Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Can We All Get Along? A Tribute and a Question
|
Thursday, August 04, 2022
Can We All Get Along? A Tribute and a Question
Guest Blogger
This post was prepared for a
roundtable on Wrestling with
Religious Diversity, convened as part of LevinsonFest 2022—a
year-long series gathering scholars from diverse disciplines and viewpoints to
reflect on Sandy Levinson’s influential work in constitutional law. Nomi Maya Stolzenberg On March 3, 1991, Rodney King, an African
American man driving on a Los Angeles freeway, was chased and then savagely
beaten by the police. A videotape of the beating ignited widespread criticism
and charges were brought against the participating police officers for assault
and excessive use of force. The trial, which took place one year later,
culminated in acquittals of the four officers who were charged,[1] in reaction to which thousands
of people took part in five days of civil disturbances known variously as the
LA Uprising or the LA riots of 1992. On the third day of the uprising, King
gave an impromptu news conference, deploring the shooting of a security guard
that had taken place and pleading for an end to the violence. The speech is
famously remembered for one line, oft-misquoted as: “Can’t we all just get
along?” In fact, the question that Rodney King posed was not “can’t we get
along?,” but rather, “can we get along?” The latter conveys the same longing
for peaceful coexistence that the mistaken paraphrase does, and indeed, King
went on to say, wishfully, “we can get along. We all can get along. We just
gotta. We gotta. I mean, we’re all stuck here for a while. Let’s, you know,
let’s try to work it out.” But unlike the mistaken paraphrase, “can’t we get
along?,” “can we get along?” is less a rhetorical question to which the answer
must be yes than it is a genuine question, the answer to which remains very
much in doubt. In roughly the same time period, Professor
Sanford Levinson—Sandy, to his friends—published a set of essays posing
essentially the same question, with one key difference. Whereas Rodney King
expressed the desire to overcome the racial divisions that scar American
society, these essays that Sandy wrote in the early 1990s were focused on the
problem of religious division.[2] More precisely, they examined
the divide that exists between what Sandy described as “secularist,
accommodationist liberals like myself”[3]
and “those who are religious.”[4] They gave voice to his concern
about whether these groups can get along, as opposed to splintering apart into
mutually indifferent, or worse, warring camps. And they expressed the desire
not just to confront the divide between secularism and religious belief but to
explore the possibility of bridging it. “Me” here clearly refers not just to Sandy but
to all of us who reject the “possibility of ascertaining divine desire.” It is,
you might say, not a royal, but rather, a liberal statist we—the we who
identify with the secular state (even if we are critical of it)[8] and rely on secular sources of
knowledge. For to be secularist,
Sandy explains, is precisely to reject the “possibility of ascertaining divine
desire,”[9] from which it follows that
basing state policies on divine law is impossible. From that it follows that it
is impermissible to base state policies on claims
about the divine will. Once it is recognized either that the divine law’s
content is unascertainable or that there is no divine law to ascertain, the law
and the state have to be secular and have to maintain their separation from
institutions and claims of religious authority. That being the case, the kind
of acceptance of religious arguments for public policies that religious critics
of the liberal state demand has to be denied. Yet, even as he acknowledged their
incommensurability, Sandy strove to overcome the gap between secularist and
anti-secularist frameworks of argument and to avoid the disparagement of
religious people that the ascendance of secular culture and the secular state
seemed to imply. He sought to find a way to unite secularists and people of
faith in a shared practice of democratic discourse, a practice from which none
are excluded, in which all participate on terms of mutual respect, and in which
none are required to hide, suppress, or, “cover” their identity.[10] While assessments vary[11]—some
would see condescension in a practice of inclusion and religious accommodation
that has the explicit goal of making religious groups less insular and more
open to secularist persuasion, even as it recognizes and welcomes the
possibility of secularists being converted to a religious sensibility—Sandy
undeniably succeeded in his own personal project of “getting along with” and
opening his heart (if not, ultimately, his mind)[12]
to people of faith, at least to a degree. Just by crediting the religious
critique of liberal secularism, he exhibited a sympathetic understanding, or
effort at understanding, that went a fair distance towards honoring the people
who formulated it and recognizing the validity of (some of) their claims. This,
after all, was a time when mainstream liberalism was characterized by an
astonishing level of blindness to the ongoing vitality of religious faith and
to the illusory nature of its own claims to neutrality. It was a time when the
most common response to claims of loss and injury on the part of religious
communities, who saw their traditional structures of authority being eroded and
their children becoming alienated from their families’ traditional values, was
to deny that liberal educational and legal policies were responsible for these
changes, and to double-down on the claim that the state could be, and was,
value-neutral. Sandy would have none of that. He repudiated “the insensitivity
of the standard-model secular liberal.”[13]
And it is in no small part thanks to this work of repudiation that more people
on the left as well as on the right now recognize the hollowness of
liberalism’s pretensions to neutrality. Key to Sandy’s personal practice of bridging
the divide between his own outlook and that of people who insist that
theological propositions and religious practices have a rightful place in
public policy and discourse, is friendship. The importance of friendship, and
the obligations engendered by friendship, are prominent themes in the subset of
Sandy’s work devoted to religious devotion. And it is as an act of devotion,
personal devotion, no less, that Sandy performs the work of bridging the
differences between his sensibility and that of his religious professional
colleagues and friends. Asking himself why he “cannot find it within me to
condemn as ‘irrational’ those who are religious,” and how he is able to respect
the people whose arguments, logic tells him, “can have no real meaning for me,”
he says (in a candid footnote): “Perhaps the answer boils down to the fact that some of my best
friends, whom I respect both as decent human beings and, more relevantly to the
instant discussion, as serious intellectuals, are deeply religious, and I am
unwilling to dismiss them as being necessarily deluded.”[14] Sandy did not merely extend an olive branch to his religiously-minded
colleagues. He credits them (specifically, Michael McConnell) with having
changed his mind about a number of important legal issues, in particular, the
constitutionality of vouchers (used for religious school tuition), which he
came to regard as not unconstitutional or
as nonjusticiable—that is, an issue for the legislatures, not the courts, to
decide. Beyond that, he expressed his growing sense that vouchers are an
advisable policy from the standpoint of egalitarian and diversity concerns.
Adopting this “friendly” (albeit somewhat ambivalent) position about state
funding for private religious schools entailed rejecting his erstwhile strict
separationist views. He likewise modified his views about the place
of religion in the public schools. Here again, his position was ambivalent, or,
we might say, nuanced. It issued less from a view that religious practices have a proper place in public
education than from his belief that religious people should not be “driven away” from public schools, which he
conjectured would be the result if public school authorities failed (or were
not allowed) to make religious accommodations. He first put forth this view in
a commentary (or, more precisely, a commentary on a commentary) on the case of Mozert v. Hawkins, which rejected the
claim of evangelical Christian parents that they had a right under the Free
Exercise Clause to opt out of classes that exposed their children to objectionable
“secular humanist” ideas and values.[15]
He further developed this position in a 2003 essay co-written with his
daughter, the political philosopher Meira Levinson, which espoused the
importance of integrated schools, where children (and older students) are
educated alongside people of different races, genders, sexual orientations,
abilities, cultures, and religions,
and the concomitant imperative not to adopt school policies that drive
religious parents away.[16] Here, as with his professional
interactions with religious colleagues, the importance of face-to-face personal
relationships and getting individuals of different backgrounds to “get along,”
rather than separating from or renouncing each other, was paramount. Looking back at this body of work from the
distance of twenty to thirty years, it is hard not to see how much the ground,
and the balance of power, have shifted. What once were hypothetical
possibilities that Sandy merely entertained, such as the possibility that the
Supreme Court would decree that state subsidization of religious school tuition
is not merely constitutionally permitted but is (in certain circumstances)
constitutionally required now appear
to be on the brink of realization.[17] The exodus of religious
families from the public schools that Sandy feared and lamented has steadily
increased, with rising enrollments (and rising resistance to state regulation)
in private religious schools (for which Sandy expressed sympathy) and an
explosion of homeschooling (for which Sandy had no use.)[18]
All of this is taking place at the same time that the religious right’s
campaign against abortion rights is, finally, triumphing.[19]
Notwithstanding the thin veneer of neutrality that religious conservatives now
use to disguise their argument against Roe
v. Wade (just as secularists cover up their value-judgments with a veneer
of value-neutrality when they have the upper hand), its religious character is
plain to see. And their rise to power is equally plain to see, notwithstanding
continued protestations that religious conservatives are the victims of
secularist oppression. Which of the two warring forces is currently the more powerful and which is ultimately
destined to prevail are matters open to debate. But the one thing that does not
appear to be debatable is that secularists and religious conservatives are not,
to put it mildly, getting along. To the contrary, they are at war, and have
been at war since at least the 1960s, when the Supreme Court handed down its
school prayer decisions[20] and Sandy was just starting
his illustrious scholarly career. That “culture war” was intensifying in the
early 1990s, when Sandy first began to appeal to his fellow liberals to be less
dismissive and more respectful of—otherwise put, to be more friendly and
welcoming to—religious conservatives in the hopes that the culture of the
institutions that liberals appeared to dominate wouldn’t drive them away.
Looking at this body of work with hindsight raises a number of questions.
First, is it true that it was the “unfriendliness” of secular institutions,
like public schools, that led increasing numbers of religious conservatives to
opt out of the public school system and turn to parochial schools,
homeschooling, and the charter school movement—while simultaneously seeking
public support for private education? The “drive away” hypothesis/lamentation
is an essentially empirical, causal claim, the implication being that if public
schools—or, more precisely, the liberals who supposedly run the public
schools—had just been more accommodating of religious parents, and more
receptive to expressions of religious identity, then fewer people of faith
would have defected from them. Is this true? As with all counterfactuals, this
causal proposition is difficult, if not impossible, to prove or disprove. But
there are serious reasons to doubt that more robust forms of religious
accommodation, such as selective opt-outs from public school classes deemed to
be religiously offensive, would have resulted in less attrition.[21] But even if they had, there are other reasons
to question the recommendations for more religious accommodation in public
schools and more state aid for private ones. Both of these sets of policy
recommendations, which Sandy endorsed in the past (albeit with ample
qualifications), rest not just on the value of cultural pluralism (which, for
him, includes but is not limited to religious pluralism), but, more
specifically, on a theory of strong parental rights. After all, it is not
children upon whom the sought-after right to opt out from offending public
school classes would be conferred, but rather, their parents. Whether parental
rights are exercised in the public school domain, where they take the form of
selective rejection of elements of the curriculum, or in the private domain, where
they take the form of exiting the public system of education altogether,
parental rights entail authority over
children, authority that parents can exercise to prevent their children
from being exposed to secular ideas or receiving a secular education that
conflicts with their religious values. Whether there are any limits to such parental
rights is a proposition that is now being tested, most notably by a New
York-based organization representing former yeshiva students called YAFFED,
which has been lobbying the legislature and suing the State and its Department
of Education for failing to enforce statutes imposing minimum (secular)
educational standards on private schools.[22]
As Anne Dailey argues with respect to the current bans on the teaching of “critical
race theory” and LGBTQ awareness, this kind of invocation of children’s rights constitutes a serious
challenge to the proposition that pluralism and liberalism require upholding
parental rights.[23] Now that advocacy groups like
YAFFED are bringing the conflict between parents’ rights (to deny their
children a secular education) and children’s rights (to receive a secular
education) to a head, one wonders what Sandy’s position is on this issue. So,
too, one wonders where he stands on state aid for religious education now that
the Supreme Court had deemed it to be constitutionally required, at least when
the state provides aid for tuition at “nonsectarian” private schools.[24] Does
he still hold the view that vouchers are likely to promote diversity and
equality? Is he still of the view that parents should be able to prevent public
schools from exposing their children to ideas that violate their beliefs? If
so, is that a policy of accommodation that evinces respect for people of faith?
Or is it more accurately characterized as a form of liberal condescension,
motivated by the desire to minimize the degree of self-segregation engaged in
by religious parents and to maximize their children’s exposure to other ways of
life, with the ultimate aim of weaning them from their families’ conservative
values? Or is it better characterized, as Micah Shwartzman and Nelson Tebbe
have characterized other policies of liberal accommodation, as a form of
appeasement, which is destined to have the effect of strengthening conservative
beliefs and resistance to liberal and progressive values rather than weakening
them?[25] Recognizing the possibility of these complex
dynamics puts the practice of friendship that Sandy has modeled for us in a
different, more dubious, light. Two things I find to be missing from Sandy’s
analyses of the religious-secularist divide are 1) a recognition of the
existence of a political movement
dedicated to overthrowing the liberal secularist outlook, which has been
gathering strength since the late 1970s; and 2) a recognition that many (in the
United States, quite possibly most) of the people who subscribe to the liberal
secularist or “secularist humanist” outlook that this movement is trying to
overthrow are people of faith. The proposition that secularists are people of
faith might sound paradoxical, but it is only a paradox if to be a secularist
is to reject not only the knowability, but also the existence, of a divine being
and divinely ordained moral laws. Like Sandy himself, many people who recognize
the unavailability of knowledge of divine law (and the consequent necessity of
secular law) are agnostic, rather than atheistic.[26]
They are not so much unbelievers as
they are not believers or not sure
what they believe. Still others are
believers, or occasional believers. Or they are affiliated with religious
communities and/or adhere to religious traditions, whether they believe in the
metaphysical propositions those traditions are based on or not. Such variable
attitudes are neither inconsistent with secularism, nor preclusive of being
able to “get” religiously-based arguments. In point of fact, the antagonists of
secularism with whom Sandy has sought to “get along” are not “those who are
religious,” as he broadly characterizes them, but rather, those who subscribe
to conservative religious beliefs and
have a conservative political theology. That is to say, it is those who
subscribe to the specifically anti-secularist belief that the content of divine
law is ascertainable and who further subscribe to anti-liberal beliefs
about what the content of divine law is. Which brings me to my final question, which is
how to reckon with the existence of the conservative religious movement and how
to reconcile the practice of friendship that Sandy espouses and models so
beautifully for us with its growing power. As Sandy recognized, treating people
as ideologues is not how we treat friends. Sandy insisted on treating
colleagues as friends. And he further insisted on the importance of the
distinction between the individual and the political movements in his accounts
of participants in litigation with whom he had no personal relationship, as in
his analysis of Vicki Frost, the lead plaintiff in the Mozert case who, he points out, became overshadowed by the national
organization, Concerned Women for America, an advocacy group which used her
case to advance its own conservative ideological agenda. To be sure, we need to meet our friends as
individuals and not as proponents or pawns, of an ideological movement.
Regardless of whether they are our friends or strangers whose behavior we are
observing and seeking to evaluate and understand, treating people as mere
agents of the political movements in which they are caught up is disrespectful
of their individuality, and fails to recognize the possibility that they well
might not agree with, or even be aware of or fully understand, all of the goals
of the movements their actions are advancing. But it is equally important to
recognize when people are participating in the promotion of a movement. Vicki
Frost’s outlook had been molded by a conservative ideological movement well
before the advocacy groups got involved in the litigation. She came to her view
that the public school was indoctrinating children after reading tracts against
so-called secular humanism that were published by Christian publication
companies, widely circulated in the evangelical community.[27] The
theological battle against “secular humanism” promoted by those tracts has been
being waged for centuries. Vicki Frost may not have fully understood the cause
in which she was participating, but she was advancing it, and it was shaping
her, nonetheless. Even the leaders of the religious conservative
movement against secularism may not fully understand their cause or completely
identify with it. They may have only a partial understanding or be committed to
only some of the mission. They may have ulterior motives. They may think they
are in control of the movement they are helming, when actually there are forces
beyond their control, which are at least partly in control of them. The same is
true of our colleagues who advance the anti-secularist cause. And the same is
true of those of us who are products of, and participants in, the secularist
movement, whether we are aware of its existence and its effect on us, or, more
likely, not. But what do we do when our colleagues and friends advance a cause
which is anathema to our own values? Is it an act of friendship to try to
change their minds or is that an act of condescension or, alternatively, appeasement?
Or is it an act of complicity in the anti-secularist cause? Asking, not for a
friend, but for myself. Nomi Maya Stolzenberg is the Nathan and Lilly Shapell Chair in Law at the
University of Southern California School of Law. You can contact her at nstolzenberg@law.usc.edu. [1] More exactly, the jury failed to reach a verdict on one of the
charges. The rest of the charges all resulted in acquittals. [2] See “The Confrontation of Religious Faith and Civil Religion,” 39
DePaul L. Rev. 1947 (1990); “Religious Language and the Public Square,” 105
Harv. L. Rev. 2061 (1992)(reviewing Michael Perry’s Love and Power: The Role of Religion and Morality in American Politics);
“Some Reflections on Multiculturalism, ‘Equal Concern and Respect,” and the
Establishment Clause of the First Amendment,” 27 U. Richmond L. Rev. 989
(1993); “The Multicultures of Belief and Disbelief,” 92 Mich. L. Rev. 1873
(1994)(reviewing Stephen Carter’s The
Culture of Disbelief: How American Law and Politics Trivialize Religious
Devotion and Stephen Bates’s Battleground:
One Mother’s Crusade, the Religious Right, and the Struggle for Control of Our
Classrooms). Sandy returned to the theme with a second round of essays in
1997 and a volume of collected works, which bears the title of this symposium,
published in 2003. See “Abstinence and Exclusion: What Does Liberalism Demand
of the Religiously Oriented (Would Be) Judge,” in Religion and Contemporary Liberalism (Paul J. Weithman, ed., 1997);
“On Political Boundary Lines, Multiculturalism, and the Liberal State,” 72 Ind.
L. J. 403 (1997); Wrestling with
Diversity (2003). It bears mention that in this same time period, Sandy
also wrote about race and slavery, making him one of a small number of legal
scholars to write about both race and religion. See “Slavery in the Canon of
Constitutional Law,” 69 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 1087 (1992); “They Whisper:
Reflections on Flags, Monuments, and State Holidays, and the Construction of
Social Meaning in a Multicultural Society,” 70 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 1079 (1995);
“Allocating Honor and Acting Honorably: Some Reflections Provoked by the
Cardozo Conference on Slavery,” 17 Cardozo L. Rev. 1969 (1995-96). [3] “Multicultures,” supra note
2, 1876. [4] Id., at 1878, 1880. [5] It is notable that this is the same time period in which he first
began to write about law as performance. See Sanford Levinson & Jack
Balkin, “Law, Music, and Other Performing Arts,” 139 U. Penn. L. Rev. 1597
(1991). [6] See Carter, Culture of Disbelief,
supra note 2. [7] “Multicultures,” supra note
7, at 1879. [8] By “identify with the secular state,” I mean, precisely, recognizing
that the state has to be secular in nature (as opposed to being on founded on,
and serving to implement, divine law.) Many who accept that proposition–that
is, those who are secularist, as Sandy and I both define the term–would not
necessarily identify themselves as “secularists” or accept the description of themselves
as “identifying with” the secular state. But unless one is prepared to accept,
or even welcome, the dissolution of the state (in other words, unless one is a
true anarchist), to reject the theocratic state in favor of a secular one is,
in the sense in which I am using the term, to identify with the secularist
state (or secular statist) project. On the anarchist alternative, see James R.
Martel, Anarchist Prophets: Disappointing Vision and the Power of Collective
Sight (2022). [9] Id. Note that while this definition requires the rejection of the
epistemological claim that the divine will is ascertainable, it does not
necessarily require (though it may include) rejecting the ontological claim
that there is a divine being who wills us to act in accord with divine law.
Sandy characterizes himself as more agnostic than atheistic and he attributes
his receptivity to religious arguments that “can have no real meaning for me”
in part to this equivocation regarding the ontological claim. But that being
the case, there is no reason to classify all secularists as non-believers. One
can believe in the ontological proposition of the existence of the divine (and
divine law), yet reject the proposition that the content of the divine will is
ascertainable by human beings. Indeed, not only can the belief in the existence of God and the disbelief in the
knowability of the content of divine law coexist, it is precisely this
combination of (religious) beliefs that gave rise to the original political
theology of secularism, which, I have argued elsewhere, constitutes a, if not
the, intellectual origin of liberalism. See Nomi Maya Stolzenberg, “The
Profanity of Law,” in Law and the Sacred
(Austin Sarat, Lawrence Douglass and Martha Merrill Umphrey, eds., Stanford U.
Press, 2007), 29-90; “Political Theology With a Difference,“ 4 U.C. Irvine Law
Review 407 (2014); “From Eternity to Here: Divine Accommodation and the Lost
Language of Law,” in The Oxford Handbook
of Law and Humanities (Simon Stern, Maksymilian Del Mar, and Bernadette
Meyler, eds., Oxford University Press, 2019). I rely heavily in this work on
Amos Funkenstein’s historical theorization of what he called “secularist
theology” and Kathy Eden’s work on the classical and Christian origins of
humanism. See Amos Funkenstein, Theology
and the Scientific Imagination from the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century
(first published in 1986, with a new edition, with a forward by Jonathan
Sheehan, released in 2019); Kathy Eden, Hermeneutics
and the Rhetorical Tradition: Chapters in the Ancient Legacy and Its Humanist
Reception (1997). [10] See Kenji Yoshino, Covering: The
Hidden Assault on our Civil Rights (2006)(developing the idea of “covering”
as a distinct form of discrimination). [11] For a positive
assessment, see Rodney K. Smith, “Treating Others As Our Own: Professor
Levinson, Friendship, Religion, and the Public Square,” 38 Tulsa L. Rev. 731
(2013); But see Robert Justin Lipkin, Reconstructing the Public
Square, 24 Cardozo L. Rev. 2025, 2074 (2003)(querying, “is this not a rather hollow commitment to
religion in the public square? If [religious] views are likely to be
unpersuasive ‘which will be the case, almost by definition,’ [according to
Sandy], is one truly engaging religious citizens in democratic debate or merely
paying lip service to such engagement?” [12] Sandy is unsparing in his analysis of his and his fellow secularists’
ultimate close-mindedness to policy arguments and knowledge claims that are
based on theological propositions. See “Multicultures,” at 1880. (“Could anyone
claiming to be a secularist ever not treat
theologically based arguments as “inferior”—in the operational sense of
capacity to persuade—even if one admired their intellectual intricacy? To be
persuaded by a theological argument is, I think, just to say that one is not in
fact a secularist.”) [13] “Multicultures,” supra note
2, at 1884. [14] Id., at 1880. [15] Sanford Levinson, On Political Boundary Lines, Multiculturalism, and the Liberal State, 72 Ind. L. J. 403 (1997). Sandy is here discussing the analysis of Grumet v. Kiryas Joel put forward by
Judith Failer; see Judith Lynn Failer, The Draw and Drawbacks of Religious Enclaves in
a Constitutional Democracy: Hasidic Public Schools in Kiryas Joel, 72 IND.
L.J. 383 (1997). [16] “Getting Religion”: Religion, Diversity, and Community in Public and
Private Schools,” in Wrestling with
Diversity, supra note 2. [17] As this essay went
to press, the Supreme Court handed down its decision in Carson v. Makin,
holding that Maine’s requirement that otherwise generally available tuition
assistance payments by the state only be used at “nonsectarian’ schools is
unconstitutional. Carson v. Makin, slip op. (06/21/22). [18] See “Getting Religion,” supra
note 14. [19] Dobbs v. Jackson
Women’s Health Organization, No. 19-1392 (U.S.
filed June 18, 2020) (draft opinion), https://perma.cc/Z84J-5UF4. [20] See Engel v. Vitale, 370 U.S. 421 (1962); Abington v. Schempp, 374
U.S. 203 (1963). On the conservative reaction to these two cases, which brought
about the coalition between conservative Protestants and conservative Catholics
we know now as the Christian Right, see Sarah Barringer Gordon, The Spirit of the
Law: Religious Voices and the Constitution in Modern America (2010); Noah
Feldman, Divided by God: America’s Church-State Problem—And What We Should Do
About It (2005). [21] Among the alternative explanations is the hypothesis that white
enrollment in private schools increased after Brown v. Board mandated the desegregation of public schools because
white families did not want their children to attend school with Black
children. See Anthony M. Champagne, “The Segregation Academy and the Law,” 42
J. Negro Education 58 (1973); Marilyn Grady and Sharon C. Hoffman, “Segregation
Academies Then and School Choice Configurations Today in the Deep South,” 7
Contemp. Issues in Educ. Leadership 1 (2018). [22]
https://yaffed.org/what-we-do/ [23] See Anne C. Dailey, In Locos
Republicae, unpublished manuscript on file with the author. [24] See Carson, supra note 17. [25] See Micah Schwartzman & Nelson Tebbe, “Establishment Clause
Appeasement,” 2019 S. Ct. Rev. 271; Nelson Tebbe & Micah Schwartzman,
“Re-Upping Appeasement: Religious Freedom and Judicial Politics in the 2019 Term,”
https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3694589. [26] Multicultures, at 1880, fn. 41. For further elaboration of
this point, see my fn. 9, above. [27] Nomi Maya
Stolzenberg, “He Drew a Circle That Shut Me Out”: Assimilation,
Indoctrination, and the Paradox of a Liberal Education, 106 Harv. L. Rev.
581, 594 (1992-1993).
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |