E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Bruce Ackerman’s We
the People series is self-consciously about canon formation. He wants
“us”—on which more later—to “consider seriously whether landmark statutes
[alongside the written Constitution] deserve a place in the modern
constitutional canon.”
Ackerman is
right that the “texts” that need interpretation in order to make sense of American
constitutional discourse include but are by no means limited to the written
Constitution and its internally legitimate Article V amendments. Ackerman has
long been among our profession’s most eloquent expositors of that view. Part of
the work of a good constitutional law scholar is to be a kind of legal
sociologist, one who spends enough time interacting with the law to develop a sense
of what those central texts actually are and to be able to convey that sense to
the world and to her students. She must seek to understand not just what West Coast Hotel v. Parrish and NLRB v. Jones & Laughlin Steel and Brown v. Board of Education say but also
what they mean. This is an
interpretive question that requires synthesis with the meaning of other cases, statutes,
and political and cultural moments.
The question that puzzles me, and
that I do not think Ackerman adequately answers in We the People Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution, is who
controls canon formation. Canon interpretation is the domain of judges,
lawyers, and legal scholars, who are trained in decoding legal texts. As noted
above, canon identification is also
essentially constitutional lawyers’ work, though it might be supplemented by
the insights of political scientists. But canon formation is another thing entirely. Ackerman’s book is a
provocation to canonize the Civil Rights Act, the Voting Rights Act, and the
Fair Housing Act, but a provocation to whom? Scholars can use the analytic
tools that Ackerman has provided to verify that these landmark statutes have been
subject to Ackerman’s identified stages of signaling, proposing, triggering,
elaborating, ratifying, and consolidating. But those criteria are not a
description of what has been canonized—or else there would be no need to urge a
new canon. The stages are rather a set of normative criteria for what Ackerman
believes should be canonized. And
this is something over which scholars—and certainly any particular group of scholars—have
incomplete control, if any.
Canons do not arise through
nomination but rather through use. A notable feature of canonical texts is that
they serve as resources across the ideological spectrum. Opponents of a
particular reading of the Constitution tend to argue not that the Constitution
is not law but that its proper interpretation requires a particular favored
outcome. Likewise with Brown, Ackerman is right that its ratification by opponents of a new
political-legal order is vital to canonicity. But canonical texts are not
merely tolerated; they are weaponized. Brown
is what it is because conservatives as well as liberals argue that its proper
interpretation favors their particular favored outcomes, as in the affirmative
action debate. So too, inversely, with “anticanonical” texts like Dred Scott v. Sandford and Lochner v. New York. Both conservatives
and liberals argue that the proper interpretation of these cases—whether for or
against originalism or judicial activism or whathaveyou—support the modern
adjudicative outcomes they favor.
It is tempting to assume that we
choose a favored (or disfavored) text for canonicity (or anticanonicity), and
then, once chosen, it becomes a resource in constitutional argument. But the
chain of causation may run in the opposite direction. The cases, events, and
political moments that prove canonical are the ones whose rhetorical use has
become the most ecumenical. The fact that a text is used across ideologies is a
key to its durability. For example, the canonization of the New Deal settlement
did not occur, as Ackerman argues, because of the superprecedents of the
Roosevelt Justices. It occurred, rather, because the substantive due process
revolution of the 1960s and 1970s gave conservatives an opening to use those
precedents against liberals. And so Lochner
endures as part of the anticanon, and West
Coast Hotel endures as part of the canon. Justice Harlan’s dissent in Plessy v. Ferguson is part of the canon
not just because of Brown and the
civil rights revolution but because the debates over affirmative action enabled
Harlan’s opinion to be refashioned in favor of an anti-classification
principle. Those texts that movement players and their legal fellow travelers
across the political spectrum have not been able to tap for their purposes
remain (like the Voting Rights Act) constantly vulnerable to repudiation by
future generations.
The texts that become and remain central to constitutional interpretive
discourse are not the ones whose meaning may be forever specified in advance,
as Ackerman has worked so hard to do in identifying his “anti-humiliation”
principle. Rather, the canonical texts, the ones that endure, are the ones
whose meaning is so indefinite that they are worth arguing about. Parents Involved in Community Schools v.
Seattle School District No. 1, in which the Supreme Court invalidated
voluntary school integration plans based on its reading of Brown, is curiously absent from Ackerman’s book, and it makes the
point. Destabilizing the meaning of foundational political and legal precedents
is the surest path to making them immortal.
The civil rights revolution—and a
revolution it was—has been a vital aspect of American political development.
But canons are, by definition, part of a culture. When we speak of a
constitutional law canon, the relevant culture is a culture of legal argument. Participants
in a culture of argument appropriate the resources they need to persuade others
operating within the culture. The civil rights revolution will be canonized if
and only if it needs to be. Jamal Greene is a Professor of Law at Columbia Law School. He can be reached at jgreen5@law.columbia.edu.