Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Constitutionalism after Populism: Empowering Which Democracy?
|
Tuesday, March 08, 2022
Constitutionalism after Populism: Empowering Which Democracy?
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Silvia Suteu Tushnet and Bugaric offer a welcome
reassessment of our understanding of populism in a constitutional key. In their
Power to the People: Constitutionalism
after Populism, they argue against easy assumptions about what populism is
and isn’t, and in particular “write against a background of popular and
academic publications arguing that populism is by definition antithetical to
constitutionalism.” (36) Their monograph proposes to take seriously both the populist
critiques of liberal constitutionalism and the alternative visions of
constitutionalism the populists put forth. In that sense, they reject the
notion – advanced by Jan-Werner Müller and others – that populists are by
definition anti-constitutionalists. Instead, they echo Robert Howse, who has argued
that anti-populists seeking to defend elite liberal democratic politics
mischaracterise populism in purely pejorative terms, as synonymous with mob
rule. Like Howse, Tushnet and Bugaric are interested in rescuing the radical
democratic potential of populism and “are sympathetic to many aspects of
progressive populist programs.” (2) They argue that there are different types
of populisms out there, and selection bias has meant that analyses so far have
overemphasised authoritarian versions – especially the cases of Hungary and
Poland – and underemphasised progressive ones – such as Syriza in Greece,
Podemos in Spain, and several Latin American examples. (44) Instead, the
authors view populism as coming in both democratic and authoritarian varieties,
and compatible with a host of ideologies, making easy generalisations a
mistake. (45) In this contribution, I want to focus on
Part III of their book, which also gives its subtitle. More specifically, I’d
like to engage with arguments the authors raise in the final chapter, on
‘Empowered Democracy’, about the potential for democratic renewal after the
populist challenge. This is where they look at the constitutional tools
employed and the type of democracy embraced by progressive populists. In
particular, they focus on populists’ supposed affinity for direct democracy,
especially the referendum. Contrary to the views of scholars like Nadia
Urbinati and, again, Müller, Tushnet and Bugaric believe populists not to have
a plebiscitarian penchant for its own sake. Instead, they argue that “populists
in Greece and Spain used direct democracy precisely because they wanted to
“deepen” sometimes too rigid and unresponsive channels of representative
democracy.” (147) For Tushnet and Bugaric, in other words, direct democratic mechanisms
are not in opposition to representative democracy; the referendum is not an
inherently evil tool of decision-making; and progressive populists are interested
in engaging the electorate directly because they are committed to the idea of
self-government and because they believe, unlike elitist liberal democrats,
that ordinary citizens have relevant policy expertise worth tapping into. As a democratic constitutionalist
myself, I find much to agree with here. As I have argued
elsewhere, we ignore populists’ critiques of liberal constitutionalism at
our own risk. These include fierce attacks on the rise of technocracy, pushback
against the retreat of politics from policymaking, and an overt rejection of
the project of globalisation in the name of national economic (and often
identitarian) retrenchment. There is a reason this discourse resonates with
voters, especially in places where they have felt systematically sidelined, and
a committed democrat should be able to provide a better answer to these woes,
rather than simply ignore them. In short, then, I agree with Tushnet and
Bugaric that constitutionalism after populism has the potential to be more genuinely
democratic and inclusive. However, I believe their analysis – in Chapter 10 of
the book in particular – rests on two main misconceptions: one rooted in
oversimplification and one in nondifferentiation. 1.
Oversimplification: populists and referendums The authors focus on the referendum as
the main tool of direct democracy, and implicitly self-government, that populists
are prone to use in decision-making. They seek to rescue it from criticism that
it is an inherently flawed mechanism of decision-making, and instead view it as
“only one of the tools available for populists seeking to determine what a
majority prefers”, and even that on only a subset of policy issues. (260) But
to suggest the only, or even main, reason why populists, and indeed any
politician, will put an issue to a referendum is to determine majority views on
a given question is to miss the special appeal of referendums. Referendums
could easily (and much more cheaply) be replaced by national opinion polls if
that were the case. Instead, it is the special claim to
democratic legitimation that a referendum vote can bring that makes it
appealing. All parties will try to shape public opinion during the referendum
campaign, not just gauge it dispassionately, and may use unfair tactics to do
so. Even less nefariously, the referendum may be used as a way for politicians
to eschew responsibility for unpopular decisions (e.g. on abortion or same-sex
marriage), to break political deadlock or rework the political rules of the
game (e.g. changing the electoral system), or even for inner party reasons, to
settle internal competition (e.g. as the Brexit referendum started out). All of
this to say that, even during ‘normal’ times of representative politics, the
recourse to referendum is more complex and potentially instrumental than the
authors’ account acknowledges. I see no reason to believe populists’ use of the
referendum is somehow purer or insulated from party politics and political
self-interest. Elsewhere, the authors also equate
referendums with a form of direct policymaking by the people: “Legislation by
the people themselves may be the cleanest example of populism”. (252) This,
connected to their view of (progressive) populists as singularly committed to
maximising self-government, make referendums especially appealing to the
populist as democrat. However, arguing that referendums may be democratic instruments need not require us to go as far as
identifying them with popular authorship as such. Not just because referendums
are prone to manipulation and elite control, but also because the very decision
of putting an issue to the people is not open to all. Rules will differ greatly
across systems on the right to initiate a referendum (most often resting with
the political branches) and may leave much wiggle room; assessing populists’
relationship to referendums solely on the basis of whether they have put a
particular issue to a popular vote therefore risks ignoring the politics
surrounding that initial decision. To illustrate these points, we can look
at some examples Tushnet and Bugaric themselves consider. They point to
Ireland’s successful legalisation of same-sex marriage and liberalisation of
access to abortion through referendums as examples of the instrument’s success,
not least in advancing, rather than stifling, minority rights. (259) To the
authors, the embrace of citizens’ assemblies in addition to the constitutionally-mandated
referendums on constitutional change in Ireland meant that “Ireland did see a
political party taking direct democracy as part of its program and to that
extent saw an existing party become more populist.” (270) However, there is a
different way to tell the story of both Irish referendums that raises doubts
about them as the means of choice to effect legal change. In both instances,
groups previously excluded from full rights recognition were forced to argue
for their accession to full citizenship. This in itself caused harm,
reinforcing as it did the notion that the LGBT community and women would need
to persuade the majority in order to be granted full equality before the law.
Seen from this perspective then, the minority rights-based objection to referendums
is harder to dismiss than Tushnet and Bugaric acknowledge. It’s precisely the
majoritarianism reinforced by the referendum that is the problem. 2.
Non-diferentiation: populists as direct or deliberative democrats? Briefly on the second misconception now.
The authors discuss direct and deliberative democracy interchangeably, and
count the turn to deliberative mechanisms such as citizens’ assemblies and
deliberative polling together with the use of referendums as part of populists’
entrusting of ordinary people with decision-making capacity. This would read as
an at least unorthodox understanding of deliberative tools, seeing as
deliberative democracy has long been accused of precisely the type of elitism
populists want to overcome. The small size of deliberative exercises such as
citizens’ assembly at the very least raises doubts as to whether they are
participatory instruments in the way referendums are. Tushnet and Bugaric
simply assume the problem of scale can be overcome, and even believe “citizens’
assemblies are designed precisely so they can be scaled up.” (262) This is not the case. In fact, the
scaling up problem persists in deliberative democracy, even while the spread of
the use of deliberative mechanisms allows for more evidence gathering and experimentation.
In the authors’ own cited case of Ireland, where a constitutional convention
and a citizens’ assembly preceded the same-sex marriage and abortion referendum
votes respectively, it is unclear what impact the micro-deliberative stage had
on the outcome. In the latter case, the assembly recommendation – to abolish
the constitutional ban on abortion entirely – actually exceeded expectations of
how radical a change it might prompt. But in both instances, and certainly in
the former, it was the referendum campaigns rather than the convention/assembly
deliberations that galvanised the public. How much voters actually knew or
cared about the preceding small size deliberative stages was unclear. This is why, together with Stephen
Tierney, I previously argued
that democratic legitimation and an approximation of demotic authorship requires
both the micro and the macro levels, both small scale deliberative exercises
like citizens’ assemblies and large scale ones like referendums. One allows for
the intense exchange of views under conditions of reciprocity, to which
participants come open to changing their mind but also endowed, at least to an
extent, with agenda-setting powers; the other entails societal debate on a
single question that will take the majority’s pulse and (if done right) engender
acceptance of the outcome of the vote. The latter is obviously appealing to
populists; the latter less so. Why does all this matter to the authors’
argument then? They acknowledge that populists don’t seem to have, at least so
far, made use of these deliberative innovations. (269) To Tushnet and Bugaric,
however, the main criterion for evaluating these innovations as instruments of
democratic empowerment is comparative vis-à-vis existing representative
institutions. As long as innovations lead to “more democracy than we have now”,
they are presumed to be both compatible with existing structures and desirable.
(271) However, this undifferentiated account of direct and deliberative
mechanisms misses an important distinction, one that matters to populists. As
Tierney and I have argued, the two “pursue different goals, operate based on
different dynamics, and are more suited towards producing certain types of
goods and not others.” (860) Because of this, direct and deliberative
democratic tools are better thought of as complementary but nevertheless
different, with the better focus on their sequencing so as to harness their
respective and combined potential. It is not coincidental that Tushnet and
Bugaric can find numerous examples of populist recourse to the referendum but
not of democratic innovations. The majoritarianism of the former can sit ill at
ease with and even undo the gains of small-scale deliberative structures. So
long as it is majoritarian decision-making the populists are after, they won’t
be likely to find much use for mechanisms of deliberative rather than direct
democracy. Dr Silvia Suteu, Associate Professor, University College London, UK, s.suteu@ucl.ac.uk.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |