Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Will Richard Primus Get the Readership He Deserves (and the Country Needs)?
|
Thursday, July 10, 2025
Will Richard Primus Get the Readership He Deserves (and the Country Needs)?
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization Symposium on Richard Primus, The Oldest Constitutional Question: Enumeration and Federal Power (Harvard University Press, 2025). Sandy Levinson
In
February I contributed, under the title Who Is The Audience For This Book?, to a Balkinization symposium
on Zack Price’s Constitutional
Symmetry: Judging in a Divided Republic. I
did not mean to be snarky or to criticize what is in fact an interesting
book. My point was simple,
perhaps even simplistic: The book was in
effect a plea to the members of the Supreme Court to mend their ways and to
adopt a more self-consciously politically “symmetrical” approach when writing
opinions, especially in cases that touched on polarizing issues. Thus, I argued, it really didn’t matter what
the general response might be to Price’s arguments, many of which were
certainly compelling, if the justices themselves did not read his book and
change their behavior accordingly. Instead,
it might be just another “academic” book, comparable, in its own way, to a
missive thrown into the vast ocean with the hope that someone will find it and
read it. So this brings me to my altogether heartfelt
blurb that can be found on the back jacket of what I describe as “Richard
Primus’s stunning book” The Oldest Constitutional Question. It is a landmark achievement in both the history
and theory of the American constitutional order. With meticulous attention to
historical sources and beautifully argued analysis, he upends many decades of
conventional wisdom about the nature of national power, including the
remarkably unexamined cliché that the Constitution created only a limited
government of enumerated powers. No one, including members of the Supreme
Court, can be truly literate about these issues without grappling with Primus’s
arguments and evidence. I could end my own contribution to this
symposium now. For the major point is
that anyone hoping to profess literacy about the nature of the Constitution must
read Primus’s book in its entirety and not, as is so often (and
understandably) the case, rely on symposia like this one to serve as an
adequate substitute. Life is short, and way too many books, not to mention
articles, compete for our scarce attention.
Most probably do not have to be read fully and carefully in order for
one to grasp their arguments, become tolerably familiar with their strengths
and weaknesses, and then move on to the next competitor for time. This one does, not least because it
successfully “upends many decades of conventional wisdom about the nature of
national power.” To be told the argument
in bare outline—that everything we’ve accepted as the simple ontological
reality of a “limited Constitution of assigned (and enumerated) powers” is
basically wrong—will scarcely be accepted without submission to the
overwhelming evidence that Primus brings forth.
One can readily anticipate a great deal of resistance to his argument. After all, can it really be true that much of
what we’ve been taught (and teach) is mistaken? That is not a conclusion easily
to be accepted. It is as if one were a traditional Newtonian physicist
in the mid-1920s being confronted by the strange and disruptive ideas
identified with quantum physics. As
Thomas Kuhn suggested in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, science
(and intellectual life more broadly) can hardly be described under the placid
metaphor of a conversation where the better idea, as Habermas might suggest, is
accepted simply because it is better and adherents of the older, and now
disproved, ways of thinking are “good losers” who readily concede the
point. Instead, “conventional wisdom”
has a decided power of its own, and challenges to it are far more likely to be
dismissed, sometimes angrily, rather than accepted with equanimity. The best explanation for changes in
“conventional wisdom” is that adherents of the old (and intellectually
defeated) paradigms retire or die, while newcomers socialized to the new truths
take their positions (and mold the consciousness of future generations accordingly). Life tenure in office may be good for those
who have such job security, but it is not at all clear that it is conducive to
what is sometimes labeled intellectual “progress.” Primus’s argument is far more radical than a
simple recognition, conceded by many who are not happy with the work product of
the Supreme Court since the New Deal, that the doctrine of “enumerated powers”
as a genuine limit on what the national government can do has not proved truly
successful. Ernest Young, for example,
has written of the near futility of relying on this doctrine to claw back
contemporary congressional power. Anyone
who teaches “constitutional law” must teach that Congress, especially through
the Commerce Clause, has a de facto “national police power.” There are, to be sure, some trouble cases,
especially the Sebelius case in which a majority of the Court rejected
the validity, under the Commerce Clause, of the Affordable Care Act’s
requirement that the citizenry purchase medical insurance. But, of course, Chief Justice Roberts pulled
the taxing power out of the doctrinal hat to uphold the Act, much to the
consternation of many conservatives, including, of course, the four angry
dissenters. But the point is that Primus is doing far
more than offering a descriptive account of the Court and making the obvious
point that many of its decisions are hard to explain within the rubric of
“enumerated powers” as a genuine limitation on governmental activity. He does not, incidentally, proffer the
foolish argument that the national government therefore “can do whatever it
wants to.” Like all liberals, he does
believe in limited government. But
the limits come from explicit prohibitions, including those in Article I,
Section 9 or, most importantly, within the Bill of Rights and some other
amendments added well after 1787 and not from inferences to be drawn
from the enumeration of powers set out in Article I. I write as someone thoroughly convinced by
Primus’s careful research. Already I
have assigned part of the book in a course on federalism that I taught in the
spring of 2025 and will teach again in 2026.
I now view as “inoperative” the contrast that I used to draw between a
national government with enumerated powers and state governments with basically
unlimited powers save for those explicitly entrenched upon by the constitution’s
text. My hope is that all other legal
academics will change their own syllabi accordingly. But, frankly, it may not matter all that
much, at least in the foreseeable future, how successful Primus may be in
affecting the way that legal academics think, write, and teach. For the reality of our constitutional system
is that the majority of the nine members of the United Supreme Court are
empowered to engage in what John Austin called “performative utterances” that
serve to constitute the legal reality within which we operate. It is misleading to refer to their writings
as mere “opinions,” for that suggests, as in conversations among equals, that
one is altogether free to reject what is being opined because, after all, it
rests on demonstrably shaky, even false, assumptions. Instead, if one is writing a majority opinion
“for the Court,” thinking—or writing—can in fact create the legal reality
regardless of what dissenters, whether on the Court or in the outside world,
might justifiably think. Alexander
Bickel once referred to the Supreme Court as a “vital national seminar.” If so, it is one led by a decidedly
authoritarian leader who demands that his utterances be accepted as definitive
and who will have no compunction in failing any student who dares to suggest
otherwise. Purported participants are
not taking part in a genuine dialogue, but, rather, might be analogized to
those petitioning the Czar, or even to inhabitants of a Kafka novel, hoping
that the all-powerful director will deign to read their missives and
then—perhaps, but who really knows—to be influenced by their pleas. There is an old joke on what one calls the
person who graduates last in his class at medical school. The answer, of course, is “doctor.” Similarly, one can ask what we call the
stipulations of a majority opinion with which we might vehemently
disagree. The answer, alas, is “the
law.” To paraphrase Elena Kagan’s
(in)famous statement about “textualism,” “we are all positivists now” at least
in this specific sense. Just as
libertarians like Randy Barnett readily conceded that the New Deal decisions
established “the law of the land” even as he (like Robert Bork) criticized
their validity if one believed that they violated the original meaning (however
defined) of the 1787 Constitution, so must contemporary liberals like myself
reluctantly accept the legal status of a variety of decisions that we find
abhorrent. Even constitutional
“protestants” like myself, who reject the arguments undergirding “judicial
supremacy,” must nevertheless teach our students that we do live in a
largely “catholic” jurisprudential culture where opinions of the Supreme Court
are indeed treated as “law.” Indeed, at
the present moment, when one regularly expresses fear that Donald J. Trump will
defy judicial orders, it is especially fraught to suggest that judicial
opinions should have to be fully persuasive in order to be binding. And “the law” includes not only the barebones
commands, but also in many ways the intellectual scaffolding, including views
of our history, by which the Court purports to justify those commands. I can well remember, as an impressionable
youth in college and even graduate school, being swept away by Justice Hugo
Black’s historical account of the First Amendment. Only much later did I realize that there were
problems in his account, however inspiring it might have been. Under no circumstances today would I advise a
student to emulate my own past credulousness with regard to the “history”
offered within the pages of the United States Reports. But then, of course, the question becomes
whom can one trust to provide authoritative accounts of what Jack Balkin
identifies our constitutive historical memories? Whatever my own esteem for his book, as a
practical matter it is not enough for Primus to persuade his fellow academics
of the validity of his argument. There
is an 800-pound gorilla in the room with regard to issuing pronouncements about
our Constitution. So Primus must, in
effect, also persuade at least five members of the Supreme Court to upend much
of their established jurisprudence going back at least as far as McCulloch
v. Maryland. It was there, after
all, that John Marshall, even if granting enormous power to Congress under the
“necessary and proper” clause, for whatever reason took pains to remind his
audience that “[t]his Government is acknowledged by all to be one
of enumerated powers…[;] that principle is now universally admitted.” To be sure, he immediately went on to
acknowledge that “the question respecting the extent of the powers actually
granted is perpetually arising, and will probably continue to arise so long as
our system shall exist.” But, for better or, quite definitely, for worse, his
“universally admitted” principle has endured as a linchpin of what we call
“constitutional interpretation.” Primus is here to remind us, however, that
Marshall could often be an intellectual bully, claiming “universal” recognition
of some principle that was in fact highly (and legitimately) disputed. And Primus brings forth all the evidence that
one should need in order to demonstrate exactly how mistaken was the “Great
Chief Justice.” But, of course, Marshall earned his title, whatever we might
think of it, precisely because so many of his utterances, however sometimes
orphic, have served as performatives to establish the very framework of our
legal conversations. It is one thing to
question an utterance by Morrison Waite, perhaps the most obscure of our chief
justices, or by Roger Taney, whose legacy was permanently tarnished by Dred
Scott and whom it is tempting to demonize as a rogue justice with nothing
to tell us about the Constitution. It is
too threatening to our culture of constitutional “veneration” to acknowledge
the possibility that Taney was offering a plausible interpretation of a
Constitution that was, after all, a “covenant with death and an agreement with
hell,” as argued by William Lloyd Garrison and the early Frederick
Douglass. But challenging John Marshall, who is treated
within the legal academy as a de facto Founding Father, is quite another
matter! It is difficult indeed to
suggest that one’s father was fundamentally in error and merits our own
rejection. That is the task that
Primus is engaged in. He is swimming
upstream—and inviting his readers to join him—against a mighty current of
conventional wisdom founded on two centuries of Supreme Court utterances and
repetition by those teaching students how to “think like constitutional
lawyers” which has become synonymous with accepting the premises of
enumerationism. So, as a practical matter, just as with Zack
Price’s book, the key question is not how many sales he will make among
his fellow academics, but, instead, whether members of the Supreme Court will
read it with requisite care and genuinely learn its lessons. Ideally, five members of the Court
would realize the error of their commitment to conventional wisdom, but one
might more realistically hope that even one will embark on a sustained mission
to educate his or her colleagues. If one
took seriously the claims of the current majority to be guided by
“originalism,” however defined, then one might assume that at least one of them
would in fact be eager to read a book published by a leading university press
and authored by an eminent constitutional scholar at the peak of his powers. But, frankly, it is quite impossible to take
most of their claims seriously. None of
the justices exhibits any of the particular talents and intellectual discipline
one associates with being a professional historian or even a gifted
amateur. John Roberts might have majored
in history at Harvard before graduating in 1976, but there is no evidence
whatsoever that he has any deep understanding or abiding interest in American
history. And he is not alone. Amy Barrett majored in English literature and
minored in French at Rhodes College. One
might applaud these as intellectual interests, but they are scarcely pathways
to deep historical knowledge of the American past. Nor, incidentally, do the justices seem
interested in hiring clerks with disciplined training in American history. Mark Tushnet once referred to the phenomenon of “lawyers
as astrophysicists.” He did not mean to be offering a compliment. Rather, he was adverting to the belief by
smart, and overly confident, lawyers that they could master anything in a long
weekend. Actual professional training
was irrelevant, even if lawyers themselves were often quick to attack any
pronouncements on “the law” offered by the laity. So it is with the Court and American
history. They read what they want to
read and, more the point, like many mere mortals, mine what they read in order
to bolster their own priors. How often
do any of us—and I use the pronoun advisedly—actually “change our minds” with
regard to some fundamental beliefs simply by virtue of reading a book and being
convinced by the sheer force of argument that we were wrong and must mend our
intellectual ways? Primus certainly changed my mind, but it would be
inaccurate to say that I was truly deeply invested in the “enumerationist” narrative
of American constitutionalism. I usually
taught it as indeed conventional wisdom; I chided my colleague Calvin Johnson,
who disdained any reliance on “enumerated powers,” as insufficiently
nuanced. I would go on, as a political
scientist/lawyer, to note how little “enumerationism” really contributed to our
understanding of contemporary constitutional law, especially since the New
Deal. But that was not intended to
disconfirm the historical importance of how the Constitution had been imagined
by an earlier generation. Primus forces
the diligent reader to revise this account of the historical imagination. But what if I were a Supreme Court justice, even
a liberal one? Would I emulate Louis
Brandeis and overthrow not only 100 years of error, but, in fact, at least two
centuries of misunderstanding reflected in a myriad of Supreme Court decisions
and the teachings of the legal academy? After
all, no one, least of all anyone advocating in behalf of a liberal reading of
the Constitution, has been willing to affirm that the Constitution, correctly
understood, does basically establish plenary power for Congress save for
explicit prohibitions. Consider the fact
that there was widespread agreement that first Drew Days and then Donald
Vereilli “lost their arguments” before the Supreme Court in the Lopez
case in 1995 and then Sibelius in 2012 by being unable to offer an
answer to the question “is there anything that Congress can’t do under
your theory of the Commerce Power?” Thus
the importance of the infamous “broccoli” hypothetical in the latter case. Neither lawyer, including Days, a
distinguished member of the Yale Law School faculty, was willing to say, in
effect, “yes, Justice X, you’re right, Congress does have plenary power under
Article I, save for the specific limitations set out. Otherwise, John Hart Ely was right. We are ultimately reliant on the good sense
of the American people not to require the eating of broccoli rather than on
strained interpretations by judges of the meaning of commerce.” And the dissenters in those two cases,
clearly frustrated with the majority’s cramped view of the Commerce Power, were
unwilling to dismiss “enumerationism.” Will
anything change now that Primus has in fact given them—and all of us—more than
enough intellectual ammunition to bury the doctrine? The
answer will tell us much about how intellectual revolutions do (or do not)
occur. Perhaps someone writing in 2050
will look back on Primus’s work as the foundation of a “long, melancholy roar”
by which the assumptions of an earlier generation were upended and ultimately
replaced. Jonathan Gienapp’s wonderful
book Against Constitutional Originalism:
A Historical Critique might also receive similar acknowledgement as
a truly transformational work. But will changes in academic consciousness
necessarily be reflected in the pages of the United States Reports? That will take many new appointments
of justices themselves educated to question the assumptions that are now taken
for granted. When Trumpistas call for
greater intellectual “diversity” within the legal academy, are they thinking of
someone like Primus? Or, instead, do
they insist only that “originalists” who in fact know relatively little about
history be appointed to the judiciary and continue to take aim at the “New Deal
Settlement” or the Civil Rights Revolution because of altogether dubious
accounts of a singular “original public meaning” ostensibly present in 1787? There
is no doubt that Richard Primus has written a book for the ages at least within
the circle of scholars of the United States Constitution. It is, in its own way, comparable to some of
the books written after World War II that exploded the hold that the Dunning
School had on the presentation of Reconstruction and, therefore, the history of
the Reconstruction Amendments. As Steve
Griffin wrote in a recent review of books by Balkin, Gienapp, and Mark Graber,
“one of the lessons of Reconstruction-era scholarship is that one of the most
important tasks historians can perform is ‘myth-busting’—challenging what we
think we know, generating new insights by excavating long-buried assumptions of
entire bodies of constitutional doctrine and bringing into question common
assumptions that undergird the legal profession’s everyday work.” Primus’s book certainly qualifies as a
“myth-busing” effort to challenge deeply embedded assumptions. But it remains to be seen whether the most institutionally
important potential audience for his book will bother to read it and, more to
the point, acknowledge the extent to which it requires a genuine
transformation—and intellectual revolution—in the way we conceive of the
Constitution. John Marshall was correct when
he reminded us of the importance that “it is a constitution we are
expounding.” For far too long we have
expounded it within the framework of “enumerationism.” Even if we might expect, perhaps naively,
that academics would be able to liberate themselves from a very powerful
intellectual status quo built up over generations, can we expect the same of
members of the Supreme Court, even those who might themselves have spent time
as legal academics?
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |