E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
RutiTeitel, Straus
Fellow, NYU Law School (2012-2013); Ernst
C.Stiefel Prof of Comparative Law, NY
Law School
In general, in international
law, the distinction between the state of war and the state of peace is
becoming less relevant, or at least less determinative of the applicable
legal norms. This produces new challenges of interpretation and new
trade offs in the relation between law and politics.
The following are three illustrations of what has been happening.
1. First is the question of when does international criminal justice come into
the picture? At Nuremberg, international criminal responsibility was conceived as
fundamentally part of ius post bellum, something that occurs at the end of
hostilities.In a way, it took the place
of the kind of collective punishment that became questionable in the wake of
the Versaille Treaty.
Today international criminal
justice has a transformed functionality, coming into play during
conflict, before the peace, and even ex ante (the case of Libya, where
referrals to the ICC preceded military intervention in the conflict);
indeed it is used as means of regulating conflict itself. We don't need
to know whether conflict has ended.
This began with the
Balkans war where the International Criminal Tribunal for the former
Yugoslavia (ICTY) was created during the conflict by the Security
Council and where its jurisdiction to create a tribunal was its
peacemaking powers under the UN Charter chapter 7, and where the very
stated aim of the law is to regulate the conflict and to restore the
peace. Since then this has been reiterated in the ICC Statute.
The
introduction of international criminal law during conflict raises the
peace versus justice dilemma. What if the prospect of criminal justice
intensifies the conflict or makes peace negotiations more difficult
(e.g. Quaddaffi in Libya?)? The flip side is the politicization of law,
where
criminal prosecutions or the threat of them is used to achieve specific
strategic political objectives such as may well have been the case vis
avis Milosevic’s indictment at the time of the Dayton negotiations.
The
second illustration is that it is now rather well established that
international human rights law does not apply only in peacetime.
Continue reading below the fold.
Here
consider the treatment of this matter by the International Court of
Justice (ICJ) in its advisory opinion on the security fence between
Israel and the territories; whether and which norms -- human rights or
humanitarian law -- apply cannot be determined simply on the basis of
whether there is peace or war, and if war, internal or international
conflict. Obviously, the determination of the existence of a state of
war is still important to how these norms or regimes interact, and
whether humanitarian law trumps as a lex specialis (for example
permitting the targeting of combatants, which would deviate from the
basic norms of human rights).
Hence in the language of the ICJ, it asserted in that
case, “In the Court’s consideration of whether or not the construction of the
wall is contrary to international law, the Court determines the rules and principles
of international law which are relevant to the question posed by the General
Assembly. The Court begins by citing, with reference to Article 2,
paragraph 4, of the United Nations Charter and to General Assembly resolution 2625 (XXV),
the principles of the prohibition of the threat or use of force and the
illegality of any territorial acquisition by such means, as reflected in
customary international law. It further cites the principle of self‑determination
of peoples, as enshrined in the Charter and reaffirmed by
resolution 2625 (XXV). As regards international humanitarian
law, the Court refers to the provisions of the Hague Regulation of 1907, which
have become part of customary law, as well as the Fourth Geneva Convention
relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons in Time of War of 1949,
applicable in those Palestinian territories which before the armed conflict of
1967 lay to the east of the 1949 Armistice demarcation line (or “Green
Line”) and were occupied by Israel during that conflict.” The Court
further notes that certain human rights instruments (International Covenant on
Civil and Political Rights, International Covenant on Economic, Social and
Cultural Rights and the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child)
are applicable in the Occupied Palestinian Territory.According to the ICJ, “the protection offered by Human Rights
conventions does not cease in case ofArmed conflict….”
While there
are pros and cons of the overlapping orders, indeed, it is not always clear
that applying international human rights law results in a more protective
standard -- because many international human rights are derogable and involve
considerations of other countervailing social interests.But the bigger point for our purposes is that
the line between war and peace which used to be the defining factor and predicate
for the choice of legal order, is no longer the critical divide; now given
judicialization of conflict, there is more overlapping legal protection.
Particularly to insure gap-filling in a number
of settings to assure a threshold of human security, indeed the shift is
elaborated upon in my new book,Humanity's Law.
Finally, a third and last illustration of the diminishing relevance of the
distinction between war and peace as the defining factor occasioning
individual legal responsibility under international law can now be seen in the
growing role of international criminal law within international law.
While in the past, e.g. Nuremberg, the
nexus to war was a critical dimension both as basis for jurisdiction
and for the substantive offense Now, international criminal responsibilityis no longer measured in terms of war crimes: A range of crimes such as “crimes
against humanity” don't presuppose waging of armed conflict, nor a nexus to war.Starting with the post-cold war conflict in
Yugoslavia, crimes against humanity are applicable whether international or
internal armed conflict.
Now, the nexus has been further diluted as can be seen in
the permanent ICC Rome system, what triggers international criminal
responsibility can be triggered in peacetime -- enmeshing international criminal
law in more domestic situations. For
example, “crimes against humanity” at Article 5 now include a number of offenses associated
with peacetime repression and discrimination, so long as there is a “widespread or systematic attack directed
against any civilian population, with knowledge of the attack,”e.g. apartheid, forced disappearances, and
which nevertheless, a matter for individualized criminal responsibility under
international law.
So for example, post-election violence in Kenya became the
subject of International Criminal Court supervision. What this means is that
international criminal law is becoming more and more enmeshed in more
situations of violence with consequences for potential conflict of laws as well
as conflict over ways to approach conflict resolution: e.g., transitional
justice, raising dilemmas of peace versus justice, i.e. whether prosecutions
should take precedence over peace.
In sum, these are just some illustrations of the destabilization of the war and
peace divide within international law.The interesting
question of why this is happening lies at the heart of Mary's book addressing
the changing nature of war and its political functions.
From my standpoint, the relevant question today is do we need to be rethinking
the relationship between war and peace -- the historical basis for this
importance which goes back to Hobbes;Or,
instead, ought we recognize that the war
/peace divide has become relativized in regards to other determinations
relating the evolving mix of normative goals at issue, including human security.The question for the future is whether there
can really be any re-establishment of a stable understanding of war and peace;
and even if we had it -- it would hardly be determinant of the mix of legal norms
and the evolving nature of security relevant today.