Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts The Collective-Action Constitution and the Community of Legal Scholars
|
Saturday, September 14, 2024
The Collective-Action Constitution and the Community of Legal Scholars
Neil Siegel
For the Balkinization Symposium on Neil S. Siegel, The Collective-Action Constitution (Oxford University Press, 2024) In The Collective-Action Constitution, I use what I have learned in law, history, political science, and economics to offer a broad, deep theory of the U.S. Constitution’s federal structure. I argue that the Constitution’s primary structural purpose, both originally and today, is to empower the federal government to solve collective-action problems for the states and to prevent the states from undermining those solutions or causing such problems. That main structural purpose is reflected in, and reinforced by, Chief Justice Marshall’s two holdings for the U.S. Supreme Court in McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316 (1819), that (1) Congress may create a national bank, thereby facilitating the solution of multi-state collective-action problems; and (2) states may not tax it, thereby preventing states from interfering with those solutions or creating collective-action problems. Any faithful account of what the Constitution is for and how it should be interpreted, I contend, should include that main structural function. In a fundamental—albeit not complete—sense, the U.S. Constitution is the Collective-Action Constitution. If Americans do not recognize that truth, I maintain, government cannot adequately address the sobering problems facing the U.S. today. Examples include foreign aggression, unlawful immigration, terrorism, nuclear proliferation, inadequate access to health care, climate change, pandemics, opioid addiction, gun violence, racism, other bigotry, income inequality, and political extremism. I thank Professors Jack Balkin and Erin Delaney for organizing and participating in this symposium on the book. I also thank Professors Jessica Bulman-Pozen, Guy-Uriel Charles, Tara Leigh Grove, Richard Re, and David Strauss for their characteristically smart, generous, and constructively critical contributions to the symposium. Reading their posts has been a humbling experience, and not only because of the eminence of the authors. Their insights remind me that the more I study the U.S. Constitution and judge-made constitutional law, the more aware I become of how much I have to learn about what one of my law teachers, Professor Robert Post, and I once called “our indispensable and yet ultimately mysterious Constitution.” I worked on the book for more than five years, wrote almost five hundred pages (after cutting more than 30,000 gratuitous words), and ultimately deemed relevant many more provisions, principles, precedents, ideas, and debates than I had initially imagined. Yet, as I note in the Conclusion, I largely neglected important subjects that are also relevant to the structural account offered in the book, including personal jurisdiction, state sovereign immunity, and state secession. Some symposium contributors usefully underscore additional subjects that are pertinent to a collective-action account of the Constitution. For example, Professor Bulman-Pozen emphasizes the centrality of the modern administrative state to the mission of the Collective-Action Constitution. She is right that I did not adequately pursue that topic. As Professor Balkin implies, however, my emphasis on Congress’s primary role in solving multi-state collective-action problems is intended to include a defense of what he calls “Congress’s construction of the administrative state.” And as Professor Bulman-Pozen notes, the book criticizes the Court’s major questions doctrine for making it even harder for the Congress that wrote the laws in question—not the current Congress, as Professor Re appears to suggest—to provide for the solution of multi-state collective-action problems over time by using broad language that delegates authority to expert agencies. It is hard enough for Congress to solve such problems given today’s politics; the Court’s doctrine, including its overruling of Chevron, adds additional impediments to collective action. I therefore conclude the book by cautioning the federal judiciary “not to substantially restrict federal authority in the years ahead, whether through constitutional-law rulings concerning congressional power or administrative-law rulings regarding agency power.” Given the historical forces that have produced an ideologically and affectively polarized national politics and constant razor’s-edge elections, I agree with Professor Grove that restoring Congress’s key role in the constitutional scheme will require much more than my reluctant suggestion to abandon the legislative filibuster in the Senate. I appreciate her reminder of the work that she, Professor Vicki Jackson, and I have done on developing a constitutional role morality for elected officials. And I find moving her subtle suggestion that we might be more mindful of how we talk about Congress as an institution. As I note in the book, Congress still legislates today, and it does so far more frequently than states form interstate compacts to solve their collective-action problems. Moreover, Professor Balkin reminds us that “[t]his kind of gridlock is not a permanent condition” and we have been here before. Those points suggest that I have not written an elegy. One of Professor Balkin’s most important contributions to our symposium is to centralize conflict—disagreement—about the nature and scope of collective-action problems facing the states and about the efficacy of Congress’s solutions. He fleshes out in illuminating detail why I emphasize that, “when states disagree, collective-action problems do not simply exist or not in a technical, scientific way.” Although “[c]ost-benefit collective-action problems have a certain objective structure,” I write, “their existence and significance require assessing the extent to which states are externalizing costs that are greater than the benefits they are internalizing.” I would add to Professor Balkin’s astute observations that the existence of such disagreement is not just hypothetical but historical and modern in the U.S. I offer numerous examples in the book. I would also add that the under-determinacy of collective-action reasoning is not only a vulnerability of the theory but also a virtue. Part of what I mean to accomplish is to provide a common vocabulary that participants in federalism debates can use to productively disagree. Professor Balkin sees that possibility and illustrates how the process might work. Consider, for example, the Interstate Commerce Clause. It is structurally more sensible to engage whether Congress reasonably concluded that the states face a collective-action problem caused by interstate spillovers with material effects—so that “Commerce” broadly construed is “among the several States”—than it is to debate whether the conduct that Congress is regulating is “economic” or “activity” in some functionally irrelevant sense. The partially normative dimension of collective-action thinking may make challenging Professor Re’s thought-provoking attempt to reconceptualize the Collective-Action Constitution as “an inquiry into the law’s underlying structure” and “a fact about our world.” Again, although empirical facts are directly relevant to collective-action reasoning, multi-state collective-action problems do not simply exist or not independent of normative commitments. Professor Re’s approach is more empirical and descriptive than mine—indeed, than the genre of constitutional interpretation more generally. Moreover, his normative conclusions regarding presidential unilateralism, aggressive judicial review of structural issues, and the major questions doctrine are different from the ones I defend. What I most admire about his contribution, however, is that it exemplifies how scholars with different methodological and ideological commitments can use the structural theory offered in the book. That does not mean all conclusions are equally plausible, but it does suggest that there is often room for debate. Professor Re astutely identifies what is likely to be a major challenge to The Collective-Action Constitution. How can I persuasively argue that solving and preventing multi-state collective-action problems is the primary structural purpose of the Constitution, as opposed to a primary structural purpose? Aren’t there multiple structural purposes that must be balanced? Don’t we have The Compromise Constitution, not The Collective-Action Constitution? Although I would be pleased to persuade readers that addressing and avoiding collective-action problems facing the states is one important structural purpose of the Constitution, I make the more assertive claim not to be provocative by overclaiming, but because much evidence supports it. We should not forget that the Constitutional Convention took place, and the Constitution was ultimately ratified, primarily to solve the collective-action governance failures that routinely occurred under the Articles of Confederation, not to protect state authority or individual liberty from federal overreach. As I examine in the book, that original order of priority is more evident once one realizes that the founders were contemplating strictly limited use of the president’s veto power, sharply restricted judicial review of federal legislation, and more assertive judicial review of state laws. In addition, they were not anticipating political parties, let alone today’s polarized and antagonistic parties. Moving from original structural purposes to contemporary ones, my claim about the Constitution’s primary structural function reflects a view about the expectations of the American public. Most Americans want members of Congress to compromise and address such issues as national security, climate change, pandemics, unlawful immigration, and other multi-state collective-action problems. They do not want Congress to routinely be thwarted in its efforts to do so. Both originally and today, it does not make structural sense to give Congress impressive powers, and to create impressive executive and judicial branches to enforce federal law, while simultaneously rendering it extraordinarily difficult for the federal government to act other than through unilateral, fleeting actions by presidents—who were intended to be law enforcers, not lawmakers. Presidents represent one political party and so lack the broader democratic legitimacy and interest balancing of Congress. Depending upon who occupies the office, presidents also pose a greater threat of democratic backsliding. On the other hand, preserving state autonomy remains an important structural purpose of the Constitution, and that purpose is advanced by (inter alia) the anti-commandeering doctrine. Professor Delaney is right that the constitutional text does not demand state protection from commandeering: it is a structural principle, not a textual one. My purpose is neither to fully embrace the Court’s version of the principle nor to fully reject it, as Professor Delaney would. Rather, I would allow commandeering where all states would be better off if such a coercive federal solution were imposed, and I would presumptively prohibit commandeering if some states would be worse off given the unusually coercive nature of commandeering. I also argue, however, that the presumption against commandeering should “be rebuttable where Congress lacks regulatory alternatives that would be about as efficacious.” Such a regime would respect state autonomy without impeding Congress’s ability to address what it reasonably deems cost-benefit collective-action problems. Professor Strauss’s contribution to the symposium is sharp, plain-spoken, and thoughtful. He explains why The Collective-Action Constitution has much to offer those who, unlike me, reject the idea of judicially enforceable limits on Congress’s enumerated powers. Even if we disagree about the proper role of courts, we should all agree that legislators should be constitutionally conscientious: they take oaths, too. We should also agree that constitutionally conscientious legislators should think through federalism questions. They should ask what sorts of questions are best addressed by the federal government, either alone or with the state governments. As Professor Strauss observes, the different categories of multi-state collective-action problems can help such legislators execute their responsibilities. In offering a collective-action account of the Interstate Commerce Clause, my goal is not to “make the case for reinvigorated judicial review” of interstate-commerce questions, as Professor Strauss writes. My purpose is instead to provide an intergenerational synthesis of the doctrines articulated by the Marshall Court and the various Courts since 1937—a synthesis that is responsive to the original purpose of the Clause. For several reasons I identify, I am optimistic that judicial review can work reasonably well in this area, although I agree with Professor Strauss that such review should be relatively modest—as it was originally intended to be—because courts possess substantially less democratic legitimacy and expertise than Congress (or agencies) in determining the nature and scope of multi-state collective-action problems, especially when states disagree. Still, there are ways to make judicial review sufficiently tractable that it is available if Congress goes too far, as it occasionally does. For example, in interstate-commerce cases, I would require the interstate spillovers that cause collective-action problems for the states to have material effects, not merely psychological ones. I would also impose reasonable limits on the time horizon within which Congress can identify the existence of collective-action problems facing the states. With those limitations in place, it is difficult to understand what the multi-state collective-action problem was in United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995), where the Court invalidated a federal ban on gun possession in school zones. I would not, however, restrict Congress to reasoning about collective-action problems according to standard cost-benefit analysis, which assumes that everyone values a dollar the same no matter how rich or poor they are. As I emphasize in citing my colleague Matt Adler’s work on prioritarianism, Congress is entitled to assign greater weight to the welfare of the less well off, which in the Civil Rights Era discussed by Professor Strauss would generally mean Black Americans, not the segregationists who owned hotels or restaurants. In addition, as I argue in Chapter 9, when Congress seeks to vindicate human freedom, equality, and dignity, Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment—whose language and history exude McCulloch deference to Congress—should routinely be available. The modern Court’s contrary doctrine is based upon a misunderstanding of state action and a failure to recognize the implications of the Citizenship Clause in Section 1 of the amendment. In many areas, the book privileges breadth of coverage over depth. A hope I express in the Conclusion is that subject-matter experts will examine the relevance and implications of The Collective-Action Constitution for their areas of interest. Professors Charles and Delaney provide inspiring examples of that aspiration in action. As Professor Charles highlights, it is critical to the theory that multi-state collective-action problems be addressed in democratically legitimate ways. Again, states often disagree about the existence and seriousness of collective-action problems, so the question becomes which governmental institution is best situated to resolve such disagreements. My first-best answer is Congress, where all states and individuals are better represented than anywhere else. The book defends that comparative institutional judgment on textual, historical, and theoretical grounds, but it does not defend the proposition that the Constitution and contemporary political practice in the U.S. are sufficiently democratic by modern standards of democratic legitimacy. Professor Charles gives us reasons to fear that they are not. For example, he observes that the Guarantee Clause (housed in Article IV, Section 4) does not ensure that “our political parties are committed to representative democracy,” that “oligarchs [do not] control our politics,” or that “local officials will certify the results of a federal election.” There are numerous ways to defend democratic self-government; my book offers just one. But as Professor Charles perceives, it is a deep, structural defense. If the most fundamental structural purpose of the Constitution is to solve collective-action problems for the states in democratically legitimate ways, there is a strong structural rationale for interpreting many constitutional provisions and principles in a pro-democratic fashion. For example, on that structural view, the Constitution may offer resources to both courts and a mobilized public should a state legislature in 2024 attempt to disenfranchise its electorate in a presidential election by choosing its own slate of electors to tip the election from one candidate to the other. Cf. Trump v. Anderson, 144 S. Ct. 662 (2024) (disabling states from enforcing Section 3 of the Fourteenth Amendment against presidential candidates). In my view, the Court’s judgment in Trump, although not its reasoning, is defensible on structural, McCulloch grounds as elaborated in The Collective-Action Constitution. I thank Professor Charles for reading the book as asking what it means to be a collective—a Union of states and people—that acts in democratically justified ways to identify sufficiently common problems amid disagreements and to ameliorate them insofar as government can. Professor Delaney accurately observes that my book does not engage the literature on comparative federalism. I hope she is correct that my book contributes to federal theory and will enrich comparative debates. I know she is right that my work would benefit from greater engagement with scholarship on comparative federal systems. Among other things, comparative experience can help test whether I am correct about which parts of the U.S. Constitution and constitutional law can persuasively be explained in collective-action terms. For example, the variation among federal constitutions on the issue of central consent to interstate compacts tends to support my conclusion that collective-action theory cannot fully explain the form of congressional consent required in the U.S. Constitution. *** Moving beyond the symposium contributors, The Collective-Action Constitution has been called “hundreds of pages of ambitious centrism” (by Professor Craig Green) and “constitutional law for grownups” (by Professor H. Jefferson Powell). Those descriptions capture my ambitions in writing the book, although it is up to others to decide how far I have succeeded. During a cynical era, in which one may wonder whether certain commentators, lawyers, politicians, and jurists take law or other people’s commitments seriously, I have tried to take diverse constitutional materials seriously; incorporate other people’s constitutional commitments; avoid overclaiming; acknowledge the limitations of my approach; and emphasize that no structural theory, including mine, can save America from terrible politics. I have no doubt fallen short, and I have no illusions that either full-throated nationalists or constitutional skeptics of federal power will be satisfied with my structural theory, or with how I would apply it. But it is important for legal scholars to try to model for one another, their students, elected officials, and jurists willing to listen that law still lives, and that it remains possible to “forge[] community in dissensus,” as Professor Reva Siegel has skillfully written in the context of her own work. My greatest hope is that The Collective-Action Constitution contributes to that effort.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |