Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Gloss and Practice: Reading Bradley Through the Lens of Hart and Dworkin
|
Sunday, January 19, 2025
Gloss and Practice: Reading Bradley Through the Lens of Hart and Dworkin
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization Symposium on Curtis A. Bradley, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice (Harvard University Press, 2024). Richard Fallon
Curtis Bradley’s book Historical
Gloss and Foreign Affairs: Constitutional Authority in Practice will be
welcomed as an indispensable resource for anyone seeking to understand the
constitutional law of the United States as it bears on foreign affairs. Among the book’s contributions, it provides an
engaging description of the potentially disputable powers that Presidents and
Congress have respectively asserted, and about the arguments that they have
advanced in support of their positions, over the sweep of history. At the very least, Historical Gloss and
Foreign Affairs thus establishes how de facto constitutional authority has
historically been distributed. Bradley, however, goes
a step further. His central, formally
stated thesis holds that the historical practices of Presidents and Congress can
become valid sources of interpretive authority in subsequent constitutional
disputes. Bradley offers multiple case
studies in which he takes historical practice of the President and Congress, as
much as that of the courts, to have resolved “ambiguities” and “fill[ed] gaps”
in the constitutional text. And
sometimes, he writes, a form of practice that he calls “gloss” “largely
supersedes (or at least overshadows) the text.” According to him, examples of “gloss” can be
seen in the widespread recognition that the President can negotiate treaties
without seeking “advice” from the Senate in any formal sense “and, more
dramatically,” in the widely shared understanding that the President can bind
the nation via executive agreements rather than treaties. (pp. 192–93) If Bradley had cast his book as a political
history of the assertion of legally disputable powers, or as a sociological
account of when the President and Congress are likely to acquiesce in
assertions of authority by other actors, it would seem to me to be wholly
persuasive. But insofar as Bradley
claims that “gloss” makes “law” or establishes a source of legal authority in
constitutional argument — and, equally importantly, that historical practice by
the President and Congress that fails to meet his definition of gloss has no
similar law-altering effect — a bit more caution may be in order. To assess Bradley’s claim that “gloss” can
alter or establish constitutional law, we need a jurisprudential theory of what
“law” is and of when and how “practice” can make or change it or authorize
Presidents and Congress to make or change it.
As I read Historical
Gloss and Foreign Affairs, Bradley never definitively embraces a
jurisprudential theory nor provides explicit answers to the question of how
certain practices of the President and Congress can achieve law-altering status. At a very general level, however, he appears
to assume the correctness of some version of practice-based jurisprudential
theory. As used in reference to
practice-based theories of law, the term “practice” refers to or describes an
activity that is constituted by the convergent or overlapping understandings,
intentions, and expectations of multiple participants. Baseball and chess are practices in this
sense. And so, according to
practice-based theories, is law. As
practice-based theorists would emphasize, the ideas of a President, a Congress,
courts, and a Constitution all depend on shared understandings among
participants in our political system about what these offices or institutions
are and what they can lawfully do. The
fact that a text — the written Constitution — refers to those offices or
institutions or describes their powers cannot provide the ultimate grounding of
their legal authority in the absence of deeper, shared assumptions about the
text’s exclusive or less-than-exclusive authority. In other words, a text such as the
Constitution can stipulate offices and institutions into existence only insofar
as relevant constituencies share assumptions and attitudes about the text’s status
as a source of norms and treat those norms as providing reasons for action. Although the assumption
that law is a practice in the sense in which legal philosophers use the term furnishes
the background to most of Bradley’s arguments in Historical Gloss and
Foreign Affairs, he often speaks of “practice” and “practices” in a second,
more quotidian sense. In this second
sense, practices are the familiar patterns of activity of people and
institutions — including legal and political officials — in going about their
professional lives. Using the term practice
in this sense, we can say, for example, that it is the practice of Presidents
or Congress to do certain things, including acting as if they had lawful
authority to do those things, and for lawyers to make certain kinds of
arguments in defending or contesting claims of presidential or congressional authority. Within practice-based
theories of law, there is no inherent reason why some practices in this second
sense could not have the capacity to shape, alter, establish, or constitute law. It is certainly a possibility that “gloss”
might have the status and effect that Bradley says that it does in the United
States if relevant participants in our practice view it in the way that Bradley
claims. But it is also evident, even if
we assume that the best theory of law is practice-based, that not all practices
of all officials (in the quotidian sense) have this lawmaking or law-constituting
effect. Once again, whether they do or
do not depends on the understandings and attitudes that constitute the law of
the United States when the U.S. legal system is understood as a practice in the
first, quasi-philosophical sense of that term. Nothing that I have
said so far is intended to register disagreement with Bradley. Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs is
very explicit that not all practices of political officials, such as Presidents
and members of Congress, and the lawyers arguing on their behalf, establish,
shape, or alter the law. To the
contrary, as I have said, it is Bradley’s stated thesis that practice in the
domain of foreign affairs has lawmaking effect only when it meets the criteria
to count as what he calls “gloss” on the text of the written Constitution. But he acknowledges that “[t]here is no
canonical account of the historical gloss approach to constitutional
interpretation.” (p. 25) Based on “[a]
review of the ways in which [the term ‘gloss’] has typically been invoked by courts
and other interpreters,” Bradley posits at one point that a pattern of practice
by the President or Congress acquires the status of legally authoritative gloss
only when it satisfies “three general requirements.” It must be “(1) governmental practice (2)
that is longstanding and (3) concerning which the affected branch of government”—that
is, any branch that might plausibly have thought that an assertion of power by
another branch intruded on its power—"has acquiesced.” (pp. 25-26) But he then quickly qualifies the second and
especially the third of those demands as, for example, when he says that “[a]n
interbranch agreement about constitutional meaning is not required for gloss,
although evidence of such an agreement will bolster the case for deferring to
the practice.” (p. 30) He also appears
to insist that gloss, even when it exists, is not a permanently binding source
of interpretive authority: “[G]loss is not necessarily permanent. At least in theory, what is glossed can be
reglossed.” (p. 28) Because Bradley’s claims
about the legal status and effect of “gloss” are not self-evidently true, readers
who want to appraise them will have to confront the jurisprudential question on
which I said earlier that he takes no explicit stand. To recast that assertion in slightly more
critical terms, avoidance of jurisprudential questions becomes untenable when a
question about the grounds of law — or about how we could ascertain whether a
legal claim is true — arises. And
Bradley’s claims raise a multitude of questions about the legal effects of
presidential and congressional practices.
There is the obvious question whether it is true as a matter of law that
any kind of practice by the President or Congress (in the quotidian sense) can acquire
the status of legal authority capable of altering the Constitution’s properly
ascribed meaning. And if the answer to
that question is affirmative in some cases, readers will want to know
which. More pointedly, they will want to
know how to tell who is right and who is wrong when participants in our
constitutional practice disagree about which practices (in the non-technical sense)
have potentially law-altering authority within our constitutional practice (in
the more technical, quasi-philosophical sense). Although there are many possible frameworks
within which to seek answers to these jurisprudential questions, I shall
consider just two. Some
textual evidence in Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs suggests that Bradley
thinks the strand of legal positivism pioneered by H.L.A. Hart furnishes the
necessary jurisprudential underpinnings for his central legal claims. According to Hart, law or a legal system is a
network of rules that are held together by a master “rule [or rules] of
recognition.” (See The Concept
of Law pp. 92, 94-95, 105-110 (3d ed.)) As described by Hart, the most fundamental
rule or rules of recognition are “social rules,” existing as a matter of
sociological fact, that are fixed by the convergent attitudes and practices of
relevant officials. Bradley notes that
his argument is compatible with Hartian positivism at two places in Historical
Gloss and Foreign Affairs even though he does not explicitly endorse that
theory in either instance. At one point in
Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs, Bradley suggests — though he stops
just short of saying — that a Hartian rule of recognition identifies “gloss” as
a source of legal authority. He writes: [U]nder prominent jurisprudential accounts most
famously associated with H.L.A. Hart, what is ‘law’ is determined by how the participants
in the system understand the relevant ‘rules of recognition.’ As this book has
shown, gloss is considered by the participants in our system as relevant to
constitutional interpretation. (p. 193) As I read Bradley’s book,
however, the historical evidence that it adduces fails to support his claim that
there is a convergent practice of judges and other officials in recognizing
that practices by the President and Congress that meet his vague criteria for gloss
are valid sources of authority in constitutional interpretation but that other
practices by the President, Congress, and constitutional lawyers are not
similarly valid sources of authority. As Bradley recognizes, some participants in our
constitutional system deny that post-ratification practice by Congress and the
President can alter or establish constitutional law at all, especially when the
practice contravenes what they take to be the Constitution’s original meaning. And other participants would ascribe legal
significance to “gloss” as defined by the relatively stringent criteria by
which Bradley says gloss has “typically” been defined but not if it is defined as
not requiring interbranch “acquiescence” or “agreement.” Under these circumstances, I do not believe
that Hart’s theory could underwrite
Bradley’s claim that “gloss,” especially when defined as loosely as Bradley
ultimately appears to define it, provides constitutionally valid support for
arguments about the scope of presidential and congressional power. Bradley might counter
that there is widespread, convergent agreement on a very vaguely defined rule
of recognition such as “at least some, even if not all, practices of the
President and Congress rise to the level of sources of authority for adopting
or altering interpretations of the written Constitution.” But even if so, his argument that a rule of
recognition ascribes singular significance to “gloss” as he defines it would remain
unsupported. An
alternative jurisprudential foundation for Bradley’s arguments about gloss
could imaginably come from the work of Ronald Dworkin. Dworkin was even more explicit than Hart in
characterizing law as a “practice.” (See Law’s Empire pp. 45–53) But he vehemently denied that law can be
accurately described as constituted by “rules,” and he specifically sought to
debunk the Hartian idea that “rules of recognition” exist as social rules fixed
by overwhelming consensus among judges and other relevant officials. Rejecting those ideas, Dworkin characterized legal
practice as deeply “argumentative.” When
lawyers and judges disagree about such matters as whether and if so when
practice (in the quotidian sense) establishes a valid foundation for legal
arguments, Dworkin maintained that they are engaged in “constructive
interpretation” of their society’s irreducibly argumentative practice of law
(in the jurisprudential sense). Interpreters,
Dworkin posited, try to find an interpretation that fits tolerably well with past
events occurring within legal practice and that also, at the same time, portrays
law in the normatively best light in which it can be portrayed. Unlike Hart, Dworkin did not expect that the
best legal arguments would always reflect or rest on consensus understandings. Whereas Hart insisted that rules of
recognition are “social rules,” Dworkin’s account of legal interpretation was moralized
— in the sense of requiring normative judgments of what would be “best.” In Dworkin’s theory of law, all of the
questions about “gloss” to which Bradley’s argument gives rise have “one right
answer,” which is the one given by the “best” constructive interpretation of
U.S. legal practice (whatever that best interpretation might be). But we also need to accept that interpreters
are likely to differ about what that one right answer is. Although Bradley
nowhere refers to Dworkin in Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs, his
argument concerning the distinctive importance of gloss in the constitutional law
involving foreign affairs could easily be characterized in Dworkinian terms. Early in the book, Bradley offers normative
arguments for according gloss the kind of significance that he ascribes to
it. These include normative reasons for
thinking that practices satisfying the vague and possibly defeasible criteria by
which “gloss” is defined, including acquiescence, are more likely to reflect
accreted wisdom about the practical requirements of effective government than
other past practices of the President or Congress. (pp. 12–15, 25–30) In addition, Bradley self-consciously crafts
his thesis about “gloss” to achieve what he evidently regards as a reasonable
“fit” with what has historically happened both in the courts and in public
debates about the scope of presidential and congressional powers. If
we viewed Bradley’s argument as Dworkinian in form, or as capable of being
reframed in Dworkinian terms, the question would of course remain whether it
was more persuasive than other arguments that also could be cast in a
Dworkinian mode. I shall not pursue that
question here in any depth. Working out
the details of the analysis would be challenging. That said, I am inclined to believe that
Bradley’s argument for the distinctive legal significance of gloss (as he
defines it) in U.S. constitutional practice would be more persuasive if we
assume the validity of Dworkin’s jurisprudential theory than if we posit the correctness
of Hart’s. If so, then an
assessment of whether Bradley is correct as a matter of law about the
significance of “gloss” would appear to depend on whether Dworkin’s theory offers
a correct account of the grounds on which legal claims should be adjudged either
true or not true. Followers of Hart, and
adherents of some other theories as well, would of course answer in the
negative. This, obviously, is not the
time or place for me to advance and defend a general jurisprudential theory. In other writing, however, I have expressed
more sympathy for Hart’s general jurisprudential theory than for Dworkin’s. And anyone who shares that judgement is
likely to conclude, as I do, that Bradley’s argument for defining gloss in the
vague way that he does and for crediting it as thus defined with the legally distinctive
force that he ascribes to it (in comparison with other past presidential and
congressional practices) is unproved. How damning is this
conclusion? The answer seems to me to
depend on issues of perspective and emphasis.
On the one hand, Historical Gloss and Foreign Affairs does not
persuade me that “gloss,” as Bradley loosely defines it, possesses a unique,
law-changing capacity that other practice-based arguments do not possess as a
matter of constitutional law. On the
other hand, Bradley is indubitably convincing that lawyers make lots of
practice-based arguments, including ones that satisfy his criteria for
constituting “gloss,” and I understand the nature of their debates much better
after reading his book. My own
conclusion, which is deeply informed by the evidence that Bradley adduces, is
that when Presidents, members of Congress, and their defenders make
constitutional arguments based on different kinds of practices (in the
quotidian sense), different lawyers, judges, and members of public and
political audiences are likely to respond differently. Some will share Bradley’s view of what
constitutes gloss and of the legal significance that gloss, as so defined, uniquely
possesses. But others will not. And whose argument will prevail in any
particular case will likely depend on contingencies that may be unpredictable
in advance. If constitutional law is a
practice (in the jurisprudential sense), as I agree with Bradley that it is, then
it is, in my view, the kind of practice that must be expected to evolve over
time. It is based on this
view of the nature of our constitutional law that I ultimately find Historical
Gloss and Foreign Affairs to be as helpful, important, and even potentially
indispensable as I said it is at the beginning of this comment. Going forward, no competent lawyer arguing
about presidential and congressional authority over foreign affairs, and no
searching student of constitutional law, will be able to ignore Bradley’s historical
case studies and analytical insights. And
for many purposes, it is more important to understand the argumentative
techniques that participants in high-stakes constitutional arguments deploy,
and will continue to deploy because of their likely persuasive effects, than it
is to know whether their arguments are based on valid sources of legal
authority in the sense that Hart and Dworkin debated. Richard Fallon is Story Professor of Law, Harvard
Law School. You can reach him by e-mail at rfallon@law.harvard.edu.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |