Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Text, Principle, and Living Constitutionalism
|
Tuesday, May 20, 2008
Text, Principle, and Living Constitutionalism
JB In response to Steve's very interesting post about living constitutionalism and the New Deal, let me offer a few points that may help resolve some problems he has about how easy it is to reconcile my method of text and principle with the living constitutionalism that arises from the New Deal. The first point is that Mitch Berman, Ronald Dworkin and Akhil Amar have convinced me, in their various ways, that principles underlying the constitutional text, as constitutional constructions, do not have to "have a pedigree in historical evidence from the time of the adoption of the text." That is, as long as original (semantic) meaning is preserved, new principles may be associated with the Constitution over time if they are constructions that the text can bear. The reason is simple: Arguments from structural principles may invoke principles that become clear only after the government has been in operation for some time. Structural principles may be derived from original expectations about the way the Constitution would work, but they also stem from the way the Constitution actually does work in practice over the years. If we said that new principles (which are constitutional constructions) can never be recognized, we couldn't explain much of our current practices of structural argument. These principles have to be consistent with the original meaning of the text, but they do not have to have been intended by anyone at the time the text was adopted. Of course, there are many principles that we do derive from the history of the adoption of the constitutional text. I have argued that these principles must be stated at the same level of generality as the text itself; this means that they are also likely to be indeterminate and require further implementation through constitutional construction (which will require invoking sub principles and sub sub principles). In particular, that means that we do not have to apply the class legislation principle underlying the Fourteenth Amendment in the same way that people in 1868 would have applied it. The same is true with the principles underlying the Due Process Clause. Steve is worried that, based on the expectations of people living in 1868, much redistributive legislation passed during the New Deal might be unconstitutional because it violates Reconstruction era conceptions of police powers and the boundaries of permissible state regulation. But central to my theory is the claim that we are not bound by the original expected application. Some redistributive programs-- in fact, many such programs-- could be viewed today as having a bona fide public purpose and thus not class legislation, even if people in 1868 would have regarded them as clearly beyond the scope of the police power. As Akhil Amar and Mike Curtis have pointed out, once you adopt the Sixteenth Amendment, which presupposes the power of the federal government to engage in progressive income taxation, you need to rethink what the class legislation principle means in the modern administrative and welfare state. Class legislation comes to be more about stigmatizing or subordinating government practices and less about adjustments of contract and property rights in the public interest. The application of the Fourteenth Amendment and its principles can change in light of changing circumstances, although the meaning of the terms in the text does not change. Third, you can make a similar point about changes in the scope of federal power that arose with the New Deal. Steve worries that the text of the commerce power (and other clauses) is not capacious enough to justify the modern administrative state. I disagree, and so did Roosevelt himself. The basic principles underlying the commerce power, and indeed, the entire set of enumerated powers in Article I, section 8, were well stated by James Wilson in the Pennsylvania ratifying convention in November of 1787: "Whatever object of government is confined, in its operation and effects, within the bounds of a particular state, should be considered as belonging to the government of that state; whatever object of government extends, in its operation or effects, beyond the bounds of a particular state, should be considered as belonging to the government of the United States." Wilson, in turn was simply restating the content of Resolution VI at the Philadelphia Convention, adopted on July 16, 1787, which stated the basic principle that Congress should have the power "to legislate in all cases for the general interests of the Union, and also in those to which the States are separately incompetent, or in which the harmony of the U. States may be interrupted by the exercise of individual Legislation." This general statement of purpose was converted by the Committee of Detail into the enumerated powers of Congress listed in Article I, section 8, including the commerce power. The scope of each of these enumerated powers, including the commerce power, may and should be read in light of those purposes. So stated, it becomes clear why Roosevelt could say in his public speeches that he didn't think that an amendment was necessary to justify the New Deal, and why nothing he sought was inconsistent with the text of the Constitution. As he put it in his September 17, 1937 Constitution Day address, "You will find no justification in any of the language of the Constitution for delay in the reforms which the mass of the American people now demand," and that "nearly every attempt to meet those demands for social and economic betterment has been jeopardized or actually forbidden by those who have sought to read into the Constitution language which the framers refused to write into the Constitution." The central question of federal power during the New Deal was whether new forms of legislation were now within Congress's enumerated powers because of changed understandings about the nature of the economy and social life. These changes in economic and social life changed expectations about what sorts of problems, in Wilson's words, "extend[ed], in [their] operation or effects, beyond the bounds of a particular state," or, in the words of the Philadelphia Convention, what kinds of problems had become those in which Congress might reasonably conclude that "the States are separately incompetent" to address. The New Deal was premised on the idea that the United States had become a fully integrated national economy with governance problems that routinely had spillover effects that individual states could not adequately manage by themselves. These were problems for which a comprehensive federal solution was necessary. The second claim made by New Dealers was that courts should defer to the reasonable judgment of Congress and the President (through administrative agencies) about when a national solution was necessary to deal with a problem for which the states "were separately incompetent," or when a problem of governance "extend[ed], in its operation or effects, beyond the bounds of a particular state." This was a claim of judicial deference in questions of economic and social legislation. Again, there is nothing in the original meaning of the text that forbids either construction, although, of course, one might prefer different constructions that would produce a much reduced federal power. Indeed, before the New Deal, people did construe the Constitution this way. But, as before, fidelity to original meaning does not bind us to these prior constructions, including the original expected application. In sum, Steve's concerns about whether the method of text and principle can handle the forms of living constitutionalism that came with the New Deal seem to me overstated. The theory can handle these changes. The real issue, it seems to me, is that the realm of possible constructions consistent with original meaning is very large, and most of the controversy in constitutional adjudication involves choosing one set of implementing constructions over another. This process of choosing successive constructions to deal with changing circumstances is the real work of living constitutionalism; as I have detailed in a previous series of posts, (One, Two, Three, Four, Five, Six , and Seven) why particular constructions get adopted at particular points in time is due to a complicated process of interaction between courts and the political branches. Posted 1:57 PM by JB [link]
Comments:
It is curious that an opponent of original intended application such as yourself would be quoting a single ratifier of the Constitution - James Wilson - to make your point. In fact, Mr. Wilson's view of governance (and that of FDR) - that the federal government may exercise any power not granted to the States - is contrary to Article I, Section 1 of the Constitution which states:
All legislative powers herein granted shall be vested in a Congress of the United States... The Constitution intentionally limited the federal government to enumerated powers. This is a base principle arising from the plain text of the Constitution which I would think that your principles arising from the text theory of interpretation should recognize. The New Dealers were looking for ways to escape the limitations of the Constitution and not to enforce them. Thus, their views are hardly those of impartial observers of the Constitution. The New Dealers could not change the meaning of the text of the Constitution simply because they had a different idea of how government should run than did the Founders. If this was the case, FDR could also have found pesky things like elections to be a relic of a bygone era and declare himself a dictator. Somehow, I doubt Sandy would think this to be a good idea. Nor could the New Dealers simply command the courts to ignore the text of the Constitution and defer to their idea of how government should operate. Indeed, each Justice of the Supreme Court swears an oath to "I will faithfully and impartially discharge and perform all the duties incumbent upon me as [a Justice of the Supreme Court] under the Constitution and laws of the United States.'' Professor Griffin is correct that any theory of interpretation which is faithful to the explicit structure limiting the Congress to enumerated powers and the text of those enumerated powers cannot justify much of the New Deal. The courts which eventually signed off on the New Deal violated their oaths and engaged in blatant living constitutionalism.
JB --
I have to take exception to your proposition that Resolution VI was morphed into enumerated powers by the Committee on Detail. After the Great Compromise provided for one house to be allocated equally among states, the degree of democracy in the Constitution was seriously reduced (and is the 1000 pound elephant given today's bi-coastal population). Thereafter, Madison moved from supporting a federal government of general powers and the right to "negative" state enactments to a federal government of enumerated powers with a legally enforceable supremacy clause. This was done on the convention floor, after consideration by the committee on unresolved issues, not in the committee on detail. I had always considered it somewhat ironic that the Federalist Society was so named, because its federalism agenda was really anti-federalist. However, I think it necessary to recognize three strains of anti- and pro-federalist sentiment -- a Patrick Henry strain of anti-federalists that believed that the best government was local, who became states' righters during the Jackson era and secessionists thereafter; a Hamilton/Adams strain of federalists, who had monarchical pro-British tendencies; and a Madison/Jefferson strain of federalists who saw the country as a trans-continental democracy. So the snobby U.Va. "Mr. Jefferson" types atacheded the federalist moniker to their localist vision of the republic.
Bart: "It is curious that an opponent of original intended application such as yourself would be quoting a single ratifier of the Constitution - James Wilson - to make your point."
That doesn't seem fair. Original expected application is obviously important evidence of original meaning. It's just defeasible evidence.
Original expected application is obviously important evidence of original meaning.
In this particular case, Prof. Balkin's example is much more than "mere" original expected application. Wilson was paraphrasing a resolution adopted by the Convention on July 17, 1787, and then again on July 26, that the national government was to have power "to legislate in all cases for the general interests of the Union, and also in those to which the States are separately incompetent, or in which the harmony of the U. States may be interrupted by the exercise of individual Legislation." Cite. Wilson was explaining the principle which the Commerce Clause was intended to effect. Text and principle.
mark:
The text of the Constitution and the principle of enumerated powers is contrary to this individual ratifier's idea of the scope of federal power. If anything, the use of Mr. Wilson demonstrates the hazards of attempting to ascertain the original intent of the parties to the Constitution by cherry picking individual commentary.
HD kaliteli porno izle ve boşal.
Post a Comment
Bayan porno izleme sitesi. Bedava ve ücretsiz porno izle size gelsin. Liseli kızların Bedava Porno ve Türbanlı ateşli hatunların sikiş filmlerini izle. Siyah karanlık odada porno yapan evli çift. harika Duvar Kağıtları bunlar tamamen ithal duvar kağıdı olanlar var 2013 Beyaz Eşya modeller Sizlere Güvenlik Sistemleri ayarliyoruz Arayin Hırdavat bulun Samsung Nokia İphone Cep telefonu alin. Super Led Tv keyfi
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |