Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Just Self-Government
|
Thursday, October 12, 2023
Just Self-Government
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization Symposium on Frank Michelman, Constitutional Essentials: On the Constitutional Theory of Political Liberalism (Oxford University Press, 2022)
Steven L. Winter In Constitutional Essentials, Frank Michelman examines the conditions that would fulfill John Rawls’s liberal principle of legitimacy. The desideratum is a constitutional package to which members of a society composed of free and equal citizens should agree provides a platform for stable, democratic life under conditions of reasonable pluralism. The central claim of liberal constitutionalism is that a text-like object or a “diplomatically abstract” set of principles can work a deflection of disagreements within such a pluralist polity. This, in turn, creates the Goldilocks problem: If the constitutional essentials are to work as a response to reasonable pluralism, “they must not be too thin; they have to say something beyond vaporous or trivial about matters people care deeply about. But neither may they be too thick. They must stop short of foreclosure of questions of fundamental import to some citizens, over which reasonable citizens divide.” (CE 42-43) The project rests on two related presuppositions that cannot be redeemed. First, it assumes a pluralism that, though intractable, nevertheless remains amenable to reason. Second, it assumes that reason is a capacity independent of the profound differences of meaning, value, and forms of life that shape those intractable disagreements. Neither assumption is correct. Differences in norms, values, and forms of life inevitably undergird and structure differences in meaning, perception, and interpretation. Indeed, as Jan Deutsch explained in Neutrality, Legitimacy, and the Supreme Court (1968), constitutionalism has always faced the fatal problem of circularity that arises from its dependence on the social understandings that inform its most basic terms. The most a constitutional package can supply--though it is no small thing--is a platform for disagreement. With Karl Klare (and others), I don’t see how the strategy of deflection is supposed to work. Unless there is widespread agreement on the meaning of the essentials--in which case there is no reason to remove them from the give-and-take of democratic politics--the deflection will be quixotic. The most it can accomplish is to shift the level of conflict from debate over the acceptability of essentials to debate over the meaning of those essentials. In the end, this is a difficulty that Michelman does not resolve. Nor could he. As Michelman notes in Legitimation by Constitution (2021), the distinction between “secondary acts of interpretation” and “originary acts of legislation” is unstable--and this fact alone, he suggests, is reason to preserve such questions for the people themselves. Following Rawls, Michelman suggests that, if cast at “accommodating levels of abstraction,” the essential constitutional rights and liberties “carry a core of commonly agreed meanings” that are “sufficient to render coherent and persuasive the claims of citizens to each other.” (CE 52) But this cannot work either, and for two reasons. First, the transparency of central cases is itself a contingent phenomenon. One of the best-documented findings in cognitive science is the experience of prototype effects: category members that are reliably rated better examples of the category than others and that figure prominently in reasoning. For the most part, prototype effects arise because human categorization involves complex, gestalt conditions—i.e., a confluence of factors whose sum is psychologically more fundamental than the individual parts. The “central cases,” then, are just those that stand out because they fit some category or categories that the observer already holds. The experience of prototype effects creates the impression that there are clear, readily-available meanings for most abstract concepts. But this experience of clarity involves complex processes of intelligibility that draw on tacit knowledge of the relevant domain including context, purpose, social understandings and assumptions, models of behavior, etc. Under conditions of pluralism, differences in norms, values, and forms of life will structure different categories and produce different “central cases.” For the Roberts Court, 303 Creative LLC v. Elenis (2023) is a central case of free speech while Morse v. Frederick (2007) and Holder v. Humanitarian Law Project (2010) are not. Many of us would make exactly the opposite call. Second, basic rights and liberties pose complex distributional issues no different than those that counsel many, including Rawls, against including socio-economic issues as part of the basic constitutional package. Restrictions on hate speech, regulation of corporate speech, or limitations on campaign expenditures pit the rights, interests, and relative wealth of private actors against one another. The same is true of affirmative action or the application of the one-person-one-vote principle in the context of gerrymandering or malapportionment. In considering a liberty claim, a decisionmaker must weigh multiple competing interests, regardless of whether those affected are parties to the case. Consider a challenge to a law requiring vaccination. The decisionmaker must weigh the challenger’s interest in bodily integrity against the government’s interest in the public health, and that incorporates the bodily-integrity claims of all those who might be exposed to contagion. It is a distributional claim that balances the challenger’s social utility against the social utility of others. There will be inevitable uncertainty both about these tradeoffs and about the practical actions necessary to overall public well-being. It is a fair point to say that, with respect to socio-economic rights, only a democratic politics can answer these kinds of open-ended policy questions. But the same is true for all rights claims--including property claims under the Takings Clause, as Michelman has famously argued, or the conflict in 303 Creative between religious liberty or free speech claims, on one hand, and the claims for recognition and inclusion by LGBTQ citizens, on the other. Whatever levels of abstraction are chosen, a constitution cannot avoid the problems of pluralism, policy, and interpretation. Even if everyone in a polity has consented to the constitutional essentials, what they have consented to is a matter of interpretation and thus of current contestation. On Michelman’s own account, there is no way to interpret the text without adverting to the background traditions and assumptions that underlie it. For a respectful interpreter, he says, the constitution “will be read against the backdrop of a political moral purpose—Dworkin’s lesson—that the judicial reader cannot simply find already in the text (because it indispensably informs the reading of the text) and so must of necessity bring to it.” (CE 131) It could not be otherwise. Consider what I call the “ashtray problem.” We can reflect on any concept and tease out its implications; we may, as with the concept of an ashtray, be able to specify its necessary and sufficient conditions. But we will always already be reflecting on our culture and history and discovering there the social deposit that shapes our thinking. An ashtray is always an ashtray. But it has no meaning outside a cultural practice of the consumption of tobacco (or similar substances) by smoking. In just this way, Michelman concedes that “any defense of ‘a constitutional scheme with judicial review’ must advert to ‘historical circumstances and conditions of political culture.’” (CE 41 n.26) Repeatedly, he acknowledges that the situated social practices and attendant values that constitute our democratic nomos play an overtly regulative function. When we dig down into specifics, the vices of diplomatically “thin” essentials and unaccountable institutional arbiters becomes apparent. Abstraction becomes the sleight of hand that too often transmutes the gold of democratic self-governance into the lead of institutional dogma. A traditional response to the antidemocratic implications of constitutional review is a set of legal doctrines that institutionalize the idea of judicial restraint. Such doctrines, Michelman explains, temper the overreach of judicial interpreters without running afoul of “a strong-form understanding of the supreme court’s” role in enforcing the constitutional essentials. (CE 169-70) Michelman offers Rucho v. Common Cause (2019) as an example. A lot is at stake for the liberal constitutionalist in a case like Rucho. On one hand, a partisan-political gerrymander allows a political “party, although overall outvoted, nevertheless to gain and keep control of the legislative body in question.” (CE 161 n.23) On the other, if the courts’ involvement in partisan political squabbles undermines confidence in their neutrality, then the entire project of justification-by-constitution is in trouble. By referring some issues to other branches of government or back to the people themselves, Michelman says, doctrines of judicial restraint respond to the “standing dilemma” of maintaining confidence in the court: “[T]he dilemma would abate with entrustment of that function or some share of it to some more openly political process, one whose perceived nonpartisanship would rest not (or not exclusively) on attribution of special skills of decryption of legal texts and precedents but rather (or also) on breadth, quality, and vigor of participatory input.” (CE 162) Note two things. First, Michelman is once again invoking the ongoing democratic debates of the living citizenry (the “openly political” and “participatory” process) to do the work of institutional settlement that was supposed to solve the problem of pluralism. Second, judicial abdication in this case is doubly inappropriate. On one hand, it is an axiom of constitutional thought from Marshall to Stone and Ely that judicial review is most warranted when invoked to protect the integrity and fairness of the political process. On the other, the issue in Rucho is of the sort least suited to resolution through democratic politics. The point of a political gerrymander is to entrench the party in power by deliberately tilting the playing field. Its purpose and effect, in other words, are to undercut the quality, vigor, and effectiveness of the participatory process. For the Court to refer the problem of gerrymandering to the very political agencies, the state legislatures, that are its beneficiaries is both disingenuous and self-defeating. Nothing could more cynically undermine democracy. In the abstract, judicial restraint promotes democracy. Whether it does, in fact, depends on the circumstances. In overruling the abortion cases in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization (2022), the majority soothingly explained that the Constitution “leaves the issue for the people and their elected representatives to resolve through the democratic process in the States or Congress.” But many of these states have heavily gerrymandered legislatures that are significantly more conservative than their voters, a substantial majority of whom (even in red states like Kansas) support reproductive freedoms. In the abstract, the Court can pretend to be promoting democratic decisionmaking. But, as always, the devil is in the details. The full implications of Rucho emerge only when we recognize the many ways and the countless contexts in which, as Stone warned in Carolene Products (1938), an unrepresentative political process can no longer “be expected to bring about repeal of undesirable legislation.” For Michelman, law is something outside and above ordinary practice. Constitutional law, he says, is “an always already prior fixation.” (CE 177) It is, in a word, a reification. But law is not some abstract entity, special and above. It is not, as Michelman once said, “an autonomous force” that provides “an external untouchable rule of the game.” (CE 176) The fixed, external quality of law is a projection: It is the community, as Robert Cover (1984) astutely observes, “that posits a law external to itself.” Law may be the object (from the Latin ob, “towards, against,” +? iacio, “I throw, hurl”). But we are always the subject (from the Latin sub, “under, at the foot of,” + iacio). Law is just another institutional form--a performative practice--that does (or does not) reflect our democratic nomos. To be committed, as a strong democrat, to the rule of law as an essential element of “a regime of collective self-government among equals” (CE 181) is to be committed to the idea that we make the rules by which we govern ourselves. It does not mean that one must buy into a reified set of ground rules that are “autonomous” or “external.” The Greeks who invented democracy understood democracy and the rule of law as a tautology that they expressed with the single word isonomia: signifiying not equality “under” law but, as Demosthenes put it, an equal share in the law. Equal voice, equal power, and equal law are just self-government. They are by definition internal to--that is, constitutive of--the game. Without them, one would be doing something other than democracy. That does not make them “untouchable.” To the contrary, we are painfully aware that they are being manhandled nearly every day. But they nevertheless describe a democratic constitution that fully legitimates itself in its performance.Posted 9:30 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |