Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Care and Equality (and Abortion), Redux: Constructing a Feminist Common Good Constitutionalism
|
Tuesday, May 09, 2023
Care and Equality (and Abortion), Redux: Constructing a Feminist Common Good Constitutionalism
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Julie Suk, After Misogyny: How the Law Fails Women and What to Do about It (University of California Press, 2023). Linda
McClain
Julie Suk’s
call for a feminist constitutionalism that embraces both gender equality and
care—as public values that government should promote—strongly echoes prior
feminist calls while also speaking to the present moment. Her ambitious book, After Misogyny: How the Law Fails Women and
What to Do About It, significantly contributes to a large feminist
literature on equality and care spanning decades (even centuries) and national
boundaries, yet also offers all-too-timely diagnoses and prescriptions for the
United States at a very particular moment. That “moment” includes being four
year into the COVID-19 pandemic and nearly one year into the post-Roe v. Wade and Planned Parenthood v. Casey world wrought by Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization. Further, at a time
when the most hotly debated model of common good constitutionalism (“CGC”) in
the U.S. is that of conservative legal scholar Adrian Vermeule, who proposes
that “best way forward” for constitutional
interpretation is to look “backward for inspiration”
to “classical law,” Professor Suk looks to comparative constitutionalism for
constructive models of an attractive alternative: a feminist CGC. (I have critiqued Vermeule’s account of CGC in
a prior book symposium on this blog.) Finally, that moment also includes
a sense that transformative political and constitutional change are urgently necessary
but very difficult because (as Suk and Kate Shaw recently noted) Americans have
“lost the habit and muscle memory of
seeking formal constitutional change” —and because of problems like polarization, gerrymandering,
and restrictions on voting. What are the
prospects for a feminist CGC to provide tools and concepts to move beyond misogyny? Suk uses the term “misogyny”
to describe what “endures after patriarchy,” when “patriarchy loses its force
as law”—a “range of expectations and entitlements” that “maintain patriarchal
gender relations” in ways that “keep women down in order to keep everyone and
everything else up”? In this review, I will first address Suk’s pairing of
gender equality and care, focusing primarily on Chapter 6 of After Misogyny, “Building Feminist
Infrastructures: The Constitutionalism of Care.” I will then consider her
analysis of abortion in the post-Dobbs
landscape, engaging with Chapter 3, “Misogyny and Maternity: Abortion Bans as
Overentitlement.” In each of these
contexts, I will explore the promising and possibly problematic aspects of
Suk’s framework. Gender Equality and Building a Care
Infrastructure Professor
Suk persuasively argues that the COVID-19 pandemic made visible that “essential
work is women’s work.” That is true in two sense: mothers disproportionately
engage in caring for children, as compared with fathers (both as single parents
and in different-sex households), and women are disproportionately among
“essential workers.” Moreover, as
Catherine Powell has observed, essential workers are also
disproportionately women and men of color. As many feminist scholars and organizations have argued, the pandemic revealed
and exacerbated the care crisis in the U.S. and showed the urgent need
for—finally—building a care infrastructure that is attentive to gender and
racial equality. Naomi Cahn and I argued that this should be a vital part of a feminist (or gender equitable)
recovery plan. Suk
helpfully refers to building a care infrastructure as part of the task of
building “feminist infrastructures.” Addressing the perennial question about
why the U.S. lags so far behind other countries with respect to elements of
such an infrastructure—paid parental and family leave; affordable, accessible,
and high quality child care; workplace flexibility, to name a few—Suk suggests
one reason is the U.S. Constitution. She writes: “In many other countries, paid
maternity leave is not only a long-standing public policy, like social
security; it is often a constitutional entitlement.” Suk traces the evolution
of “the special protection” of motherhood and the family in a number of
constitutions, in particular, Germany, Italy, France, and Ireland. She also notes that such clauses raise
eyebrows for those concerned about gender equality and seem directly in
conflict with both the formal equality and
anti-stereotyping jurisprudence associated with the Equal Protection
Clause in the U.S. Constitution. What I find
most interesting in Suk’s historical account of feminist constitutional efforts
in, e.g., Germany and Ireland is their insistence both on governmental support
of care—and the work of social reproduction—and
of equality. Without a similar
constitutional anchor, similar calls for a politics that embraces care and
equality have
sounded in the U.S. for decades. Building on strands of feminism, civic
republicanism, and liberalism, I have argued both that care is a public value that government has a responsibility
to support and that gender equality is a constitutional commitment and public
value that government has a responsibility to foster. What gives me pause with Suk’s
comparative constitutional examples is the repeated language about a certain
degree of expected and beneficial maternal “sacrifice” that is for the “common
good” and for which the state owes compensation. For example, Suk writes of the
evolution—through judicial interpretation—in both Germany and Ireland of “the
constitutional protection of motherhood” to support policies that “value
mothers’ socially beneficial sacrifices and to mitigate the disadvantages that
such sacrifices could cause.” Fitting
some of this jurisprudence within her framework of overentitlement and unjust
enrichment, Suk quotes an Irish High Court judge reasoning about what seems to
be a counterpart to equitable distribution of property upon divorce. The court
bases such an award on a woman’s contribution in the home, which entails both
“emotional and economic” sacrifice: “In return for that voluntary sacrifice,
which the Constitution recognizes as being in
the interest of the common good, she should receive some reasonable
economic security within the home” (emphasis added). Nonetheless, Suk’s is a narrative of
constitutional evolution to embrace care and
equality. With respect to the Irish Constitution, she traces a journey from the
constitutional recognition (in Article 41.2) of women’s work—specifically—as a
“sacrifice that is essential for the common good” to concern over the Article’s
gender essentialism to a proposed revision to adopt “gender-neutral language
protecting all parents and carers.” Suk praises as a constructive model for
possible transplanting that of the Citizens’ Assembly that convened to address both
abortion and the language of Article 41.2. The COVID-19 pandemic (as the Assembly
recognized in its report) “shone a strong spotlight on care, its importance in
our society, and the gendered nature of its provision.” Of course,
one could point to similar political rhetoric in the U.S., including from the
Biden presidential campaign and the American Rescue Plan. Early on, the
Biden/Harris Administration created a Gender Policy Council and announced commitments both to gender equity and equality
and to racial equity. As Suk notes in her book, the most robust public policies
that would instantiate a care infrastructure and advance gender equality have
often failed in Congress (particularly, in the Senate, due to the filibuster
and other factors). An important victory, nonetheless, is the Pregnant Workers Fairness Act, signed by President Biden on
December 29, 2022 and which (like many comparable state laws) requires
“reasonable accommodation” and adopts the inclusive language of pregnant
“workers.” Would there be more such legislative victories if the Senate stopped
impeding recognition of the Equal Rights Amendment? In her conclusion, Suk,
whose last book chronicled the generations of women who were constitutional actors in
the struggle for the ERA, suggests some possible innovations along the lines of
Ireland’s Citizens’ Assembly even as she candidly recognizes the “American
resistance to constitutional change.” Abortion Bans Professor
Suk evocatively discusses abortion bans as “overentitlement.” Suk aptly argues that Dobbs makes possible a landscape— in the many states that have
either banned or severely restrictive access to abortion—in which motherhood is
compelled but uncompensated: “Abortion bans enforce society’s entitlement to
women’s sacrifice as childbearers for the public benefit of reproducing the
community, without sufficient governmental restitution for this unjust
enrichment.” By comparison, Suk points to different legal regimes in which
there are restrictions on abortion to protect potential life (particularly
after the first trimester), but also public funding of abortion and public
policies that support pregnancy, childbirth, and parenthood. Using the example of Germany, Suk
traces how constitutional commitments both to a right to life and to the right
to “free development” of one’s “personality” eventually led to such a
regulatory scheme. Once again, the language of “sacrifice” by women and
compensation for their labor are pertinent: how much may a pregnant women be
expected to sacrifice and what is the state required to do to relieve the costs
and burdens of pregnancy and parenthood? Suk argues:
“After the demise of Roe, the battle
against misogyny should not resurrect privacy rights but rather pursue laws
that fully recognize the public value of the sacrifices pregnant women endure
for the benefit of others.” This is sobering. As she notes, the Casey joint opinion aptly discusses the
constitutional wrongness of compelled maternity in the language of the “sacrifices”
that pregnancy entails. In his partial dissent, Justice Blackmun, as Suk
quotes, explicitly spoke about abortion bans as conscripting women’s bodies
into the state’s “service.” Justice Blackmun continued: “The State does not compensate women for their
services; instead, it assumes that they owe this duty as a matter of course.” The language
of overentitlement and a lack of compensation do have some power here. Post-Dobbs, states may ask for quite a bit of
sacrifice but with no obligation to provide any “compensation.” It is hard to
imagine a status quo more at odds with a vision of reproductive justice, with its commitment to human rights to bodily
autonomy, to have children, to not have children, and to parent children in
safe and sustainable communities (as in Sister Song’s Visioning New Futures for
Reproductive Justice Declaration). States with the most restrictive laws have some of the weakest laws and worst outcomes with respect to
supporting pregnant persons, parents, and children. In such
circumstances, does a legal regime that combines a “robust conception of the
state’s positive duties, not only to the unborn fetus, but to women facing
unwanted pregnancies” look more attractive? What is the promise and peril of
rhetoric about pregnancy and childbirth being a sacrifice that is for the
“common good”? Does such rhetoric of pregnancy benefiting others miss the
significance of pregnancy to the individual pregnant person or what
childbearing and rearing mean to a person’s conception of their own life? One of my
first encounters with a comparative constitutional analysis of abortion law was
Mary Ann Glendon’s Abortion and Divorce in Western Law, published in 1987, where she praised
both the French and German models as better than that of the U.S. in Roe. Like Suk, Glendon quotes from the decision
of the Federal Constitutional Court of West Germany that the 1974 West German
abortion law was unconstitutional. But Glendon also quotes a passage that Suk
does not and which has stayed with me since first reading it: “In this
context it will be principally a matter of strengthening the willingness of the
person about to become a mother to accept the pregnancy with responsibility to
self and to bring the fetus to full life. For all the State’s duty to furnish
protection, one may not lose sight of the fact that the developing life has,
first of all, been entrusted by nature to the protection of the mother. It should be the most eminent purpose of
government efforts on behalf of the protection of life to reawaken and, if
necessary, strengthen the maternal protective will [in cases] where it has been
lost.” (Emphasis added.) This
language of the lost “maternal protective will” sounds a lot like arguments
that pregnant women inevitably should become mothers and that no woman who
understood what abortion was would have an abortion because it goes against
their nature. As Reva Siegel has written, this is the “woman protective antiabortion
argument” sounded in
the report of the South Dakota Task Force to Study Abortion back in 2005 and
also in Gonzales v. Carhart, in 2007. Glendon also
wrote, of the 1975 German Constitutional Court decision: “In the hierarchy of
constitutional values, the court held that human life is a central and supreme
value of the constitutional order, to which the woman’s acknowledged right to
self-determination and privacy is subordinate.” This “hierarchy” is all too
evident in the post-Dobbs landscape,
with harrowing stories of pregnant women’s health and sometimes life
subordinated. Most chillingly, this is true even in instances where a pregnancy
will not result in a live, healthy fetus, but doctors fear prosecution for
providing help before a statutory threshold of danger is met. Suk’s
comparative constitutional law survey ends with a more recent iteration of
German abortion law, post reunification, that protects life “by supporting
mothers and gender equality.” Once again
the Constitutional Court struck down an abortion law, with reasoning similar to
its 1975 opinion. However, Suk finds it instructive and encouraging that the
Court expanded its discussion of the state’s duty to protect life to link that
duty both to the constitutional entitlement of “mothers to the special
protection and care of the community” to the guarantee of “equal rights between
men and women.” Her point to U.S. readers, confronting the Dobbs scenario of compelled maternity without compensation, is that
the Constitutional Court offered a more robust idea of the “care” the community
owed to mothers (and parents) in terms of addressing “problems and
difficulties” that a pregnant person would encounter during pregnancy as well
as creating a “child-friendly society” that addresses material hardships and
disadvantages from becoming a parent. The Court uses language of “compensation”
of parents for financial disadvantage for giving up work or devoting “herself
or himself to raising a child.” Suk finds encouraging that, two decades after
its earlier decision, the Court has moved from assuming it was “reasonable” to
expect pregnant women to “bear the ‘normal’ burdens of motherhood” to
acknowledging “that even normal motherhood exacts heavy burdens unless the
state intervenes to promote a ‘child-friendly society.’” Further, the court
also stressed the futility of “criminal sanctions,” compared to “preventative
means” to help a pregnant woman “overcome her conflict and meet her
responsibility to the unborn.” However, the underlying premise is still of a
“responsibility” to continue the pregnancy.
In 1987,
Glendon wrote: “An important segment of the prolife movement has already
recognized that those who would restrict or deny abortion should be prepared to
give the pregnant woman every possible form of assistance. If the state is once
again to restrict the availability of abortion and to affirm the value of
unborn life, it should in all fairness strive to help those who bear and raise
children, not only during pregnancy but also after childbirth.” With a more
explicit commitment to gender equality and with the additional concepts of “overentitlement”
and unjust enrichment (or a lack of just compensation), Suk reaches a similar
conclusion about the post-Dobbs U.S. Both Glendon
and Suk critique “privacy” as a foundation for abortion rights, and stress the
public dimension of human reproduction (as well as public duties to support
such reproduction). I continue to believe that privacy, better understood as
autonomy with respect to significant personal decisions (as in Casey), is a critical constitutional
value, even if the Dobbs majority
decimated it in the context of decisions about whether or not to continue a
pregnancy. But I also join Suk in believing that, post-Dobbs, it is critical to argue for the public dimension of human
reproduction and to explore arguments about how compelled pregnancy unjustly
conscripts the bodies of, and demands sacrifices from, pregnant persons (as
Justice Blackmun argued in Casey). Such
unjust conscription hinders rather than furthers the “common good.” Whether or
not comparative constitutional models make those arguments more persuasive or
reinforce notions about women’s natural responsibilities remains to be seen. In
the meantime, After Misogyny offers a
set of innovative arguments and concepts aimed at ending misogyny and advancing
care and equality.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |