E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Bruce Ackerman’s We
The People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution is a beautifully
written book full of historical interest. He provides what I think will be the
definitive discussion of how Everett Dirksen, the Senate minority leader, made
his support of legislation against employment discrimination contingent on
eliminating the administrative structure to which anti-New Deal Republicans had
long objected. And the book also offers much legal insight,
particularly about the different enforcement mechanisms chosen to enforce civil
rights in the different social spheres of schools, housing, and employment.
But, despite its excellence as history and positive analysis,
in my view the book ultimately does not succeed as normative constitutional
theory. It does not show that the Civil
Rights era of the 1960s changed our fundamental law in a way that binds us
today. In this brief response, I begin with general
objections to Professor Ackerman’s constitutional moments theory. I then observe that the constitutional moment
of the Civil Rights revolution is not as persuasive on its own terms as the
constitutional moment of the New Deal. And
finally I suggest that that Professor Ackerman’s use of this moment as a cudgel
to club Chief Justice John Roberts’ opinion in Shelby County v. Holder is not
warranted.
Professor Ackerman’s constitutional moments theory is a bold
and fascinating effort to invent a framework for creating higher quality norms,
whose very quality then justifies preferring them when they conflict with
subsequent legislation—the norms of ordinary politics. Through heightened deliberation and consensus of such
moments Professor Ackerman hopes to capture some of the virtues of Article V. But a constitutional moment fails to offer
the certainty and indicia of quality conferred by the amendment process. For
instance, a basic requirement of higher lawmaking is that people know they are
engaged in it. But Professor Ackerman’s process for constitutional moments—that
politicians signal their support for a proposal, gain support in a first
election and then pass the proposal into law—does not tell the people that this
process is changing the Constitution. Indeed, since high school civics teaches that
the Constitution can be changed only through Article V and Professor Ackerman’s
idea is so original, this new method is likely to have completely escaped them.
Moreover, another difference between a
constitutional moment and an amendment is that the latter generates a new
constitutional text. But a constitutional
moment depends on a series of statutes that are embedded in their own
circumstances and judicial opinions that pass on the constitutionality of these
specific statutes. It is unclear why this moment should have
binding force equivalent to the Constitution when circumstances change and the
Court must determine the constitutionality of new statutes.
I have not been persuaded that American people endorsed a
change to the Constitution in the New Deal, as Professor Ackerman previously
argued. But it is more plausible than they endorsed a
constitutional change in that era than in the 1960s. First,
in the New Deal context, there were substantial complaints that the Court had
incorrectly curbed the power of the federal government. Extraordinary constitutional action might
have at least been seen by the public as a necessary corrective. Here the Warren
Court was not perceived by the public as an obstacle to civil rights. Indeed,
if anything, it was seen as in the vanguard. Second, political scientists have shown that
economic issues, like those in the New Deal, are generally the most important
to voters. While civil rights were of course important issues in the 1960s, I
would have thought that Professor Ackerman might have provided more evidence of their salience compared to
usual pocketbook issues that are generally thought to move voters.
Finally, I do not
think Professor Ackerman’s theory undermines the result or much of the analysis
in Shelby County. That is not to say
this opinion is right. And indeed he raises some useful questions about the
equal sovereignty doctrine on which Chief Justice Roberts in part relies—doubts
I do not have the space to explore here. But I think criticisms of this
doctrine could be made irrespective of the civil rights history of the 1960s he
presents. This history is of limited
relevance because the legislation of that time was passed against the background
of that time—of Jim Crow, of substantial racial violence, and of massive denial
of voting rights. Thus, it is not obvious to me why the American people’s
endorsement, if endorsement it was, of the Voting Right Act of 1965 was not
also embedded in the circumstances of the time.
And changed
circumstances are of relevance to Shelby, because the gravamen of the complaint
there is that Congress took a formula for preclearance that made sense in the
1960s and applied it without any concern for rational fit today, although times
had changed so much that one appellate court judge observed that turnouts among
African Americans were higher in the areas subject to preclearance than those
that were not. That is the reason that one can argue that preclearance
provision of the Voting Rights Act legislation of 1965 was wholly “appropriate”
within the meaning of section 2 of the Fifteenth Amendment while preclearance
provision of the Voting Rights Act of 2006 was not appropriate.
Professor Ackerman’s book, as fine as it is, does underscore
the problems with his theory of constitutional moments as a replacement for the
Article V amendment process. Article V produces a text whose meaning can be
applied to a changing world. A
constitutional moment does not have the same indicia of quality of the Article
V amendment process and provides no such definite criteria for future
application. As such, a moment lacks
the both the generative and normative force of a constitutional text. John McGinnis is the George C. Dix Professor in Constitutional Law at Northwestern University Law School. He can be reached at j-mcginnis@law.northwestern.edu.