E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Pope
Benedict XVI recently issued two important messages, one on the occasion of
Christmas and the other in celebration of World Peace Day. Both messages concentrated on the serious
threats “to justice and peace” confronting society in the twenty-first century,
including, most prominently, the threat of same-sex marriage.
The Pope warned that, although
lamentable in and of itself, the spread of same-sex marriage was symptomatic of
a deeper “crisis” in the modern world: namely, the dissolution of traditional
sex roles and the rise of feminist ideology. Before there was same-sex marriage, the Pope asserted,
there was Simone de Beauvoir, who paved the way for same-sex marriage by
suggesting that sex roles are a product of culture, rather than nature, and
that one’s life path ought not to be determined by his or her biological sex. The Pope called on people of all faiths to
resist this feminist “attack” on traditional sex and family roles, and to pursue
social policies that reflect and reinforce “gender complementarity,” in
marriage and all other walks of life.
The Pope
may not have been aware, when he issued these messages, that he was taking
sides in longstanding debate among legal scholars and gay rights advocates
about whether discrimination against gays and lesbians should be understood as
a form of sex discrimination. But he
was. Ironically, the Pope’s position in
this debate aligns him most closely with feminist scholars, who have argued that
much of the disapprobation of homosexuality is a
reaction to the way in which it violates gender norms, and that opposition to
same-sex marriage is fueled in significant part by a desire to preserve traditional
conceptions of men’s and women’s roles.
If courts
were to accept the argument that discrimination against gays and
lesbians is a form of sex discrimination, they would almost certainly find such
discrimination unconstitutional. Sex
discrimination is subject to heightened scrutiny, and sex-based equal
protection law is particularly skeptical of state action that reflects and
reinforces stereotyped conceptions of sex and family roles. But courts have not accepted this
argument. They have almost uniformly
rejected it. Even courts that have sided
with gay couples in marriage cases have almost all agreed with the California
Supreme Court “that discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation cannot
appropriately be viewed as a subset of, or subsumed within, discrimination on
the basis of sex.” The notion that the
sex classification in marriage has to do with preservation of traditional
gender norms garners support in some high places—but in court, it’s been a pretty
clear loser.
I think,
however, that all of the attention devoted to debating whether orientation-based
discrimination is a form of sex discrimination has obscured a different and
increasingly important relationship between these two forms of discrimination. Although courts have rejected the argument
that discrimination against gays and lesbians is sex discrimination, they have increasingly borrowed—and
adapted—constitutional doctrine developed in the context of sex-based equal
protection law to explain why discrimination against sexual minorities violates
the Fourteenth Amendment.
Constitutional sex discrimination
law rests on an anti-stereotyping principle, which bars the state acting in
ways that reflect and reinforce traditional conceptions of men’s and women’s
sex and family roles. Courts have
rejected the argument that discrimination against gays and lesbians runs afoul
of this principle. But in recent years,
courts have begun to hold that orientation discrimination reflects and
reinforces a related set of stereotypes about sexual minorities, also centering
on children and families: namely, that they are sexual perverts, that they have
no place in, or have a deleterious effect on, family life, and that they
present a threat to the nation’s children, through predation, recruitment, or
role-modeling.
Although these stereotypes are not
the same as those targeted by sex-based equal protection law, they are
frequently complementary; indeed, many of the threats gays and lesbians have
historically been understood to pose to children have to do with the proper
performance of gender. Thus, although
courts have resisted the notion that discrimination against gays and lesbians is discrimination on the basis of sex,
orientation-based equal protection law is developing in a way that is far more
symbiotic with sex-based equal protection law than courts’ near-universal
rejection of the sex discrimination argument for gay rights would suggest. Courts have begun to develop, in the context
of sexual orientation law, an anti-stereotyping doctrine that is closely akin
to the anti-stereotyping doctrine in the context of sex—but that takes aim at a
different set of stereotypes.
I don’t
have space in this post to trace the emergence of this new anti-stereotyping
doctrine or to demonstrate the growing role it plays in many areas of gay
rights law. Nor do I have space to
discuss all of its implications for current litigation, particularly same-sex marriage
litigation. But I want to mention one
implication—and it has to do with how we think about the marriage cases. There is a longstanding debate in the gay
rights movement between those who supported the prioritization of marriage and
those who feared it would further cement the notion that marriage is special—that
it tells us who is worthy of dignity and who is not, that it confers moral
legitimacy on relationships and families that otherwise lack this quality, and
that its participants are rightly entitled to a host of government benefits of
which the unmarried are deprived. The
growing prominence of the anti-stereotyping principle in gay rights law is
important because it suggests that gays and lesbians are winning marriage
rights not because marriage is special, but because it is not. Courts have grown increasingly skeptical of
the exclusion of gays and lesbians from marriage not because marriage is
unique, but because—like discrimination in the context of the military,
adoption, child custody, and employment—policies and practices that once seemed
natural and innocuous now seem to perpetuate stereotypes about sexual
minorities in constitutionally illicit ways.
In invalidating exclusionary marriage laws, courts have begun to recognize
not only gays’ and lesbians’ right to equality, but also their right to a
certain kind of liberty: the right to be free from state action based on
outmoded stereotypes and to shape their lives according to their “own
conception of [their] spiritual imperatives and . . . place in society.” (Planned
Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 852 (1992)).
Cary Franklin is Assistant Professor of Law at the University of Texas at Austin. You can reach her by email at cfranklin at law.utexas.edu