Balkinization  

Thursday, March 06, 2025

Constitutional Symmetry: Symposium Response Part II

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization symposium on Zachary Price, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2024).

Zachary S. Price

This is my second post responding to participants in the symposium on my new book Constitutional Symmetry:  Judging in a Divided Republic.  I’ll respond here to the remaining four reviewers and then offer some closing thoughts.

Read more »

Wednesday, March 05, 2025

Constitutional Symmetry: Symposium Response Part I

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization symposium on Zachary Price, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2024).

Zachary S. Price

I am grateful to Jack Balkin for hosting this symposium on my new book Constitutional Symmetry:  Judging in a Divided Republic, and I am even more grateful to the participants for their thoughtful contributions.  Having a group I respect and admire so much engage with my work is a scholar’s dream, and I appreciate the time that participants took to prepare their reviews.  In this post, after summarizing the book’s overall argument, I will offer brief responses to the first three reviewers.  I’ll respond to the other four in a second post tomorrow.
Read more »

Friday, February 28, 2025

Not Recommended

Ian Ayres

 A few days ago I received the following email:

Dear Professor Ian Ayres,

It's Jesse from FlyingEdu Hong Kong. We mainly provide services for students who are applying for future study programs.

Some of them are of outstanding performance, but they will need the authorities' recommendation to accomplish the application process. In this case, we wish to connect you and our students. We would send you their CVs, arrange online communication to help you know them better, and you could choose to assign homework to help evaluate. In return for your assistance, handsome rewards would be given (about 10000usd/month). Also, the content of the recommendation letters can be further discussed with you.

Please feel free to reply or message me when you are available. Looking forward to further contact and cooperation with you.

Email:x@flyingedu.org

Regards,

Jesse

Senior Business Manager of FlyingEdu HongKong

Website:

http://www.flyingedu.org

Part of me was appalled by this concept. Paying substantial sums for recommendations gives the children of rich people yet another leg up. And might the recommendation fraudulently misinform the recipient? What’s next — paying for book blurbs? The whole endeavor seems super sketchy — including using a “.org” website at what screams out as a for-profit business.

Read more »

Thursday, February 27, 2025

A Thought about the Unitary Executive and the 22nd Amendment

Richard Primus

            A fair amount of the argument in favor of the unitary executive model of presidential power is rooted in an account of the Founding.  I am skeptical of important parts of that account.  But the point I want to raise here is about the impact, on theories of presidential power, of a later event in the making of constitutional law.  That later event is the adoption of the Twenty-Second Amendment, under which a twice-elected president cannot run for re-election.  The point I want to raise is about what an enactment like the Twenty-Second Amendment can tell us, not about any original vision of the presidency, but about the vision of the presidency that prevailed in 1951, when the Amendment was adopted.  The further question I want to raise goes like this: if the Constitution’s provisions about the presidency were partly written in the middle of the twentieth century, what role should the prevailing understanding of the presidency as it existed at that time play in an overall theory of presidential power?  The chief bearing of this question, for present purposes, is that it might induce skepticism about an important aspect of unitary executive theory: that is, the proposition that the president must be able to remove executive officers at will, and that Congress lacks the power to insulate executive-branch officials—or maybe even executive-branch personnel generally—from the presidential ax.

Unitary executive theory is heavily structural.  To be sure, it comes with a (contestable) reading of the text of Article II and various claims about the way the Founding generation understood executive power.  But in the form that has been most potent within the judiciary, unitary executive theory depends for its force on an idea about democratic accountability: that the personnel of the executive branch must be accountable to the president, who in turn is accountable to the electorate.  For the president to be held responsible for the actions of executive officials, the thinking goes, he must be able to fire executive-branch personnel who fail to carry out their duties in the way he thinks proper.  The public’s assurance that the president will for the most part exercise his authority over the executive branch prudently, and in the public interest, lies in the public’s ability to hold the president accountable at the polls. 

To be sure, a modicum of reality-checking would reveal that democratic elections are blunt mechanisms for holding executive-branch personnel to account.  Presidential elections turn on multiple factors, some of which would be beyond the control of presidents even if presidents were able to direct all executive-branch action with impeccable precision.  Given the size of the electorate, the infrequency of elections, and the dizzying array of reasons why people vote the way they do, the chances that any particular decision a president makes about firing or retaining a subordinate will play a significant role in a re-election campaign are rather small.  Still, the basic idea that elections are a mechanism of accountability has something to it.  And one of the chief reasons that presidents (and many other officials) are thought trustworthy to exercise the powers of office is that they can be turned out of office if they use those powers poorly.

The Twenty-Second Amendment puts a major dent in that idea.  It means that the President of the United States will frequently be electorally unaccountable.  If you cannot run for re-election, the voters cannot police your behavior by threatening to refuse to return you to office.  To be sure, presidents ineligible to run for re-election might have other incentives to stay popular with the electorate: popularity might help them get cooperation from Congress, and an unpopular president might damage his party’s electoral fortunes even after he is out of the game, and so on.  But it would be hard to say that the elimination of the straightforward electoral check makes no significant difference in the degree to which a president is democratically accountable.  And once we recognize that the Twenty-Second Amendment makes presidents less democratically accountable than they previously were, we should ask what assumptions about the presidency might have helped the Americans who supported that Amendment reach the view, all things considered, that it was safe to vest the considerable powers of the presidency in someone who be electorally unaccountable much of the time.

I make no strong claim about the answer.  But it is worth noting that the presidency the drafters and ratifiers of the Twenty-Second Amendment knew was not the presidency of unitary executive theory.  He was enormously powerful: the Leader of the Free World, with access to a (small but terrifying) stock of nuclear weaponry.  But he did not have unlimited freedom to direct the bureaucracy, or choose the personnel, of the modern administrative state.  A dozen years before Congress proposed the Twenty-Second Amendment, the Supreme Court decided Humphrey’s Executor v. United States, holding that Congress had the authority to constrain the president’s latitude to dismiss administrative commissioners and, more broadly, federal officials whose duties could be described as other than “purely executive.”  One year before proposing the Twenty-Second Amendment, Congress passed the Administrative Procedure Act, whose rules channel and constrain the exercises of bureaucratic power, including a great deal of power exercised by people appointed by or answerable to the president.  In short, the presidency that the framers and ratifiers of the Twenty-Second Amendment contemplated—and whose electoral accountability they were willing to compromise—was a president whose freedom of action was importantly constrainable by Congress, including through the mechanism of insulating federal officers from at-will removal.

I’m not claiming that the Twenty-Second Amendment would not have been adopted if the constitutional law of the mid-twentieth century had conformed to the unitary-executive model that later gained so many adherents.  How post-war Americans might or might not have thought differently about the presidency if this or that feature of the office had been different then is a question on which proof is essentially impossible.  In the age of totalitarian dictators, maybe the fear of a president-for-life would have been strong enough to inspire a constitutional term limit, and the concomitant loss of electoral accountability during a second term, even if the president had had the power that unitary executive theory would give him.  Or maybe, in that same age of totalitarian dictators, the successful movement for a constitutional amendment limiting presidential terms would also have been a successful movement for a constitutional amendment disestablishing a unitary-executive model of the presidency, had that model been operative at the time.  It’s impossible to know. 

But two propositions seem clear.  First, a theory of presidential power that rests in any significant part on ideas about what the Constitution-makers presumed about the office needs to take account of the presumptions that operated for the Constitution-makers of 1947-51 and not just those of 1787-88.  Second, the presidency of 1947-51 was not the presidency of unitary-executive theory.  Indeed, the Constitution-makers of 1947-51 restructured the office in a way that has meant that a great deal of the time, the president is not an officer for whom the mechanism of democratic accountability functions in the way that the theory standardly presumes.  (Or more precisely, the president is an officer for whom that mechanism, which never functions more than bluntly in the real world, does not even function as a matter of ideal theory.)  Perhaps that matters.


Tuesday, February 25, 2025

How Important Is Presidential Immunity?

Andrew Coan

When the Supreme Court decided Trump v. United States last July, critics warned of dire consequences for the U.S. constitutional order. Are those chickens now coming home to roost? Either way, might the decision pose another large and looming threat to the rule of law? These questions obviously require speculation, but I want to suggest four reasons for answering both in the negative. The argument below is exploratory, rather than definitive, and some of its elements are familiar. But I have not seen anyone pull the threads together in quite this way. Points 2 and 4 seem particularly under-appreciated. If the argument is correct, presidential immunity is largely a distraction. We have bigger constitutional problems to worry about. 

1. Most basically, it is easy to say that no one is or should be above the law. But it is quite complex to apply this principle to the official conduct of the President, who is plainly granted constitutional power to take actions that ordinary people are not. Congress can certainly regulate this power to some extent, including through criminal prohibition. But to what extent, precisely? Could Barack Obama have been prosecuted for ordering a drone strike on U.S. citizen Anwar al-Awlaki in Yemen? The answers are quite hazy as a matter of text, history, and pre-Trump precedent. This complexity was candidly acknowledged by special counsel Jack Smith’s lawyer Michael Dreeben in his briefs and oral argument. It also forms the foundation of Justice Barrett’s Trump concurrence, which as many commentators have noted, is much more persuasive than the Chief Justice’s majority opinion. In my view, Barrett fails to show that the conduct at issue in Trump exceeds Congress’s power to regulate the presidency. But she makes a very persuasive case that this is a complex question of overlapping constitutional powers, rather than a simple or one-sided question of bedrock principle as the dissents and many critics contend. 

2. There are strong reasons to doubt the practical importance of criminal prosecution as a check on the abuse of presidential power. Before Donald Trump, there had never been a single prosecution of this kind in U.S. history. Long-standing policy and the president’s control of the executive branch combine to foreclose any realistic possibility of a sitting president being prosecuted. And many practical and political considerations have always made the prospect of post-presidency prosecutions extremely remote and unlikely to succeed: 

  • the possibility that a president will be reelected or succeeded by a political ally, who quashes the investigation/prosecution or issues a pardon;
  • the possibility that a hostile successor will be loath to pursue investigations/prosecutions that might be perceived as a political witch hunt;
  • the blizzard of official authority and other defenses a president might raise, even short of full immunity;
  • the longstanding presumption against reading general statutory prohibitions as applying to the president;
  • the possibility that presidential offenses will be successfully concealed;
  • the elderliness of many presidents at the end of their terms.
For all of these reasons, the specter of post-presidential prosecution was at best a weak deterrent even before Trump. Conversely, the criminal liability of presidential subordinates, who carry virtually all presidential decisions into effect, remains an important check on high-level criminality even after Trump. It has probably always been a more important one historically (even if there are real limits to its effectiveness).

Read more »

Thursday, February 20, 2025

Emerging Outlines of an Executive Power Grab

David Super

      One month into the new administration, the typhoon of news stories about radical, often unprecedented, executive actions is dizzying.  Daily, sometimes even hourly, we hear of new, aggressive actions posing fundamental challenges to our constitutional order each rivaling President Truman’s seizure of the steel industry or President Nixon’s sweeping impoundments of appropriated funds. 

     Everyone can see that something dramatic is happening, but for many a clear picture of the new Administration’s plans may be elusive.  This is an attempt to synthesize the Administration’s actions into six principles.  The Administration will no doubt continue to elaborate on each of these, but the basic structure guiding this attempted revolution now seems fairly clear.

Read more »

Wednesday, February 19, 2025

John Bingham on Monsters and Natural-Born Fools

Gerard N. Magliocca

From a speech he gave on October 8, 1867:

[T]hey framed your matchless Constitution of Government at Philadelphia, known as the Constitution of the United States.— The word white is not there. The words "natural-born citizen" are there, and the man is a natural-born fool who does not understand that the term "natural-born citizen" implies that citizenship is a birthright. It comes with a man into the world. He has a right to citizenship, no matter what his complexion, upon the spot in which he had his origin; and the man who denies it to him, or attempts to withhold it from him, is simply a monster. When he comes to you with his nostrums you ought to herald his approach with the cry of the old cheating peddler: "This is the genuine old Doctor Jacob Townsend's sarsaparilla." - [Laughter.] 

UPDATE: Dr. Jacob Townsend's sarsaparilla was a popular "medicine" with many imitators.


 

 

 



Symmetry and Substance

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization symposium on Zachary Price, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2024).

Osagie K. Obasogie
 
I am teaching a seminar this semester on Substantive Due Process. The Supreme Court’s decision in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization compelled me to offer this class, as the rejection of reproductive rights as fundamental rights may very well signal the beginning of the end for the idea that unenumerated legal entitlements are hidden in due process clauses, and that a skilled jurist can discover and enforce them. My thinking has been that it would be good to be able to teach these materials now, before they become part of the Legal History curriculum.  
 
On the first day of class, I offered students a framework that could help them think through the nuances and complexities connected to an expansive reading of the 14th Amendment that might acknowledge such rights. I told them that, as a relatively young  person in my late 40s, I am part of the first generation of Black Americans in this country’s nearly 250-year history who was born entirely free. Students looked puzzled, and a bit shocked.  Wasn’t freedom for Black Americans settled in 1865 with the 13th Amendment?
Read more »

Tuesday, February 18, 2025

Lost in Translation: "Constitutional Symmetry" and the Challenge of Polarized Court Coverage

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization symposium on Zachary Price, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2024).

Stephanie Barclay

In his ambitious new book, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic, Zachary Price tackles one of the most pressing challenges facing American constitutional democracy: how courts can effectively adjudicate politically charged cases in an era of intense polarization. Price presents a framework for judicial decision-making that aims to reduce the political temperature while maintaining the legitimacy of constitutional interpretation. Price's core argument is that courts should strive for “constitutional symmetry” by applying consistent interpretive principles across ideologically different cases and by actively seeking to frame their decisions in ways that acknowledge and respect competing viewpoints. This approach, he contends, can help prevent constitutional law from becoming merely another battlefield in America's culture wars. The book points to illustrative examples of how courts have alternatively succeeded or failed at achieving this balance throughout American history.

One of the book's greatest strengths is its detailed historical analysis of how courts have navigated politically charged cases in previous eras of intense polarization. Price draws fascinating parallels between contemporary challenges and similar moments in American history, from the early Republic through the Civil War era and into the twentieth century. This historical perspective helps readers understand that while our current political divisions may feel unprecedented, the judiciary has long grappled with similar challenges.

Read more »

Monday, February 17, 2025

Who Is The Audience For This Book?

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization symposium on Zachary Price, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2024).     

 Sanford Levinson

          In Constitutional Symmetry:  Judging in a Divided Republic, Zachary Price captures the sense that I suspect that many of us feel about the current reality of politics in the United States.  In particular, he focuses on the undoubted fact that the polity is suffering from a kind of polarization that rationally leads many—perhaps most—thoughtful observers to an increasing sense of hopelessness about the ability of those purportedly “leading” the country to confront the pressing challenges facing us.  Some of these, such as climate change, are potentially existential.  And, of course, the election of a pathological lying narcissistic grifter as President does not help.  As an earlier theorist of politics once asked, “What is to be done?”  We know what Lenin’s answer was, and few of us are really happy to follow his model.  But the question remains all too powerful. 

          Professor Price, perhaps reflecting his position as a professor of constitutional law, offers what to many might seem a peculiar answer to the question.  That is, he turns away from my own obsession with constitutional reform, which to most people I know seems too radical or else simply impossible.  But he also pays no real attention to what one might do with regard to Congress and presidents with regard to their own revealed deficiencies.  Instead, he focuses exclusively on what the Supreme Court might do to help.  I will turn presently to his overarching suggestion.  It is worth noting, though, the degree to which he, like most legal academics, almost grotesquely overemphasizes the importance of the Supreme Court.  Whether by offering excessive praise, as many liberals did with regard to the so-called Warren Court, or perhaps justified condemnation, as with the present majority, one might well be exaggerating the actual role of the Court.

Read more »

Sunday, February 16, 2025

AI, Privacy, and the Politics of Accountability Part 2: Privacy Harm in the AI Economy

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization Symposium on Ignacio Cofone, The Privacy Fallacy: Harm and Power in the Information Economy Cambridge University Press (2023).

Ignacio Cofone

[This first part of this response appeared yesterday as “AI, Privacy, and the Politics of Accountability Part 1: Post-traditionalist Privacy for AI”] 

Privacy Harm is Systemic Because Privacy is Relational

Systemic harms relate to power asymmetries. Solow-Niederman emphasizes the structural power imbalances inherent in the information economy, a point echoed by Shvartzshnaider when discussing the opacity of data flows and by Bietti when identifying surveillance as infrastructural. AI intensifies these dynamics by enabling large-scale data aggregation and analysis that grow power over those whose data is held. Governance frameworks must account for these entrenched imbalances, as failure to do so risks perpetuating harms masked by claims of neutrality in AI.

For example, AI-powered credit scoring systems have been shown to disproportionately deny loans to minority applicants, even when data on race is excluded. This occurs through inferences such as those drawn from zip codes and purchasing patterns. Guggenberger correctly indicated that “the difference between product liability for cars and data lies in the type of harm.” Products’ liability harm might be systematic, but it is not systemic. Shifting responsibility from individuals whose data is being processed (where consent provisions place it) to entities that process it responds to critiques that account for power. Doing so requires advocating for governance models that recognize the systemic nature of AI-driven harms.

Read more »

"Subject to the Jurisdiction" Means "Municipal Jurisdiction"

Gerard N. Magliocca

My birthright citizenship article from 2008 discusses the Senate Judiciary Committee's 1870 Report about the Fourteenth Amendment's effect on the Indian Tribes. The Committee was asked (among other things) whether the Fourteenth Amendment made tribal members citizens. Its report contains the first construction of the "subject to the jurisdiction" language in Section One.

The Judiciary Committee stated that "it is manifest that Congress has never regarded the Indian tribes as subject to the municipal jurisdiction of the United States." Moreover, "an act of Congress which should assume to treat the members of a tribe as subject to the municipal jurisdiction of the United States would be unconstitutional and void." Accordingly, the Committee concluded that "the Indians, in tribal condition, have never been subject to the jurisdiction of the United States in the sense in which the term jurisdiction is employed in the fourteenth amendment to the Constitution." 

Thus, the first construction of the relevant language (two years after ratification) said jurisdiction meant "municipal jurisdiction." What is municipal jurisdiction? The legal authority to regulate, which is also the ordinary meaning of jurisdiction. The alternative suggestion put forth by some scholars that "subject to the jurisdiction" means "allegiance" finds no support here. 

     


Saturday, February 15, 2025

AI, Privacy, and the Politics of Accountability Part 1: Post-traditionalist Privacy for AI

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization Symposium on Ignacio Cofone, The Privacy Fallacy: Harm and Power in the Information Economy Cambridge University Press (2023).

Ignacio Cofone

Introduction

I’m very grateful to the contributors of this Balkinization symposium for their sharp analyses of The Privacy Fallacy—as I am to Jack Balkin for putting the symposium together. The comments in the symposium highlight key issues (and many challenges) in regulating the information economy and, particularly, in preventing and remedying harms in the context of data and AI. I would like to structure this response by highlighting two recurring themes across the reviews. The first theme, examined in this entry, is the limits of traditional consent-based and procedural frameworks to address the collective and inferential nature of privacy under AI. Most contributors highlighted the limitations of these mechanisms, especially when AI is involved, and shared the argument that privacy law must shift toward frameworks that prioritize substantive protection—the question is which ones. The second theme, which all commentators touched upon in one way or another and from different angles, is the issue of defining the boundaries of privacy harm in the information economy, which is examined in an entry that will follow this one. Across both themes is the issue of power.

Read more »

Symmetry’s Domain II

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization symposium on Zachary Price, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2024).

Mike Greve

Constitutional Symmetry is vintage Zach Price: judicious, learned, lawyerly, fair-minded, unfailingly respectful of differing opinions and commitments. The book is also admirably clear about symmetry’s envisioned role in adjudication. It is to operate at a high level, as opposed to judicial maneuvers that toss opinionated bones now to this camp, now to the other. It should operate within the framework of a sometimes asymmetric Constitution and of the judges’ jurisprudential commitments. It is not a rule but an ethic, an orientation, an all-else-equal preference.

I can’t see anything wrong with that, and I commend Zach for showing, in many thoughtful chapters, what constitutional symmetry might imply and how it might work in highly contested areas of law and public debate. I come, then, not to oppose but to sow confusion, or at least to admit to my own.

Read more »

Friday, February 14, 2025

Symmetry’s Domain

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization symposium on Zachary Price, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2024).

Jeffrey A. Pojanowski

            It is a pleasure to be able to contribute to this symposium on Professor Zachary Price’s book Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic, which deserves broad and deep and engagement. Everyone reading this symposium should read this book.

            First, I want to comment on the book’s general virtues before focusing on more discrete matters. There is a certain pleasure in reading a work whose style embodies its argument. To use very different examples, Nietzsche’s and Kant’s very different approaches to writing philosophy mirror what they think philosophy should be. We see something like that here. Price’s thesis is that, in polarized times, legal doctrines should reflect reasoned engagement, compromise, and fairness across ideological divides. His scholarship practices what it preaches. At a time where public discourse and scholarship veers towards the millenarian or apocalyptic, Price’s book is refreshingly measured. Although the book is animated by a crisis, reading it is like taking a good, long walk with a wise friend, not doom-scrolling. He engages with legal doctrine and the scholarly literature in a fair, thoughtful fashion that only strengthens the force of his broader argument.

            The book’s thesis is also ambitious and restrained. Price offers a grand theory for constitutional adjudication today. He argues that constitutional symmetry finds justification on three grounds: an updated and improved version Ely’s political process theory; a moral reading of the judicial role; and original methods of interpretation. (Price’s argument for symmetry at the level of doctrine recapitulates at the level of justification; there are many rooms in his theoretical house.) It also has wide-ranging applications: the First Amendment, separation of powers, Equal Protection, the Second Amendment, fundamental rights, and the law of democracy all get treatment here.

            At the same time, Price avoids the perils of cosmic constitutional theory. He is not here to tell everyone to whether to be an originalist or a living constitutionalist. Rather, he makes the more modest argument that whenever your preferred method of interpretation has play in the joints or requires implementing doctrines, you should resolve those indeterminacies or build those structures with an eye toward symmetry. The spread of his theory is total, but it is not totalizing. Thus, living constitutionalists should give the aims of symmetry a more decisive role when considering contemporary public values. When originalists find themselves in the “construction zone,” they should prioritize symmetry rather than, say, popular sovereignty or a presumption of liberty.

Read more »

Thursday, February 13, 2025

The Subtle Vices of the Virtue of Symmetry

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization symposium on Zachary Price, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2024).

William D. Araiza

Zachary Price has written a big and important book. It’s big in both the sweep of its coverage and its aspirations. Addressing a wide variety of constitutional and public law subject-areas, it aspires to provide a new criterion for judicial decision-making that he argues will do nothing less than mitigate the legitimacy crisis facing the Supreme Court. (To his great credit, he does not overclaim by arguing that his solution will completely solve that crisis. His modesty in that and other regards is one of the book’s many virtues.) And while his analysis is sophisticated, careful, and thorough, his main thesis is disarmingly straightforward: the Supreme Court, he argues, should consider and, to the extent possible, accord at least some weight to whether its analysis of a given issue will equally—“symmetrically”—impact both sides of today’s partisan divides. This is an important idea that deserves to be considered. Nevertheless, despite these undeniable virtues, some subtle vices, or at least unresolved ambiguities, lurk within it.

Read more »

Wednesday, February 12, 2025

Symmetry and Constitutional Adjudication

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization symposium on Zachary Price, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2024). 

H. Jefferson Powell

That the hyperpolarization of American politics poses serious problems for American constitutional law is undeniable.  No one argues that constitutional law – and the judges who administer its central mode of enforcement – should be partisan in a crude or conscious sense, the tool of either liberal or conservative political causes.  But with depressing regularity, the results of constitutional adjudication seem to map neatly onto the political preferences of judges, most prominently those of the justices of the United States Supreme Court.  It’s natural to respond by asking or demanding that the judges avoid or ignore the political divisions that separate the rest of us. 

In his bold, fascinating new book Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic, Zachary S. Price offers the startling suggestion that the courts address the problems posed by political polarization by embracing it.  Rather than pretending that constitutional decisions have no political salience that tracks the Republic’s overtly partisan disagreements, Professor Price argues that judges should take account of those disagreements by crafting rules of constitutional law that confer benefits on both sides of the liberal/conservative chasm, not as a matter of outcomes (“yesterday we gave the Democrats a victory, today’s decision has to reward the GOP”) but of articulating and acting on principles that offer equivalent protections to both sides.

Read more »

Balkinization Symposium on Zachary Price, Constitutional Symmetry

JB


This week at Balkinization we are hosting a symposium on Zachary Price's new book, Constitutional Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2024).


We have assembled a terrific group of commentators, including Bill Araiza (Brooklyn), Stephanie Barclay (Georgetown), Mike Greve (George Mason), Sanford Levinson (Texas), Osagie Obasogie (Berkeley), Jeff Pojanowski (Notre Dame), and Jeff Powell (Duke).

At the conclusion, Zach will respond to the commentators.


Tuesday, February 11, 2025

A compromise on emergency abortions that red states should embrace

Andrew Koppelman

It is time for states that have banned abortion to put an end to the horror stories of women being refused emergency medical treatment when their pregnancies go terribly wrong. The states can do this in a perhaps surprising way — by tweaking a solution that the Biden administration proposed.

I explain in a new column at The Hill.

Institutional Vandalism

Guest Blogger

Jonathan Chausovsky

The vast uprising of critiques of the current effort to dismantle the institutions of the United States Government is pervasive and important.  Here, I suggest that to do so we ought to take institutional theory into our account of these events. 

In his groundbreaking book from 1982, Building a New American State, Stephen Skowronek argued that the governing challenges of that day were linked to the reform solutions of the past.[1] He configured politics as a set of entrenched interests seeking to preserve their institutional structures, contesting with a rising set of reformers that sought to displace them. His study of the Gilded Age and Progressive Era depicted contests in three areas: civil service, army organization, and railroad regulation. The outcome of these contests was not what any one side sought. Rather, pathologies of the old were embedded within the reform solutions that emerged. 

            We can likewise place our current challenges in the context of realignment theory. Walter Dean Burnham built on V.O. Key Jr.’s seminal work on critical elements to examine ongoing efforts at party composition and decomposition.[2] Burnham recognized that parties are coalitions, and that catastrophic events contributed to the restructuring of the party coalitions within the broader political universe. The shifts could be gradual, but were periodically punctuated by rapid disruption in response to catastrophe. Burnham was wedded to these upheavals occurring at fairly regular intervals of 32 to 36 years; but his mechanism of generational change was always somewhat inadequate for the massive disruptions he sought to explain. However, a focus on partisan composition and recomposition within our peculiar two-party system remains. With hindsight of 50 years since the end of the Great Society, we can easily identify the recomposition of the two political parties in the wake of the Civil Rights movement. This is evident in the abortion battle, the reemergence of the religious right, along with massive inequality and concentration of wealth aided by the corporate device.

Read more »

Monday, February 10, 2025

Trump Isn’t Going to be Impeached. Let’s Not Pretend That’s OK.

Richard Primus

             Amidst the predictable chaos, cavalier illegality, and general destruction of the first weeks of the new Trump Administration, it is unfortunately necessary to remember the following fact: there are no foreseeable circumstances under which President Trump could be removed from office through the impeachment process.  Nearly ten years ago, during his first campaign, he said that he could shoot someone in the middle of Fifth Avenue and his supporters wouldn’t abandon him.  He hasn’t yet actually shot someone in the middle of Fifth Avenue, but the idea he was expressing has been pretty well borne out.  Even after President Trump inspired a violent attack on Congress in the hopes of preventing the peaceful transfer of power to a legitimately elected president, his supporters mostly stayed with him, and four years later he was elected president again.  It’s hard to think there is anything he could do that would bring significant numbers of incumbent Republican officeholders to the conclusion that he had to be removed.  That being the case, impeachment is essentially impossible, and everybody knows it.

            Nonetheless, it is important to continue to assert that certain conduct in which President Trump engages is, on the merits, conduct that ought to be regarded as inconsistent with the duties of the office in a fundamental enough way to require impeachment and removal.  In other words, in full knowledge that the President will not in fact be impeached and removed, it is important to say, when it’s true, that he has done something for which he should be impeached and removed, and for which he would be impeached and removed in a properly functioning version of the American constitutional system.

            Here I want to outline a way of thinking about how and why President Trump could and should be removed, now, for two aspects of his relationship to the January 6 riot.  The first, for which he was already impeached once, is his encouragement and support of the riot itself.  The second is his pardoning and commuting the sentences of people convicted of criminal offenses for their participation in the riot.

Read more »

Tuesday, February 04, 2025

Critiquing Hadley Arkes’s not-so-mere Natural Law Theory

Andrew Koppelman

Law can’t be separated from morality, because law is a kind of human conduct.  So is compliance with the law.  Morality constrains all of human conduct.  So the idea of natural law, a set of moral constraints binding on any possible legal system, has perennial appeal.

Hadley Arkes is a leading contemporary proponent of a revived natural law.  His prominence is deserved.  His work is smart and learned and entertaining.  He writes with admirable moral passion.  He is urgently concerned that persons be treated with dignity and respect, passionate about protecting the weak and vulnerable, especially children, with an especial scorn for racism.  But he is unpersuasive with respect to some of the most important legal issues he takes up:  the scope of the modern administrative state, antidiscrimination law, and abortion.  He often ignores counterarguments.  More than that, he neglects important aspects of the natural law tradition.

I explain in a short new essay in the Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy Per Curiam.


Monday, February 03, 2025

Thursday, January 30, 2025

Glossing the Foreign Affairs Constitution

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization Symposium on Curtis A. Bradley, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice (Harvard University Press, 2024).

Curtis Bradley

In my new book, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice, I document how the U.S. constitutional law of foreign affairs has been shaped over time by the practices and interactions of Congress and the executive branch. These practices, the book explains, have “glossed” the meaning of the Constitution’s text and structure—and this has been true since the very beginning of the country. As the book documents, the political branches have filled in and clarified constitutional meaning, on issues ranging from the recognition of foreign governments, to the conclusion of executive agreements, to the use of military force. In addition to providing examples of foreign affairs authority that have been glossed through practice, the book situates the historical gloss approach to constitutional interpretation within broader debates about constitutional theory.
 
I am deeply grateful to the participants in this online symposium for their engagement with the book, and to Jack Balkin for hosting it. The commentators are all terrific scholars, and they are methodologically and ideologically diverse in their perspectives. I cannot do justice in this post to their thoughtful reflections, so instead I will just touch on a few points. (For a broader description of the book and what it seeks to accomplish, readers might also be interested in the five posts that I wrote on the Volokh Conspiracy site on the eve of the book’s release.)
Read more »

Tuesday, January 28, 2025

Dred Scott, the Northwest Ordinance, and the Perils of Historical Memes

Guest Blogger

David S. Schwartz 

A mistaken characterization of historical fact can become a conventional wisdom through the same process that generates memes. When it seems too much trouble to go back to the primary source, it is natural to quote a reliable secondary one, and repeat what may be an error. 

In Dred Scott, Chief Justice Taney asserted that the first federal Congress in 1789 passed legislation “reviving” the Northwest Ordinance of 1787.[1] In fact, Congress did not do this, but instead “adapted” the Northwest Ordinance to the Constitution’s new system of separated powers. This distinction is more than semantic. The notion of a “revived” or “re-enacted” Ordinance was an important premise in Taney’s argument that the Missouri Compromise was unconstitutional. I explain his argument in detail, in a new article showing that Taney’s argument against the Missouri Compromise sounded in limited enumerated powers—enumerationism—whereas the substantive due process argument was a mere makeweight tacked on at the end of this part of the ruling. 

This post focuses on the enumerationist argument, and the role played in it by Taney’s characterization of the 1789 Northwest Territories Act—a mischaracterization that is unthinkingly repeated by virtually all modern scholars.

Read more »

Unlawful Funding Freeze Sows Chaos

David Super

     Last night, the Trump Administration’s Office of Management and Budget (OMB) startled and befuddled state and local governments, non-profit service providers, universities, and vulnerable people across the country by announcing a freeze on a wide swath of government payments.  It announced that, as of 5pm today, “Federal agencies must temporarily pause all activities related to obligation or disbursement of all Federal financial assistance”.  (Emphasis in the original.)  This “pause” is coupled with a review federal agencies are required to conduct for activities that violate President Trump’s flurry of new executive orders.  Although OMB directs agencies to act “to the extent permissible by law”, this entire order is unlawful.  That is one of many ambiguities in the order that seems certain to cause chaos and harm vulnerable people.
Read more »

Monday, January 27, 2025

Balkinization Symposium on Rogers M. Smith and Desmond King, America’s New Racial Battle Lines: Protect versus Repair-- Collected Posts

JB


Here are the collected posts for our Balkinization symposium on Rogers M. Smith and Desmond King, America’s New Racial Battle Lines: Protect versus Repair (University of Chicago Press, 2024).

1. Jack Balkin, Introduction to the Symposium

2. Alexandra Filindra, Race, Democracy, and the Politics of Pain: A Review of America’s New Racial Battle Lines 

3. Carol Nackenoff, Is This Battle Royale?

4. Evan D. Bernick, Our Reactionary Constitutionalism

5. Corey Robin, Plus ça change

6. Chloe Thurston, Racial Orders and American Political Development: International, Intra-Coalitional, and Individual Dimensions 

7. Rebecca E. Zietlow, Backlash

8. James E. Fleming & Linda C. McClain, America’s Battle Lines: A Comment on Rogers M. Smith and Desmond King’s America’s New Racial Battle Lines: Protect versus Repair

9. Rogers M. Smith and Desmond King, When Do Differences in Degree Becomes Differences in Kind? A Response to the Balkinization Symposiasts




Wednesday, January 22, 2025

The Deep English Roots of Using the Custom and Tradition of Governmental Practice as a Source of Legal Meaning for Interpreting Written Constitutional Texts, or, A Lesson for Originalists Too

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization Symposium on Curtis A. Bradley, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice (Harvard University Press, 2024).

Julian Davis Mortenson

With its publication, Curt Bradley’s Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs becomes the standard reference on the historical role of custom and tradition in defining the President’s relationship with Congress and with the law of the land.

Debates about those relationships have long been vexed, particularly on questions of national security and foreign affairs. The text of the Constitution does not say much about presidential power. Nor, because of jurisdictional and prudential limitations, have the courts been in a good position to generate a more particularized body of judicial precedent on these questions over time. These background conditions, Bradley argues, have required custom and tradition to take on load-bearing duty as a source of legal meaning on the separation of powers. From there, he charts the consistency with which American constitutional law has reflected this reality across a wide array of controversies in foreign affairs.

Bradley’s book is thoroughly persuasive on both counts. Also cogent is his insistence on the need for scrupulous care when analyzing custom and tradition, the complexities of which are often, well, glossed over. On this score, Bradley’s critique of Zivotofsky v. Clinton is characteristically precise. In that case, the Supreme Court held that the President has an exclusive constitutional power to recognize foreign states. As Bradley deftly explains, however, the court’s analysis of evidence from custom and tradition rested on a category error. The majority collected numerous examples of presidents recognizing foreign governments. But none involved a legal structure like the one presented in Zivotofsky—i.e., Youngtown Zone 3 presidential action that defied a duly enacted statute. The majority’s evidence, Bradley observes, may well support an inherent presidential authority to recognize foreign states in the face of legislative silence—i.e., in Youngstown Zone 2. But the issue actually presented by the case was completely different. Bradley is entirely right to call for higher analytical standards than this.

Read more »

Tuesday, January 21, 2025

Birthright Citizenship

Gerard N. Magliocca

Here is my 2008 article on this subject. 

Congress and the Challenges of Historical Gloss

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization Symposium on Curtis A. Bradley, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice (Harvard University Press, 2024).

Kristen E. Eichensehr 

Curtis Bradley’s new book on Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs is the definitive account of a mode of constitutional interpretation that has proven key to the development of foreign relations law, both within and outside the courts. Bradley is an enthusiastic supporter of using gloss and persuasively explains why doing so is often necessary given the “laconic” nature of the Constitution’s provisions related to foreign affairs (Chap. 2). At the same time, Bradley acknowledges the risk that reliance on historical gloss tends to favor the executive branch, which can act and stake out legal positions more easily than Congress (30). Bradley nonetheless argues that when one understands how Congress benefits from historical gloss, “Congress looks more formidable than it is sometimes described” (166) and “can often have the last word in foreign affairs” (167). 

While Bradley convincingly shows that Congress sometimes benefits from gloss, he says less about how Congress can avoid losing out to gloss-based arguments by the executive. If congressional acquiescence is required for a valid executive branch claim of historical gloss (26), then what must Congress do to not acquiesce? In other words, what counts or should count as a congressional objection sufficient to defeat an executive branch claim of acquiescence?

Read more »

Monday, January 20, 2025

Moody v. NetChoice - The Supreme Court Meets the Free Speech Triangle

JB

I've posted my latest essay, Moody v. NetChoice - The Supreme Court Meets the Free Speech Triangle, on SSRN. Here is the abstract.

Moody v. NetChoice is the Supreme Court's first attempt at applying the First Amendment to social media content regulation. Private infrastructure owners can act both as speakers and as the governors of other people's speech. This requires a shift from the traditional dyadic model of speech regulation--government versus citizen-- to a pluralist or triangular model in which both states and owners of private infrastructure govern end user speech.

Traditional First Amendment doctrine has problems dealing with this shift. The free speech triangle generates perpetual conflicts between the free speech interests of infrastructure companies and end users. Because First Amendment doctrine assumes that only governments regulate (and censor) speech, it has difficulty dealing with these conflicts, and it tends to conflate speech rights with property rights. As a result, to the extent that existing doctrine recognizes First Amendment rights, they will usually be the rights of large digital companies and not of end users.

Moody exemplifies these tendencies, granting social media companies a First Amendment right to govern their end users' speech. The free speech interests of end users play little to no role in the Court's analysis.

The best approach is to read Moody narrowly to apply to applications resembling social media feeds, but not to other kinds of digital platforms or to other services lower in the "tech stack." This would allow governments to impose non-discrimination or common-carriage rules on other parts of the digital infrastructure, especially when their primary job is to ensure that digital traffic flows smoothly and efficiently.

Moody leaves untouched content-neutral structural regulations to ensure fair competition. For example, governments could require social media platforms to permit end users to subscribe to middleware services that would offer alternative content moderation and recommendation systems. Governments could also require interoperability between social media platforms. These kinds of reforms would allow end users to benefit from the network effects of global platforms but also offer them greater choice in how their speech is governed and regulated. They would lower barriers to entry for new companies that could provide competing content moderation and recommendation services. This would help counter the dominance of a tiny number of powerful global companies that decide who speaks online.

The Court assumed without deciding that states might impose disclosure and transparency rules on social media companies under compelled commercial speech doctrine. This is in tension with its holding that content moderation and recommendation systems involve editorial judgments like those in newspapers. Newspapers are normally free to make editorial judgments without having to justify themselves to the state. In fact, commercial speech doctrine is an imperfect proxy for the real issues of procedural fairness. What is really at stake is not whether end users are well informed; it is whether they are being governed arbitrarily.

Finally, Moody begins thinking about whether content produced by algorithms and artificial intelligence is protected by the First Amendment. The Court's brief discussion shows that it understands the problem is important but that it currently lacks the tools to resolve it in a satisfactory way.


Historical Gloss and the Erosion of Constitutional Safeguards

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization Symposium on Curtis A. Bradley, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice (Harvard University Press, 2024).

Michael J. Gerhardt

        

Introduction

For our symposium on Curtis Bradley’s book, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice,[1] I have (largely) resisted the urge to heap praise on his insightful, comprehensive, and compelling account of how “historical gloss” (or “the accretion of governmental practice”) has shaped the balance of power in foreign affairs.[2]  I agree with Professor Bradley that consistent historical practices over time may inform or shape constitutional construction.[3]  But rather than focus on our many areas of agreement, I aim to expand on and clarify some aspects of his account, particularly how to identify the use of historical practices as a legitimate basis for constructive as opposed to destructive constitutional interpretation.

More specifically, I examine how historical practices, as a gloss or in some other form, have not constructed but instead dismantled constitutional safeguards in the constitutional scheme of separation of powers. My concern is with how the accretion of historical practices can sometimes erode constitutional safeguards for the sake of aggrandizing one branch’s authority at the expense of another’s and the Constitution’s intricate system of checks and balances. In undertaking this inquiry, I revisit several examples from Bradley’s excellent book as well as several others not discussed to illustrate the erosion of constitutional safeguards primarily to shield against executive tyranny and misconduct. My purpose is not to construct some grand theory of constitutional interpretation or change. Rather, my purpose is to expand on Professor Bradley’s analytical framework to clarify the destructive side of historical practices and gloss. Sometimes, as I will show, the Court and/or other constitutional actors seek to expand their authority at the expense of another branch.

Read more »

Sunday, January 19, 2025

Gloss and Practice: Reading Bradley Through the Lens of Hart and Dworkin

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization Symposium on Curtis A. Bradley, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice (Harvard University Press, 2024).

Richard Fallon 

Curtis Bradley’s book Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice will be welcomed as an indispensable resource for anyone seeking to understand the constitutional law of the United States as it bears on foreign affairs.  Among the book’s contributions, it provides an engaging description of the potentially disputable powers that Presidents and Congress have respectively asserted, and about the arguments that they have advanced in support of their positions, over the sweep of history.  At the very least, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs thus establishes how de facto constitutional authority has historically been distributed.

Bradley, however, goes a step further.  His central, formally stated thesis holds that the historical practices of Presidents and Congress can become valid sources of interpretive authority in subsequent constitutional disputes.  Bradley offers multiple case studies in which he takes historical practice of the President and Congress, as much as that of the courts, to have resolved “ambiguities” and “fill[ed] gaps” in the constitutional text.  And sometimes, he writes, a form of practice that he calls “gloss” “largely supersedes (or at least overshadows) the text.”  According to him, examples of “gloss” can be seen in the widespread recognition that the President can negotiate treaties without seeking “advice” from the Senate in any formal sense “and, more dramatically,” in the widely shared understanding that the President can bind the nation via executive agreements rather than treaties.  (pp. 192–93)

 If Bradley had cast his book as a political history of the assertion of legally disputable powers, or as a sociological account of when the President and Congress are likely to acquiesce in assertions of authority by other actors, it would seem to me to be wholly persuasive.  But insofar as Bradley claims that “gloss” makes “law” or establishes a source of legal authority in constitutional argument — and, equally importantly, that historical practice by the President and Congress that fails to meet his definition of gloss has no similar law-altering effect — a bit more caution may be in order.

Read more »

Saturday, January 18, 2025

Justifying Constitutional Change in Foreign Affairs Outside of Article V

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization Symposium on Curtis A. Bradley, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice (Harvard University Press, 2024).

Jide Nzelibe 

Professor Bradley’s most recent book, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs, makes a valuable contribution to our understanding of the role of historical practice in the constitutional allocation of foreign affairs powers.  His normative approach is largely Burkean: once we accept that legal stability is a compelling objective, it makes sense for courts to privilege the longstanding practices of the political branches in foreign affairs over other alternatives as a source of constitutional understanding. 

But Professor Bradley also recognizes that marginal changes to the constitutional structure in foreign affairs may sometimes be necessary to respond to unforeseen geopolitical developments.  The challenge is that the constitutional amendment process under Article V is too rigid.  Significant changes to the foreign affairs powers have nonetheless occurred throughout U.S. history and have always occurred outside the formal amendment process mandated by Article V.   Professor Bradley documents many of these changes and argues that they may be justifiable on the basis that they have produced a better state of affairs and have been ratified by the continuous practices of the political branches.  One of his most striking examples is that executive agreements have since displaced treaties as the primary process through which the United States enters into international agreements.

It is the nature of Professor Bradley’s account of constitutional change outside of Article V that I wish to focus my attention.   What are the conditions under which changes to constitutional practices in foreign affairs can be perceived as legitimate, even if they are imposed unilaterally by presidents or other political actors?  Professor Bradley suggests two pragmatic conditions.  First, the change should be ratified by downstream political actors across multiple electoral cycles.  Second, the constitutional change should be gradual and incremental in a manner analogous to the evolution of the common law.  In this account, presidents and other political actors can tinker on the margins with constitutional practices in foreign affairs and allow them to be abandoned or gradually refined if they fail to work out.  Presumably, those incremental changes to the foreign affairs constitution that stand the test of time are likely to be mutually advantageous, or else they will be discarded.

Read more »

Friday, January 17, 2025

What Gloss Glosses Over

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization Symposium on Curtis A. Bradley, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice (Harvard University Press, 2024).

Jean Galbraith

When I teach Foreign Relations Law, I assign George Washington’s Message to the House Regarding Jay Treaty Documents on the first day of class.  This missive has it all:  an inter-branch fight, high practical stakes, and well-marshalled constitutional argumentation.  But my favorite sentence invokes historical practice.  Urging that the House has no role in treaty-making, Washington writes:  “In this construction of the Constitution every House of Representatives has heretofore acquiesced, and until the present time not a doubt or suspicion has appeared, to my knowledge, that this construction was not a true one.”  It had been only seven years since the Constitution entered into force, and yet the Founders were already looking to historical practice!

Curt Bradley’s book on Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs illustrates how historical gloss matters to foreign affairs.  Gloss, as Curt defines it, is “looking to longstanding practices of government institutions” in “interpret[ing] other constitutional materials, most notably the constitutional text and structural inferences from the text, when those materials are thought to be unclear.”  As his subsequent chapters show, a great deal is thought to be unclear.  Gloss has led to sharply different practices today than existed at the time of the Framing, including how international agreements are made and how much the President can unilaterally authorize uses of force abroad.  Overall, Curt finds that gloss has considerably increased presidential power over time.  Like fortune, gloss favors the bold.  This increase, however, is mostly to concurrent presidential powers rather than to exclusive presidential powers.  

Curt also makes a powerful argument for why gloss should matter.  Gloss allows for change over time – for “needed constitutional updating,” contra stand-alone originalism.  Yet gloss also presumes that “longstanding practices of government institutions – disciplined by regular elections – are indicative of what works reasonably well, or at least better than anything the judiciary is likely to impose.”  In other words, gloss serves as a beneficial middle ground between stagnancy and upheaval. 

But gloss is not just the shine that history puts on constitutional law.  It is also a way to conceal flaws – to gloss over problems.  We think that there is good law that constrains our leaders and overlook just how thin this law can be.

Read more »

Older Posts

Home