Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts The SG’s Empty Ethics Case Against Jane Doe’s Lawyers
|
Tuesday, December 26, 2017
The SG’s Empty Ethics Case Against Jane Doe’s Lawyers
David Luban
A few days ago, Solicitor-General Noel Francisco submitted a Reply
Brief for Petitioners in Hargan v.
Garza, a case in which the government fought against releasing a pregnant
teenager (“Jane Doe”) from immigration detention so she could have an abortion.
The government lost in an en banc
opinion by the D.C. Circuit Court of Appeals, and she had the abortion, as was
her constitutional right.
The government wants the Supreme Court to grant certiorari
and vacate the Court of Appeals decision, on the remarkable ground that Jane
Doe’s lawyers, including ACLU counsel, behaved unethically by not telling DOJ
when she would have the abortion. As a result, the abortion took place without DOJ
filing an emergency motion for a stay. The government also wants the Court to
take disciplinary action against Jane Doe’s counsel. My question in this
post: how good are the SG’s ethics arguments? And my answer is: not good at
all. Giving the government confidential information about the timing of Jane Doe's abortion would have been the real ethics violation.
The factual background
A bit of factual background: under the laws of Texas, where
Jane Doe was in custody, women seeking abortions must be counseled at least 24
hours in advance of the procedure by the same physician who would perform it.
Jane Doe received counseling, but the physician who counseled her (the “first
doctor”) was initially unavailable the day after the Court of Appeals issued
its order that she be allowed to proceed. On the evening of Tuesday, October
24, Doe went to the clinic to obtain counseling again, from a second
doctor. When the second doctor was not
available at the clinic, one of Doe’s representatives appointed by the Texas
courts informed government counsel that Doe had rescheduled
her appointment at the clinic for the next morning (Wednesday the 25th) at
7:30 a.m., and that the abortion would take place the day after that – Thursday
morning the 26th. At that time,
the attorney ad litem believed that fact to be true.
The SG’s argument depends upon what happened a few hours
later. Doe’s lawyer learned, later that
night, that the first doctor might be available, after all, and they moved up
the next day’s appointment to 4:15 a.m.
As Marty Lederman explained
in a recent post, at 9:30 p.m. on the 24th, Doe’s attorney ad litem emailed the
Texas shelter and the AUSA to inform them of the new 4:15 appointment time—a
step that was necessary in order to inform the shelter employees of when they
had to allow Doe’s transport to the clinic, regardless of whether that
appointment would be for counseling with the second doctor or an abortion with
the first. The attorney ad litem’s e-mail did not specifically mention
that the new appointment might be with Doe’s previous doctor (something that
was not yet confirmed), nor that Doe might obtain an abortion at that
appointment if the first doctor were able to attend. Doe’s counsel had
not promised to update the government on when the abortion would take place – they
said only that “as soon as we understand the clinic’s schedule tomorrow we’ll
let you know.” (Here,
p. 13.) Even so, and as the SG has
acknowledged, the unusual time of the rescheduled appointment naturally “caused
shelter staff to wonder later that night whether the nature of the appointment
also might have changed.”
Then, sometime
soon after midnight on the 25th, Doe and her representatives confirmed that the
original doctor could be present at 4:15, and could perform
the abortion that morning—but they did
not tell the government of this fact, which the government only learned
three or four hours later, when Doe arrived at the clinic. The SG’s argument is, in effect, that these
few hours of silence, very early on Wednesday the 25th, amounted to
an unethical “misrepresentation” by omission, tantamount to affirmatively lying
about the purpose of the visit. The government lawyers relied on this supposed
“misrepresentation,” and failed to apply for an emergency stay, even though
there was already reason for the government to suspect, as the shelter staff
did, that the 4:15 appointment might be for an abortion procedure.
Confidentiality 101
As I argued in an
op-ed in The Hill, the failure of Jane Doe’s counsel to inform
the government of the fact that the 4:15 appointment would be for an abortion was
not unethical. Just the opposite is the case: it would have been unethical for
counsel to reveal confidential client information to the adversary, who would then
likely use it to harm their client’s interests. (I should note that in
its brief in opposition to the government’s petition, Garza’s counsel cited
my op-ed – page 31, footnote 18.) Her counsel couldn’t affirmatively lie to the
government about the purpose of the accelerated doctor’s visit (and they
didn’t), but revealing it would have been an egregious violation of their duty
of confidentiality. In this case, the revelation would be particularly damaging
– it might have made it impossible for her to get the abortion she wanted, and
that was her constitutional right. That’s because at the time of her abortion,
she was 16 weeks pregnant, and in Texas
abortion is illegal after week 20. The government’s strategy was obviously
to delay the abortion for at least the time that it would take to have the case
resolved by the Supreme Court.
To be clear:
the information about the purpose of her doctor’s visit would be protected by
the confidentiality rule even if revealing it did not threaten Jane Doe’s
interests. This is common sense: a major policy underlying confidentiality is
to protect client privacy. Partly for that reason, the Model Rules defines
confidential information in the broadest possible terms: “information relating
to the representation of the client” (MR 1.6). This broad protection of
confidentiality is common to all states. The Texas rules – governing Jane Doe’s attorney ad litem – clarify that “confidences” includes both privileged
information and “all information relating to a client or furnished by the
client, other than privileged information, acquired by the lawyer during the
course of or by reason of the representation of the client” (Texas Disciplinary Rule 1.05(a)). A lawyer must not reveal confidences to
anyone “other than the client, the client's representatives, or the members,
associates, or employees of the lawyer's law firm” and “shall not knowingly use
confidential information to the disadvantage of the client unless the client
consents after consultation” (Texas Disciplinary Rule 1.05(b)(1) and (2)).
The same with the D.C. Rules of Professional Conduct, with a
minor variation in wording: “confidences” means privileged information,
“secrets” are “other information
gained in the professional relationship that the client has requested be held
inviolate, or the disclosure of which would be embarrassing, or would be likely
to be detrimental, to the client” – and both
are protected. (D.C. Rules of Professional Conduct 1.6(a) and (b)). (The “confidences and secrets” terminology
is a holdover from the Model Rules’ predecessor, the 1969 Model Code of
Professional Responsibility.) The import of all these rules is the same: if you
learned the information while representing the client, and it pertains to the
representation, it is confidential.
The SG's argument: misrepresentation by omission
The SG argues that failure to reveal confidential
information about the changed purpose of her doctor’s appoint was an unethical
“misrepresentation by omission.” The argument depends upon an awkward admixture
of one rule of the Model Rules of Professional Conduct—Rule 8.4(c)—with a
comment related to another Model Rule, Rule 4.1(a):
Rule 4.1 provides that, “[i]n the
course of representing a client a lawyer shall not knowingly * * * make a false
statement of material fact or law to a third person,” Model Rules of Prof’l
Conduct R. 4.1 (2017), and shall not, at any time, “engage in conduct involving
dishonesty, fraud, deceit or misrepresentation,” Model Rules of Prof’l Conduct
R. 8.4(c) (2017). Although a lawyer “generally has no affirmative duty to inform
an opposing party of relevant facts,” misrepresentations can occur through
“omissions that are the equivalent of affirmative false statements.” Model
Rules of Prof’l Conduct R. 4.1 cmt. 1 (2017). Even when a lawyer makes a
representation he reasonably believes is true when made, an “obligation to
disclose * * * ordinarily arises” if the lawyer subsequently discovers the
statement to be false. Restatement (Third) of the Law Governing Lawyers § 98
cmt. d (1998). Respondent points to no legitimate reason why these basic
principles should not apply here.
On this view, the “representation” that the attorney ad
litem made, reasonably believing it to be true, was that the abortion would
occur on Thursday the 26th.
And the “discovery” that that would no longer be the case occurred
shortly after midnight on the 25th.
Was this, in the words of the ABA’s (non-binding) comment to Model Rule
4.1(a), a “misrepresentation” by an “omission” that was “the equivalent of [an] affirmative
false statement[]”?
Notice that the comment says only that omissions can be the equivalent of affirmative
false statements. It does not, however,
identify which omissions those are. Nor does it explain what a lawyer should do
if the information in the omission is confidential. In order to understand the
application of the comment, it's important to look at the other half of
Rule 4.1—Rule 4.1(b), which the Solicitor General fails to cite:
In the course of representing a
client, a lawyer shall not knowingly . . . (b) fail to disclose a material fact to a third person when disclosure is
necessary to avoid assisting a criminal or fraudulent act by a client, unless disclosure is prohibited by Rule 1.6.
Two things about this rule are noteworthy. First, it prohibits failing to disclose a
material fact only when, at a minimum, such a failure would assist the client’s
“criminal or fraudulent act.” Obviously, then, Rule 4.1(b) has nothing to do
with what happened in the Jane Doe case, because she was not engaged in any criminal
or fraudulent activity—she was merely exercising her constitutional right to an
abortion.
Second, even as so limited—to cases, unlike this one,
involving the client’s criminal or fraudulent activity—a failure to disclose is
still required, if the “disclosure is prohibited by Rule 1.6.” Model Rule 1.6 establishes the duty of
confidentiality. Thus, even if a client is committing a crime or
fraud, her lawyers cannot divulge information protected by Rule 1.6. It
would be absurd, then, to suppose that lawyers can, let alone that they must, divulge a crucial client confidence
when their client’s conduct is entirely lawful. If confidentiality limits disclosure
when the client is committing a crime or fraud, it plainly does so when the
client’s conduct is blameless.
The SG quotes a standard treatise on the law of lawyering,
which says that the duty of confidentiality is not absolute. Of course
confidentiality isn’t absolute – the rule (MR 1.6) has exceptions, which every
law student is expected to learn for the bar exam. For example, if a client’s
crime or fraud will cause serious bodily or financial injury, lawyers are
permitted (not required) to reveal client confidences. But none of the exceptions applies in Jane Doe’s case. The SG doesn’t
quote or cite the actual confidentiality rule; it isn’t hard to guess why.
The Restatement of the Law Governing Lawyers
To support the charge of misrepresentation by omission, the
SG also cites the Restatement (Third) of
the Law Governing Lawyers. According to the Restatement, “A lawyer who has made a representation on behalf of a
client reasonably believing it true when made may subsequently come to know of
its falsity. An obligation to disclose before consummation of the transaction
ordinarily arises, unless the lawyer takes other corrective action.” (§98,
comment d) This sounds like clear confirmation of the SG's argument.
Notice, however, the words “before
consummation of the transaction.” They make it clear that this comment is about
obligations to disclose in the context of entering into business transactions,
not adversarial litigation. The rest of the comment – which the SG doesn’t
mention – makes that clear: it refers readers to the Restatements of Agency and
Contract, contexts where it’s illegal to consummate deals based on undisclosed
material facts.
The same comment to §98 in the Restatement
of the Law Governing Lawyers continues: “Disclosure, being required by law (see §63), is not prohibited by the general
rule of confidentiality.” Section 63, which this sentence cross-references, indeed says that “a lawyer may use or disclose confidential client information when
required by law.” This makes it crystal clear that the “obligation to disclose”
that the SG quotes only applies to disclosures required by some other law (such
as the law of contracts). Disclosure may be required by law in business
transactions – but it obviously is not
required in adversarial litigation. In litigation, lawyers are obligated to
disclose confidences to the adversary only when other law or a valid court order compels
them to do so (as in the discovery process). (Rule 1.6(b)(6))
Recognizing that fraudulent business transactions are the
primary context for doctrines of misrepresentation by omission helps us
better understand the comment to Rule 4.1 – and to see how little it has to do
with Jane Doe’s case. The 1983 Model Rules and their comments were completed while Big Law was reeling from two recent scandals (here and here) in which lawyers watched their clients commit extravagant financial frauds but did and said
nothing; one law firm paid $10 million in a civil settlement. Post-scandal, the question of how lawyers can disentangle themselves from
client frauds without violating confidentiality preoccupied the drafters,
especially Geoffrey Hazard, Jr., the reporter who drafted the Model Rules. (Here
and here.)
The Restatement's references to agency
and contract law, and to disclosures required by law make explicit what the drafting history confirms: that the comment to Rule 4.1 is about disentangling lawyers
from fraudulent transactions. The Restatement section from which the SG
selectively quotes actually harms his case rather than helping it, because it makes clear that it pertains only to disclosures required by other law.
That is not Jane Doe's case. Nothing in
the Model Rules or its history suggests that the rules require advocates in the midst
of contentious litigation to correct faulty inferences their adversary draws
from things the lawyer has not said. (One might add: this is doubly true when
the client is doing nothing fraudulent, triply true when the confidential
information concerns something as personal as a medical procedure, and
quadruply true when the client is a vulnerable minor in government custody.)
The Court's own disciplinary authority
The SG also calls on the Supreme Court to discipline Jane
Doe’s counsel under its own rules. Rule 8.2
permits the Court to “take any appropriate disciplinary
action against any attorney who is admitted to practice before it for conduct
unbecoming a member of the Bar.” But how can fulfilling the ethical obligation
of confidentiality be “conduct unbecoming a member of the Bar”? On the contrary:
violating the confidentiality rule
would be conduct unbecoming a member of the Bar. Ironically, it’s an
ethics violation to “knowingly induce” other lawyers to
violate the ethics rules – which seems to be what the SG is asking the Court to
do through the cudgel of its disciplinary power.
This past week, we witnessed government lawyers trying again
to stop two undocumented teenagers (one of whom was pregnant from a rape) from
obtaining abortions, this time on the ground that it is not in their own best
interest – a mind-boggling argument Marty blogged about here and here. They failed. The SG’s
rather desperate effort to vacate the Court of Appeals decision in Hargan v. Garza on specious ethical
grounds should fail as well.
Posted 11:16 AM by David Luban [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |