Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts War Powers, Guns, and Spitzer's Complaint (with a note on original meaning)
|
Sunday, September 28, 2008
War Powers, Guns, and Spitzer's Complaint (with a note on original meaning)
Stephen Griffin This semester I’m teaching “Foreign Affairs and the Constitution” (from the Bradley-Goldsmith casebook) after a long hiatus. I’ve been meaning to blog about some of the issues I’m covering, especially war powers. But in this post I’ll also look at a 2008 book by political scientist Robert Spitzer, Saving the Constitution from Lawyers: How Legal Training and Law Reviews Distort Constitutional Meaning. I couldn’t resist buying a book with that title and it is worth noting it comes with strong endorsements from prominent historians and political scientists who are apparently fed up with the law reviews. This is a long post and I don't mean to break up the discussion as the biggest financial rescue in U.S. history goes forward. So the rest is after the jump. Spitzer develops two well-supported indictments of legal scholarship. First, much of it is not scholarship in search of the truth but lawyering, clever brief writing in the wrong forum. Second, much of it is published in student-run law reviews as opposed to peer-reviewed journals and that leads to bad habits and poor quality control (note some law journals are peer reviewed). In the heart of the book, he offers three examples of poor quality constitutional scholarship, as run by law professors: the line item veto, presidential commander in chief powers, and gun control. Spitzer has previously published on all three topics and apparently feels his scholarship, and that of other political scientists, including some giants like Edward Corwin, has been slighted in the law reviews. To be fair, that’s not the main focus of his critique. An undercurrent in the book is his dismay at some of the questionable constitutional interpretations put forward by the Bush administration, particularly those advanced by John Yoo in the area of presidential war powers. Spitzer clearly believes that the fact that these ideas were first advanced in law reviews gave Yoo and his theories a credibility in the administration that was unwarranted. Spitzer does not deny that law reviews publish a great deal of first-rate scholarship. He contends, “the central problem is not that there is no limit to superb writing and analysis but rather that there is no floor to dreadful writing and analysis.” He thinks peer review might reduce this problem, but offering solutions is not his main focus (they are not likely to be adopted). Rather, he tries to illustrate the effects of poor analysis on the quality of constitutional argument and to policies adopted by the executive and judicial branches. In other words, bad articles can have real-world effects. No one will deny that law reviews sometimes print bad articles with terrible arguments. Whether there is a clear advantage for peer reviewed journals in this respect might be doubted. Certainly Spitzer does not turn his critical gaze on political science journals in his quest for shoddy scholarship. He does argue that poor quality scholarship is less likely to be published in peer reviewed journals. But how to show this? I suppose he might have looked at citation counts of articles he thinks are bad. If poor work is cited favorably in law reviews, that would show the “hundred flowers bloom” approach of law schools is not self-correcting. But he would have to show the same thing doesn’t happen in political science journals. Spitzer makes some valid points. I can hardly disagree with his specific argument that law professors do not always distinguish carefully between advocacy lawyering and scholarship because I have made this argument myself (as have other lawprofs). Once we move to his examples, doubts arise. The first is the advocacy by a few commentators of the idea that the president already has an inherent line item veto without the need for a statute or constitutional amendment. This near-crackpot notion got some attention in the Bush I administration, but Spitzer does not show it was accepted uncritically in law reviews. It seems to have garnered attention through a fortuitous chain of circumstances and was soon forgotten. The second example is Yoo’s advocacy of presidential war powers and a broad interpretation of the CIC clause. That’s my focus below. The third example is gun control and here I fear Spitzer undermines his credibility by contending that the traditional “collective” approach to the Second Amendment has no serious scholarly challengers. Spitzer is horrified by the case that became DC v. Heller (the book was published before Heller was decided), regarding its rejection of decades of militia-based collective precedent as a sure sign of a judiciary that has run off the rails. I believe Mark Tushnet in a recent book concludes that the historical argument between these two points of view is close. Spitzer will have none of it, treating Heller as an outlier case that proves how shoddy scholarship can gain a foothold in the law reviews and then become the law against all the evidence. I don’t believe his presentation will convince many law professors who hold that the individualist interpretation is well grounded in original meaning. With respect to war powers, I think Spitzer is on to something, although the argument might not come out as clean and sharp as he would like. Let’s start by trying to extend Spitzer’s point about the differences between law reviews and peer-reviewed journals. Thinking also of dissertations, what does research and writing in the PhD disciplines have that legal scholarship lacks? Bearing in mind there are always exceptions, two standard elements come to mind: the literature review and the defense of methodology. Legal scholars can be so eager to demonstrate their bright new idea that they can forget to assess what has gone before. As many have noted, this leads to a staggering amount of argumentative repetition in law reviews and the reinvention of not a few wheels. And a lack of attention to methodology defense can lead to law professors claiming new insights when all they have done is an elaborate version of changing the subject. Both suggest legal scholars lack standards for writing articles when there has been past work in the field. This may be related to the reality that most law professors were never graduate students in the same sense as PhD candidates. When you are in law school, for the most part you are being trained to be a lawyer rather than a scholar. It seems likely that this would have some effects on legal scholarship. I’m going to illustrate these points by examining Yoo’s argument, as expressed in his book The Powers of War and Peace, that the president has the power under the Constitution to initiate war. I’ve argued in previous articles that we have to be careful how we use history to address contemporary constitutional questions. We must ensure we are asking a question of history that history can answer. One reason the debate over war powers has been so contentious is that it does appear we are asking a question that members of the founding generation literally considered: how should the nation go to war? There is a clear asymmetry in the evidence on this question. Those who see Congress as having the power to initiate war under the “declare war” clause have the support of a long chain of consistent statements extending from the Federal Convention through the ratification debates into the 1790s and beyond attesting to three points: 1) the power to initiate war must and does belong to Congress; 2) we must beware of the abuse of executive power with respect to war and 3) the power to initiate war was deliberately not given to the president, leaving aside defensive responses to sudden attacks. The acceptance of these propositions arguably poses serious practical problems as we try to operate the contemporary constitutional system. This is a matter for theories of constitutional change. However, as a matter of history, the record is very clear. So how have “pro-President” scholars like Yoo proceeded? Largely by constructing a series of historical what-ifs. What if members of the founding generation were greatly impressed by the division of authority in the British system of government? What if they sought to preserve the British balance in the U.S. Constitution? What if they believed as a matter of theory that foreign affairs powers were executive in nature? How would we then understand the allocation of war powers? As reviewers of Yoo’s book have noted, Yoo spends pages on life in the British empire while devoting comparatively little attention the actual course of debate at Philadelphia and in the state conventions. But even more important, what is notably lacking from these what-ifs is any endorsement of the fundamental concept of the survival of the British system by any member of the founding generation during the debates over the Constitution. In other words, the advantage of the pro-Congress side is that their arguments are actually endorsed by the framers. Yoo tends to rely on what the framers “must have” thought as opposed to what they actually said. So here’s my promised point about the “new originalism” of original meaning that I wrote about last year at this time in “Rebooting Originalism.” There is a distinct tendency in the presidential power literature to embrace an implication of the turn to original meaning by emphasizing word choice (“declare”) and context (we’re all familiar with Locke, Blackstone and the British empire) over what actually took place in the process of constitution writing (the framers reordered what they learned from Britain and came up with new ideas). I’m not saying any prominent advocate of the theory of original meaning endorses this specifically. The logic of the theory demands we vacuum up meanings no matter where they occur. But that’s the problem! In actual practice in the area of presidential power, original meaning theory has tended to validate readings of the Constitution that either did not actually occur to anyone who wrote and ratified the document, or were outliers. How could this happen, you say? Remember advocates of original meaning don’t like looking for subjective intent (how the notables actually thought). They elevate “objective” evidence of original meaning over subjective intent. But, as Woody Allen once remarked, “Objectivity is subjective” (maybe it was the reverse – see Love and Death). This means we can look for evidence of meaning anywhere in the eighteenth century (or earlier) regardless of how closely it is connected with the debates that led to the Constitution’s adoption. The search for “objective” evidence of meaning allows the subjectivity of the scholar to do the picking and choosing among possible worlds of meaning. And that’s what we get – possible worlds of meaning, not analysis confined to the actual world in which the Constitution was adopted. Now back to Yoo. The relevance of Yoo for Spitzer’s argument is that anyone previously familiar with the war powers debate who has read through the records of the Federal Convention, the ratification debates, and the relevant historical commentary would spot all of this immediately. If Yoo’s argument had been peer reviewed before appearing in the law reviews, he would have had to respond to some hard questions. At a minimum, he would have had to address the historical evidence point for point. Instead, once his views were published, they could be cited (including by himself when in government) and he was off to the races. What’s more, once Yoo’s arguments were out there, he and other pro-presidential scholars could use their publication as proof that reasonable persons disagree over the status of the historical evidence. The use of this particular argument by advocates of an inherent presidential line item veto drives Spitzer up the wall. They seemed to argue: (1) there is some evidence in favor of an inherent veto, while (2) there is overwhelming evidence against, so (3) reasonable minds can differ, and thus (4) it is legitimate for a president to pick the position of the group he prefers. I think everyone can see that this sort of mega-bootstrapping is sophistry at best. But doesn’t it sound familiar? It should! Roughly the same pattern of argument has been used by the Bush administration multiple times in reasoning about presidential power in the context of the torture and NSA controversies. It’s a sort of “heads I win” (if you buy my argument), “tails you lose” (if you don’t we use the avoidance canon and I still win) approach that the administration used to spin the press that the arguments were at least equally balanced. Spitzer somewhat plaintively compares this to the case of creationism and points out, soundly I think, that to ask whether people are differing is the wrong question. He pleads for “objective analysis” and “empirical research” that must be based on “a careful weighing of legal, historical, and political evidence.” But is that truly what legal scholarship is interested in? If so, it is plain that the method of publication cuts against realizing these goals. And as we have seen with the Bush administration, this has real-world consequences. Neal Katyal has gone on record in The New Republic (reviewing Goldsmith’s book The Terror Presidency) wondering if something hasn’t gotten out of hand given that Yoo’s reputation for publishing “innovative” and “pathbreaking” law review articles might have helped him get a job with the administration. The case of Yoo may have highlighted the loss of methodological consensus in constitutional law. Would things be better if conlawprofs paid more attention to political science scholarship? I’m a fan of political science, so I would say yes, but you would see conlawprofs dragging their feet somewhat if the query became one of paying attention to what political scientists say about constitutional meaning. There would be questions about how a group composed largely of non-lawyers could have relatively better insights into the Constitution. Talking about peer review and the values of scholarship doesn’t get us anywhere because there is a disconnect in what the two camps write about. Political scientists gave up writing about the Court’s stream of decisions a long time ago. No contemporary political scientist has the doctrinal-treatise respect among lawprofs that Corwin once did because political scientists don’t earn any professional points for describing what the Supreme Court has done with respect to doctrine, wondering about what the Court is likely to do next, or, still less likely, trying to help the Court decide the next case. Political scientists aren’t interested in these topics, but lawyer-lawprofs are. And I’m sure we’ll stay interested. However, as I’ve tried to convey in this post, this fundamentally non-scholarly orientation leaves some very difficult questions open about the quality of legal “scholarship." Posted 9:58 PM by Stephen Griffin [link]
Comments:
This is an extremely interesting post, and I fundamentally agree with what Steve writes. I forbear from commenting on Spitzer's Second Amendment arguments, since I'm one of the people he most vehemently attacks.
But I do want to issue a caveat against labeling advocates of the "inherent line-item veto" position as "crackpots." I'm on record, again and again, as bewailing the presidential policy-based veto, which I believe to be far more counter-majoritarian than judicial review. BUT I think that the Constitution-based veto is not only clearly supported by the constitutional text, but also a quite good idea from the perspective of first-order constitutional design. There's no problem if Congress were limited, as are many state legislatures, by "single-subject" rules; this would allow presidents fairly easily to veto legislation that contained presumptively unconstitutional sections. But, of course, much, if not most, modern legislation is "omnibus," and the president can't be expected to veto an entire bill, which may have extremely important implications for national defense, social welfare, etc., in order to get at a particular unconstitutional aspect. Thus the "functionalist" argument for an "inherent line-item-veto" authority, which would apply only to omnibus legislation and would require that the President accompany the veto with an explanation as to why the section vetoed is unconstitutional and not only unwise policy. Why is this a "crackpot" argument? There's no support for it in historical materials because it is almost certain that the Founders had no contemplation of "omnibus" legislation. Unless one is an originalist of a certain stripe, why should it be important, let alone dispositive, that the historical materials don't negate an argument that was never made because no one imagined its potential need?
Oh man. Interesting indeed, but where to even start?
I guess mine is one of the more unique perspectives: a layman who has literally spent seven full years opposing the Bush administration's detainee policies, including a good bit of arguing with law professors about the legal issues. A good bit of reading law review articles too, including everything of Yoo's I could get my hands on plus virtually all of the major briefs filed by DOJ in the habeas cases. And I'm not an academic, I'm a mostly self-educated polymath who started studying history, politics, and war when I was 10, philosophy at 12, became a tournament chess-player at 16, switched to bridge at 18, and went to work as a computer programmer at 21 (turned out that being a chess and bridge expert was the near equivalent of a masters in computer science) and spent nearly 30 years doing it for a living. So you ask: "There would be questions about how a group composed largely of non-lawyers could have relatively better insights into the Constitution." Hmmm... By looking more at forests and less at trees? By worrying less about rhetoric and more about logic? Here's a recent example that's a perfect illustration: HERE is an opposition brief the government filed in one of the detainee cases, stating one of their key arguments post-Boumediene at 2-8. HERE is an opinion by Judge Hogan that pretty much adopts that argument hook, line, and sinker behind the weak caveat that the detainees didn't argue that 28 USC 2241(e)(2) was unconstitutional (finessing / ignoring the fact that Boumediene stated flat-out that it was an unconstitutional suspension of habeas in a typical display of legal hocus pocus). I've been doing my best to debunk this sort of thing for nearly six years now, and I'd be very interested to hear what you, Sandy, and Marty think about this particular argument. (Marty posted a quick comment on SCOTUSblog as I recall). I believe it might shed some light on the topic here. And HERE is what I think about it.
It seems to me that the omnibus bill is the natural Congressional response to non-constitutional grounds for the Presidential veto. It shifts the balance of power a bit back in the direction of Congress.
I think it would be pretty hard to preclude Presidents from using the veto for policy reasons. I'd be worried that any such restriction would lead to make-weight Constitutional arguments which would, in the long run, debase the legal system. There are ways around this, I suppose. For example, a veto could go straight to the Supreme Court for review on Constitutional grounds. If rejected, the law would stand notwithstanding the veto. There are three problems with this. First, the sheer volume of work for the Court might overwhelm it. Second, the Convention specifically considered and rejected the involvement of the Court in the veto power. Third, the very first Court refused to give advisory opinions, a generally good policy which the Court has maintained until this day. I'd be inclined to approach the problem from two angles. First, I'd reduce the veto override to 60 votes because I think the modern Presidency has become too powerful. Second, I'd give the President a line-item veto on all spending bills, but the override there would be 55 votes.
Scientists of various kinds like to criticize legal scholarship because of lack of peer review, or peer review by mere law students. If peer review really worked then they might have an argument, but peer review is not all its cracked up to be. Such eminent peer reviewed journals as the NEJM and JAMA are routinely gamed by pharmaceutical companies, pseudo-academics and academics. There is a renowned shortage of competent peer-reviewers in many fields; and there is an equally renowned bias in peer review for the views of the peer reviewers. Bogus peer review is another problem. The sociology of the sciences suggests the obsession with objectivity, which is the source of the perceived value of peer review, is a result of interdisciplinary incommensurability. Different disciplines need a way to communicate with each other, and peer review serves to license the quality of the unfamiliar work. Arguably because the context is lawyers talking to lawyers, law reviews work quite well within the legal profession. That is, lawyers who read law reviews, and who do research in law reviews, are quite competent to distinguish the good from the bad. Now, the question is whether those same trust levels can be imputed outward from the law into qualitative political science and sociology, and legal philosophy. I think there is no reason to think law review articles need peer review for readers from those disciplines. Anyone who plows through hundreds of law review articles a year, as I assume most legal researchers from any discipline do, learns the good from the bad. They learn that excellent law professors publish in law reviews from third and fourth tier schools from time to time, and to not disregard an article just because it is not published in a journal from a top-ten school. And so. Peer review complaints are proxies for political bias and disagreement. Our articles rarely depend heavily on knowledge of arcane systems of objectivity (such as mathematics); rather we are supposed to be masters of reason, masters of argument. Anyone trained to reason should be able to judge a law review article on its face, and perhaps from review of the sources cited in a few footnotes if there are red flags. Footnotes … well, they are taken to a strange extreme in the law since there lies our claim to objectivity and reliability – our method of establishing it.
philiatros:
Peer review is not the principal check on scientific misconduct. It's in part a way for the papers to be focused, criticised (and not necessarily in a bad way) and improved (I've been on both ends). The real check on scientific misconduct is full description and replication (as well as other related studies that may lead to differing interpretations). Peer review can bring to the fore other studies that, taken in conjunction with the work in question, might lead to differing conclusions or alternative explanations. But papers can and do contradict others (and go against the grain of the "commonly accepted knowledge"); this is not sufficient reason for refusal to publish, but rather is the way science works. Cheers,
Stephen,
I hope that this is not too far off topic. I just started to read "Educating Lawyers Now and Then, An Essay Comparing the 2007 and 1914 Carnegie Foundation Reports on Legal Education" by James R. Maxeiner. After reading the introduction, I jumped to the reprint of the 1914 report by Josef Redlich that grabbed my interest because of a research project of mine on the study of law outside of law schools. But I think this may tie into your post as it relates to legal academic writings. So perhaps the manner of educating lawyers - including for practice and for teaching - should be addressed up front as perhaps part of the problem.
Wishing to be friends is quick work, but friendship is a slow ripening fruit.
Post a Comment
Agen Judi Online Terpercaya
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |