can be reached at douglas.nejaime@yale.edu. Reva
Siegel is the Nicholas deB. Katzenbach Professor at Yale Law School. She can be
reached at reva.siegel@yale.edu.