Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Rejecting Thin Constitutionalism
|
Monday, March 07, 2022
Rejecting Thin Constitutionalism
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Tarun Khaitan The central claim that Professors Mark Tushnet and Bojan
Bugaric make in their provocative new book ‘Power to the People’ is that
populism is only contingently in conflict with constitutionalism. Much of their
argument will turn on what populism and constitutionalism mean. Taming either
of these two slippery concepts is ambitious enough, attempting to do so for
both simultaneously would significantly advance current discourse in
constitutional studies. This is likely to be the case even if they get it
wrong: one learns a lot even from the mistakes of clever and insightful
scholars. The first step in their carefully argued book is a description and
defence of what they characterise as ‘thin constitutionalism’. It is this first
step that I will subject to close inquiry in this post. What is ‘thin constitutionalism’ (hereinafter, ‘TC’)?
The authors give a “least-common-denominator definition: its components are
elements that nearly everyone committed to a normative idea of
constitutionalism would agree on, and it doesn’t include elements that some
people sincerely committed to such an idea wouldn’t think essential to the
project of constitutionalism” (2), namely majority rule, constitutional
entrenchment, judicial independence, and politicians and political parties
(12). The Normativity of Thin
Constitutionalism The authors’ understanding of constitutionalism is
normative, not (merely) conceptual inasmuch as it is (for them) a benchmark for
what institutional arrangements are acceptable, rather than merely a
descriptive concept or a pedagogic tool. The authors are not entirely clear on
the normativity of TC though. On occasion, for example, they claim that “it is
mostly a heuristic device” (11). Even so, I think the best reading of TC is
indeed normative. After all, they define it as made of elements that ‘nearly
everyone committed to a normative idea of constitutionalism would agree
on’ (2, emphasis added). Further support to the proposition that the authors
view TC as a (normative) guide to constitutional design is found in this claim:
“you say that constitutionalism requires a specific thing, but I can point you
to constitutional systems that seem to me to do just fine without it” (11).
Presumably, if no such system could be pointed to, in the authors’ view,
constitutionalism would indeed require that specific thing. Indeed, sometimes it seems that they view
constitutionalism not just as a normative benchmark, but as the exclusive
normative standard in relation to a state’s institutional setup: for the
authors, asking whether something “must be permitted” is the same question as
asking whether “constitutionalism requires that they be permitted” (10). In
other words, the only relevant question one ought to ask about the
(moral) permissibility of an institutional setup is whether it conforms to
constitutionalism. This is a logical fallacy of the following sort: All good persons are truthful. Nikolai is truthful. Therefore, Nikolai
is a good person. For all we know, Nikolai could well be a truthful
bully. Personal as well as institutional characters admit to value plurality:
their goodness or badness cannot be judged along just one or two normative
axes. Indeed, insisting that Nikolai must at least be good qua his
truthfulness is dangerous, for it could be used to mask or paper over a serious
flaw (bullying). Goodness of persons and institutions must be an
all-things-considered judgment. Perhaps this criticism mischaracterises the normative
essence of constitutionalism (as the authors see it). It may be that they think
of constitutionalism as akin not to singular personal/institutional virtues
(like truthfulness or efficiency), but rather a more general appraisal of the overall
character of an institutional setup. Thus, a constitutionalist regime
may itself be akin to a good person rather than an truthful person.
But then, the concept of constitutionalism does no work, or—at least—no
more work than what ’good’, ’desirable’, etc could do without invoking a vague,
heavy-duty, -ism. Unfortunately, the authors don’t tell us about what
kind of normative benchmark their conception of constitutionalism really is. I
suspect the most promising clue lies in their frequently juxtaposing it with
‘politics’: “The idea of thin constitutionalism brings out the essentially political—rather
than constitutional—nature of objections to specific populisms” (11,
emphasis added). It seems that whatever constitutionalism requires, it is
something other than ‘political’ (so, … judicial?). Further confusion is caused
by their use of the adjectival form of the term ‘constitution’ (constitutional)
rather than that of ‘constitutionalism’ (constitutionalist) in this quote. Surely, an arrangement can be
constitutional (in the context of a given constitution) without conforming to
constitutionalism, and vice versa. If the substitution is telling, have the
authors allowed their (US-inflected) equation of
constitutionality-determination with judicialization to infect their
understanding of what is at stake when we ask ‘Is this arrangement in
conformity with constitutionalism?’ Perhaps they think the attractions of TC
lie in carving out a narrow institutional role for courts. If so, TC would have
little attraction for anyone who denies—as I do—any necessary connection
between judicialization and the determination of what is constitutional (or,
constitutionalist, for that matter). To sum up my first criticism, it seems that while the
authors intend TC to work as a normative benchmark for constitutional systems,
and want it to be a relatively undemanding benchmark to leave sufficient space
for ‘politics’, they do not tell us much about its point or purpose. The
authors do raise the issue of the point of constitutionalism briefly
(22-23), only to dismiss a possible candidate (i.e. to limit governmental
power). They offer no positive account of what the raison d’être of
constitutionalism is. To put the point differently, we cannot know the content
and scope of a normative phenomenon like constitutionalism without knowing what
constitutionalism—thick or thin—is for. Reasonable Disagreement and
the Least Common Denominator Instead, they prefer to give content to TC using what
they describe as the least-common-denominator approach by stipulation:
basically, if there is ’reasonable disagreement’ on whether a specific feature
is or is not part of constitutionalism, it is automatically ruled out as a part
of the concept. What then is the case for using the ‘reasonable disagreement’
approach to determine the content of a given controversial concept? Again, the
authors do not seem to offer a defence for preferring this approach, except to
say that “Whatever else you think constitutionalism requires, you’ll agree that
it requires at least thin constitutionalism” (11). That may well be true—if the
‘reasonable disagreement’ test is indeed applied correctly—but all that can be
discovered through this approach is some sort of conceptual core of
the phenomenon under study. Chris McCrudden, for example, used something like
this approach to determine the minimum core of
dignity. While such a semantic least-common-denominator
approach can help uncover the conceptual core of a phenomenon, and therefore
aid understanding, it is incapable of determining its normative content and
scope. To see why, consider that we are interested in
determining what counts as ’murder’ (in the moral, rather than the legal, sense
of blameworthy killing). As a moral concept, murder is an evaluative concept
that is a normative benchmark for determining what types of killing another may
be acceptable. Folks disagree, dare I say reasonably, about whether the
following acts count as murder: (i) killing A to protect the lives of B, C, & D
(assuming all parties are innocent), (ii) killing A upon her request to end her suffering
(especially when A is not terminally ill), (iii) doing something that one knows will result in
A’s death, but intending to do something morally permissible (such as save
one’s own life, avoiding a greater evil etc) and wishing there was a way to
achieve this other objective without resulting in A’s death. Most of us will agree that none of these three
scenarios constitute the conceptual core of what ‘murder’ is. But, that
does not mean that the mere fact of reasonable disagreement on these three
counts should—without more—exclude them from the normative scope of what
amounts to murder. Countless similar examples can be given with respect to
other normative phenomena, including the status of ‘indirect discrimination’
(disparate impact) as ’discrimination’, ‘consent obtained by lying’ as ’rape’,
‘hate speech’ as ‘protected free speech’, and so on. The
least-common-denominator approach, when applied to any of these normative
concepts, will inevitably result in permissive, libertarian, outcomes. The
authors know this, for they “note one problem associated with thin accounts. …
thick accounts make it too easy to find fault with actual practices. Thin
accounts, though, may make it too difficult to do so” (11). One would have
expected them, having noted this shortcoming, to defend their use of the
approach. Unfortunately, no such defence is provided. To avoid misunderstanding, let me clarify that
reasonable disagreement can sometimes give us reasons to act (or refrain from
acting). In the context of deeply divided societies, they may give pragmatic
reasons to refrain from deciding either
way,? and in democratic contexts give institutional reasons
to allocate the relevant decision-making power to
legislatures rather than to judges.? The authors do not
tell us that either of these reasons apply in the context of constitutionalism.
So, this is the second criticism: either TC has no normative value, or its
scope and content need determination by substantive arguments rather than the
reasonable-disagreement method. Is Thin Constitutionalism
Really Thin? My third, and final, criticism in this blog post is
that the authors apply their least-common-denominator method incorrectly. There
are four elements that the authors identify as constituting TC’s content: (i)
majority rule, (ii) constitutional entrenchment, (iii) judicial independence,
and (iv) politicians and political parties (12). Each of these elements are
stated at a very general level, to allow very different ways of approximating
to these requirements. But if the test of a feature being admitted to TC’s
scope is an inability to “point … to constitutional systems that seem … to do
just fine without it” (11), it is not clear that all of these items pass
muster. Take majority rule for example: even if one considers a disagreement
based on China’s remarkable ability to lift millions out of poverty as
nonetheless below the threshold of ‘reasonableness’, it is harder to say that
those who disagree with majority rule in the context deeply divided societies
are also being ‘unreasonable’. Constitutional theory and practice have
recognised consociationalism for too long and too clearly to dismiss it as
unreasonable disagreement with the ideal of majority rule. Consociationalism is
not some imperfect mechanism for approximating to majority rule; at least
certain forms of consociationalism are designed to ensure that ’the majority’ does
not rule. The same can be said of constitutional entrenchment: the authors
insist that TC requires that there be at least some constitutional provisions
that are entrenched against ordinary majorities (19). This would exclude
constitutions like that of the United Kingdom, which rely on constitutional
culture, rather than procedural entrenchment, to protect its fundamental norms.
Whatever its merit, is the British position unreasonable? The argument from
reasonable disagreement proves too much. In fact, if properly applied, it may
well result in a null—rather than thin—content for constitutionalism. These problems arise because the authors stipulate but
do not tell us why these four, and only these four, items qualify as contents
of TC. The list is presented as so self-evident that not much is offered by way
of justification. Nor do the authors say very much about the methodology
employed by them to discern what disagreements exist, and how they are
determined to be ‘reasonable’. Is it disagreement between framers of different
constitutions? Or opinions of constitutional scholars? An overwhelming majority
of actual illustrations—both positive and negative—of constitutional phenomena
in the relevant section (titled ‘The Elements of Thin Constitutionalism’, pp
12-32) are drawn from the United States (pp 14, 18, 19, 20, 24, 27, 28, 29, 30,
). This is somewhat ironic, as the authors (correctly) warn against a
‘selection effect’ because ‘the conclusions you draw about populism and
constitutionalism depend upon the populisms you include in your study’ in the
introductory chapter (4)—surely this is true not only of populism but also of
constitutionalism. The outsized role that the concept of ‘reasonable
disagreement’ has played in American constitutional thought and political
life—thanks perhaps to John Rawls—is well-known. TC applies this very-American
methodological legacy beyond its Rawlsian usage in the context of disagreements
over comprehensive conceptions of a good life to disagreements over
institutional forms. It also employs a parochially American look-and-feel lens
to determine what is ‘reasonable’. In conclusion, There is something attractive about using the
lens of ‘disagreement’ to think about constitutionalism. After all, it is a
plausible normative claim that constitutions ought to be framed with the
general agreement of all, or almost all, sections of the polity. But accepting this
normative proposition entails neither the predictive claim—that people are
most likely to agree to very thin constitutions only containing items they
agree upon—nor the normative claim—that this is how constitutions should be
designed. The predictive claim is belied by the evidence of remarkable thickness of constitutions in the
postcolonial world, as well as case studies that show that folks often prefer constitutions that
include their thick claims (including those they disagree with) as a package
deal over those that include none.? As a normative claim, TC may be
worse than not employing constitutionalism at all: just as Trump employed his
supposed ‘authenticity’ to paper over his numerous personal failings to gain
the confidence of the American voters, the thoroughly undemanding normative
standard of TC may well help legitimise decidedly bad regimes. Tarunabh Khaitan is the Head of Research, Bonavero
Institute of Human Rights (Oxford), Professor of Public Law and Legal Theory,
Faculty of Law (Oxford), Honorary Professorial Fellow (Melbourne Law School),
and the Walter V. Schaefer Visiting Professor of Law (Chicago Law School). He
is grateful to Prof Nick Barber for commenting on a draft of this post. Email:
tarunabh.khaitan@law.ox.ac.uk.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |