Balkinization  

Wednesday, September 24, 2025

Symposium Response Part 1: The strange career of civil rights

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization symposium on Dylan C. Penningroth, Before the Movement: The Hidden History of Black Civil Rights (Liveright, 2023).

Dylan C. Penningroth

Many thanks to Jack Balkin and Balkinization for hosting this symposium. I’m grateful to Carol Rose, Evelyn Atkinson, Ian Ayres, Mark Graber, Mark Tushnet, and Steve Griffin for taking the time to read and provide such probing comments on Before the Movement. It has taken me awhile to post my response, in part because it has been so much fun to absorb and learn from their comments.

The contributors beautifully bring out several of the book’s main themes, and space allows me to touch on only some of their constructive critiques. The first, as Professor Griffin notes, is how Black people used and thought about law from the 1830s to the 1970s, how a subset of nineteenth-century rights and privileges came to be understood as “civil rights,” and how that term, over the next century or so, slowly came to stand for the principles of nondiscrimination and anti-humiliation that animate much of modern civil rights law. If had been more daring and witty, I might have titled the book “The Strange Career of Civil Rights.”[1]

The second theme is the sources I used to tell this story. Of course, I am far from the first historian to go asking big questions of small courts. Since the early 2000s, a number of legal historians have made the trek to the courthouse door, including Laura Edwards, Melvin Ely, Sarah Barringer Gordon, Martha Jones, Anne Twitty, Kimberly Welch and, more recently, Sarah L. H. Gronningsater. Aside from the physical and logistical challenges of researching in under-funded facilities that are not really “archives,”[2] all of us have confronted the analytic and conceptual challenges of taking the legalities latent in local court records and relating them to the “mandarin materials,” as Robert Gordon termed them, of appellate case law, statutes, and treatises.[3] But increasingly, on days when I walked past the inevitable Confederate statue to beg another circuit clerk’s permission to rummage around in the courthouse attic, I felt the presence of a different intellectual tradition than perhaps the ones we had been trained in; that we were actually following in the footsteps of earlier generations of Black historians, who had to negotiate with the gatekeepers of official records in the unfathomably harsher environment of the 1930s and 40s. Only a few of those earlier historians were professional scholars, like Luther Porter Jackson. Mostly they were lay historians—church officers, like A.M.E. Bishop Richard R. Wright,[4] or lawyer-memoirists, like Thomas Calhoun Walker,[5] or keepers of family history, like my great-great-uncle Thomas Holcomb. What they wanted to demonstrate was that, right in the maw of a nation dedicated to white supremacy, “free Negroes” and their descendants had “made a record” of achievement in education, landownership, and trade.[6] And they believed that record entitled them to “the good will and respect of [their] neighbors and fellow citizens,”[7] as Jackson put it—or what activists called “public rights”[8] or “first-class citizenship.”[9] These earlier Black historians’ linking of common-law rights to “classes” of citizenship eventually helped inform my argument about how the idea of civil rights changed. Often stuffed with thumbnail sketches and hopeful statistics about Black churches and property ownership and literacy, these works were more than mere “encyclopedic pep talks” or “storehouses of uplift ideology” in the mold of Booker T. Washington.[10] Whatever else they were, they also hinted at a history of Black legal thought, one that seemed to me to be in dialogue with questions of racial justice but not contained by them. More immediately, those early Black historians seemed to suggest that there were certain continuities across the gulf of the Civil War: that white people more or less took it for granted that Black people could own and trade things.[11] That, at least in the realm of civil rights, the transformation came gradually, raggedly, and perhaps rife with irony.

We might explain this continuity in terms of ideology—specifically, white people’s investment in the belief that law was not (just) an instrument of class power. More frequently, as Professor Graber points out, I look to Derrick Bell’s interest-convergence theory. This was a “triumph of informal property over formal law,” Professor Rose writes, where wide swaths of white southerners—including huge numbers of non-slaveowning whites—enjoyed easy access to cheap, convenient goods and services from enslaved Black people, an enjoyment procured not (just) through “brute compulsion” but through legal marginality and indeterminacy.[12] White southerners benefited precisely from the law’s refusal to speak clearly and consistently about slaves’ property and contracts. (To which I would add that there are uncomfortable resonances with the benefits American citizens enjoy from the work of undocumented immigrants today.)

In my first book, I described enslaved people’s property as “extralegal.”[13] Researching Before the Movement changed my mind: enslaved people’s privileges had legal meaning, indeed were constituted through law, not in the absence of law or in spite of law. What law? As Professor Tushnet intuits, the book is deeply influenced by scholarship on legal pluralism, though more through studies of colonialism in Africa than literature in dialogue with Ernst Fraenkel’s conception of the dual state in Nazi Germany.[14] So, although I think African Americans did develop their own distinctive ideas about property, and I agree that “Black-specific legal concepts” like “the ignorant negro” surfaced more explicitly in the South than elsewhere, as Professor Tushnet’s modified version of Fraenkel’s “dual state” theory might predict, I am just as fascinated by the ways Black-owned property was rooted in something broader—in what Arthur Corbin called “community opinion,”[15] the “sense of the situation”[16] that was shared in common by all “members of the community,”[17] not just by Black people or enslaved people. And I am equally fascinated by the furtive struggle hidden beneath that sunny Realist conception of legality, where some “members of the community”—women, poor white men, free Black people, enslaved people, young people—had far less power to mold “community opinion” than others. If Laura Edwards is right that nineteenth-century law was not just for people with rights,[18] I think this was largely because rights themselves existed in a thick network of shared understandings and symbolic acts: recording, talking, using, and showing. But also because, as Kate Masur reminds us, privileges still carried legal weight in the nineteenth century.[19] Slaves held certain prerogatives that were typically referred to as privileges, not rights, but that were nevertheless legally meaningful to the extent they comported with “community opinion”—furtively contested and riven by hierarchies of sex, race, age, and class—both of specific practices and of general legal principles.

Antislavery Republicans “popularized the idea that the law was not present in the relationship between slaves and their masters,” as Professor Griffin nicely puts it. They drew a sharp line between slavery (a law-free zone of no-rights) and freedom (the world of rights). In doing so, they abandoned not only the eighteenth-century politician’s “broader, antirepublican concept of slavery” as “illegitimate domination, political subordination, and the absence of republican government,”[20] but also the ordinary American’s long experience with the world of privileges, a world in which slaves could participate. This abandonment is a key reason why the framers of the Reconstruction amendments could assume “that slavery could be removed from the legal order without changing much of anything else”[21]—and why it seems surprising today that slaves could have owned property.

As Professor Rose perceptively draws out, Before the Movement charts the rights/privilege distinction over the long durée, trying to show how, over and over, the world of privileges was renewed—not swept away—by the coming of Black rights. The book thus levels a challenge to Eric Foner’s reigning interpretation of Reconstruction as an “unfinished revolution”[22] where millions of Black free and freedpeople asserted a grassroots constitutional vision of economic autonomy, political equality, and national protection for individual rights.[23] The “unfinished revolution” thesis, along with its close conceptual cousin ‘bottom-up constitutionalism,’ has been foundational for my thinking about political economy. But much of what I found in the county courthouses required different assumptions and concepts, ones better suited for thinking about legalities that were conceived in local, not national or constitutional terms, and about dimensions of Black life that were not primarily about race relations. I looked for inspiration from people like Jackson, Wright, and my own relatives—a Black intellectual tradition that complements but stands somewhat distinct from the Du Boisian approach that inspired Foner. As much as Reconstruction was about competing visions of freedom, and as much as the Fourteenth Amendment was shaped by grassroots constitutionalism, neither freedom nor the Fourteenth Amendment changed very much about the property law or contract law that people encountered in their daily lives. Indeed, its Republican proponents strenuously denied any intention to give Congress power to interfere with the states’ vast corpus of statutes and common-law rules, except those that arbitrarily discriminated between classes of citizens.[24] And although I did not stress it in Before the Movement, centering the world of the civil also raises questions about the revolutionary character of the Second Reconstruction. Such continuities may prove instructive as scholars bring these classic private-law domains into conversation with the nominally public-law domain of antidiscrimination.[25] This is also why, although the book avoids what Professor Graber dubs the “racial rule of thermodynamics,” I wouldn’t necessarily see it as a “largely uplifting story.” I may not be an Afropessimist[26] but I don’t think I am a constitutional optimist,[27] either!



[1] With apologies to C. Vann Woodward.

[2] These challenges are memorably described in Kimberly M. Welch, Black Litigants in the Antebellum American South (Chapel Hill, 2018), 6-8.

[3] Robert W. Gordon, “Critical Legal Histories,” Stanford Law Review 36, no. 1-2 (1984), 120.

[4] The Encyclopaedia of the African Methodist Episcopal Church, comp. Richard R. Wright (Philadelphia, 1947). Bishop Wright had a PhD in Sociology from Penn. He was editor of The Christian Recorder, the newspaper of the A.M.E. Church, president of Wilberforce University.

[5] Thomas C. Walker, The Honey-Pod Tree: The Life Story of Thomas Calhoun Walker (New York, 1958).

[6] Luther Porter Jackson, “Free Negroes of Petersburg, Virginia,” Journal of Negro History 12 (1927), 368.

[7] Jackson, “Free Negroes of Petersburg,” 382.

[8] Rebecca J. Scott, “Public Rights, Social Equality, and the Conceptual Roots of the Plessy Challenge,” Michigan Law Review 106, 5 (2008), 781.

[9] Martin Luther King Jr., “The Rising Tide of Racial Consciousness” (1960), in A Testament of Hope, 148 (“first-class citizenship”); Walker, The Honey-Pod Tree, 182-83 (“full citizenship rights”).

[10] That is how these works are characterized in David W. Blight, Race and Reunion: The Civil War in American Memory (Cambridge, Mass., 2001), 333

[11] Luther Porter Jackson, Free Negro Labor and Property Holding in Virginia, 1830–1860 (Appleton-Century, 1942), 31–32.

[12] Professor Rose’s comments about monitoring and supervision costs remind me just how much my thinking about these issues has been informed, often half-consciously and indirectly, by economic historians. In the 1990s, when I was in graduate school, questions about the origins and logic of property-owning by slaves were aimed at illuminating the organization of enslaved labor (task versus gang systems) and its impact on the economics of slavery. For example, supervision costs (or “policing,” as Barzel terms it), are key to Philip D. Morgan, “Work and Culture: The Task System and the World of Lowcountry Blacks, 1700-1880,” William and Mary Quarterly 39, no. October (1982): 563-99.

[13] Dylan C. Penningroth, The Claims of Kinfolk: African American Property and Community in the Nineteenth-Century South (Chapel Hill, 2003).

[14] The intellectual lineages are helpfully distinguished in the article Professor Tushnet flagged in his post: Michael McCann and Filiz Kahraman, “On the Interdependence of Liberal and Illiberal/Authoritarian Legal Forms in Racial Capitalist Regimes…the Case of the United States,” Annual Review of Law and Social Science 17 (2021), 485. I was in graduate school puzzling my way through Africanist literatures on slavery and colonial rule when I encountered Hendrik Hartog, “Pigs and Positivism,” Wisconsin Law Review, no. 4 (1985), 899-935.

[15] Arthur Linton Corbin, Corbin on Contracts: A Comprehensive Treatise on the Working Rules of Contract Law, vol. 1A (St. Paul, 1963), § 230.

[16] Karl N. Llewellyn, “Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules or Canons About How Statutes Are to Be Construed,” Vand. L. Rev., vol. 3 (1950), 397.

[17] Max Radin, “The Theory of Judicial Decision: Or How Judges Think,” A. B. A. J. 11, no. 6 (1925), 362.

[18] Laura F. Edwards, The People and Their Peace: Legal Culture and the Transformation of Inequality in the Post-Revolutionary South (Chapel Hill, 2009).

[19] Kate Masur, An Example for All the Land: Emancipation and the Struggle over Equality in Washington, D.C. (Chapel Hill, 2010), 6-7 (“the focus on federal legislation and constitutional change has kept our range of vision narrow, drawing attention to individual rights and away from older but still important convictions about group identities and the privileges of local citizenship”).

[20] Jack M. Balkin and Sanford Levinson, “The Dangerous Thirteenth Amendment,” Colum. L. Rev. 112, no. 7 (2012), 1462, 1482-84.

[21] Laura F. Edwards, A Legal History of the Civil War and Reconstruction: A Nation of Rights (New York, 2015), 124.

[22] In 1988, Foner was refuting a once-dominant scholarly tradition that emphasized “how essentially nonrevolutionary and conservative Reconstruction really was.” C. Vann Woodward (1979), quoted in Eric Foner, Reconstruction: America's Unfinished Revolution, 1863-1877 (1988; New York, 2002), xxi. I am far from the first person to question how useful it is to center revolution and freedom as the key conceptual paradigms for interpreting Reconstruction. For example, see Gregory P. Downs, “Eric Foner’s ‘Reconstruction’ at Twenty-Five,” Journal of the Gilded Age and Progressive Era 14, no. 1 (2015), 18.

[23] Eric Foner, “Rights and the Constitution in Black Life during the Civil War and Reconstruction,” Journal of American History 74, no. 3 (1987), 863-83.

[24] William E. Nelson, The Fourteenth Amendment: From Political Principle to Judicial Doctrine (Cambridge, Mass., 1988), 114-24.

[25] For example, see Abbye Atkinson, “Borrowing Equality,” Colum. L. Rev. 120, no. 6 (2020), 1403-69; Erik Encarnacion, “Section 1981 as Contract Law,” 111 Va. L. Rev. __ (forthcoming 2025).

[26] Frank B. Wilderson III, Afropessimism (New York, 2020) (“the narrative arc of the slave who is Black (unlike Orlando Patterson’s generic Slave, who may be of any race) is not an arc at all, but a flat line”).

[27] See Stephen M. Griffin, “Optimistic Originalism and the Reconstruction Amendments,” Tulane L. Rev. 95, no. 2 (2020), 281-357 (describing and critiquing the idea that the Fourteenth Amendment’s original meaning supports the canonical decisions of the post-1945 Supreme Court and that the Reconstruction amendments were “a binding promise” left unfulfilled until the Second Reconstruction).



Older Posts

Home