E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Abortion Rights as Health Care Rights as Equality Rights
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization Symposium on Legal Pathways Beyond Dobbs.
B. Jessie Hill
After Dobbs
eradicated liberty as a basis for the abortion right, an obvious and pressing
question is whether an alternative framing for that right might find more
purchase, either with state courts interpreting their own state constitutions,
or with the federal courts. This question is presented with particular urgency
in the context of post-Dobbs litigation, which in many instances is
geared toward protecting access to abortion in cases where the patient’s health
is endangered, in states that ban abortion in nearly all circumstances.
Two
principal alternative framings for the abortion right, which have long existed
alongside the liberty (or privacy) framing, are health care and equality. That
is to say, access to abortion may be understood as an aspect of a broader right
to access health care, which—as I argue below—has been recognized in at least
some circumstances. Or the abortion right may be grounded in sex equality, as
an aspect of women’s right to equal dignity and citizenship. Notwithstanding Dobbs’s
gratuitous rejection of an equal protection argument for abortion that no party
raised or briefed, scholars such as Reva Siegel and Cary Franklin have forcefully
shown that this legal basis retains vitality even today.
Drawing on both framings, I argue
here that the right to abortion is best understood as a right to equality in
health care, or a right to health care nondiscrimination.
To
understand the relationship between equality and health care in the abortion
context, it’s important first to understand how abortion can be understood as
part of a more general right to access health care. While a right to access
health care may sound novel, it is in fact well-established and longstanding.
Indeed, as Reva Siegel and Mary Ziegler argue in a forthcoming
article, there is a substantial “history and tradition,” around and before
the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, permitting the provision of
life-saving and health-preserving medical care, including abortions, even when
that care might be criminalized in other, so-called “elective” circumstances.
Moreover, as Eugene
Volokh and Ieach argued in articles published in 2007,
this history and tradition has a clear doctrinal and constitutional foothold. This
doctrinal grounding is evident in the Supreme Court’s recognition in Roe v.
Wade of a right to end a pregnancy when the patient’s life or health is at
risk—even postviability, when the state’s interest in potential life may be
considered compelling—which is analytically separate from the right to
reproductive autonomy recognized by Roe and its progeny. But the right
is also implied in cases dealing with vaccination and
access to potentially
lethal doses of medication to alleviate physical suffering. Professor
Volokh argues that it is grounded in the constitutional and common-law
self-defense right—a right whose foundation has only become stronger since the
U.S. Supreme Court’s rulings in D.C. v. Heller and McDonald v. City
of Chicago, extolling the fundamental nature of the right to self-defense. And
it is notable that numerous state constitutions include protections for the
right to life,
for self-defense,
and even for the protection of health.
But a
right-to-health or “medical
self-defense” approach to abortion is incomplete without an equality lens.
Equality arguments should be mobilized to complement the understanding of the
right to abortion an aspect of the right to health care. For example, scholars
such as Maya
Manian and Katie
Watson argue for abortion rights as an aspect of health justice. As they have
demonstrated, abortion access is shaped by the same sorts of disparities that
affect other kinds of health care access, underscoring that the harms of
restrictive policies fall primarily on marginalized groups and highlighting the
harms to both individual and public health that arise from a lack of access.
Thus, Manian argues, a “health-justice approach” is needed, taking account of
structural inequalities and the social determinants of health.
But the equality arguments can also
be crafted in more explicitly doctrinal terms. If the right to protect one’s
health is fundamental, it must be available on nondiscriminatory terms,
according to the fundamental rights strain of equal protection doctrine. Thus,
for example, a right cannot be available to one sex and not the other; it is
discriminatory to recognize a self-defense right except when a condition that
primarily affects one sex—pregnancy—is involved. But it is also discriminatory
to grant individuals the fundamental right to protect their lives and health
when they suffer from physical conditions, for example, but not mental health
conditions, as the North
Dakota Supreme Court recently suggested. In fact, the equality lens, as
applied to the right to health care, ultimately requires dismantling the
elective-therapeutic distinction regarding abortion, since the distinction
itself is a product of sexism. The only way an abortion for family-planning
purposes can be considered “elective” rather than “therapeutic” is by devaluing
the right of women to chart their life course, and to make medical decisions
that support that chosen course. Such reasons are accepted as a legitimate basis
for medical intervention in other contexts, such
as when an older individual chooses knee replacement surgery so they can
continue to have an active lifestyle.
This combined
equality and right-to-health approach to abortion requires further refinement,
and it may require significant education of judges who are entrenched in the
therapeutic-elective distinction, which assumes pregnancy as a natural and
therefore healthy state except when it poses particular kinds of threats to a
pregnant person’s physical wellbeing. It is also unclear whether, and how far,
this right extends beyond one’s ability to prevent death or serious physical
harm. But it may also hold the promise of opening a new path to reproductive
rights as an aspect of the fundamental constitutional rights to self-defense
and equality.
B. Jessie Hill is Judge Ben C. Green Professor of Law at Case Western Reserve University School of Law. You can reach her by e-mail at bjh11@case.edu.