Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts The Common Good as a Universal Framework
|
Wednesday, July 27, 2022
The Common Good as a Universal Framework
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Adrian Vermeule, Common Good Constitutionalism (Polity Press 2022). Adrian Vermeule I
thank Jack Balkin for his good offices in organizing the symposium on Common
Good Constitutionalism (CGC), and also thank the participants
for their thoughts. In this brief contribution, I will offer some thoughts in
reply. My discussion will by no means be comprehensive, with the understanding
that silence as to any of the points the participants have raised is not
necessarily to be taken as signifying either agreement or disagreement. Rather
I will address some points that seem to me of the greatest general interest,
and on which I have currently have something to contribute. Thus I pass over in
silence the excellent contributions of Conor Casey and Daniel Bell, not because
I disagree with them, but simply because in the former case I have no impartial
standpoint from which to assess Casey’s suggestion that there is a deep
continuity to my own work over time, and in the latter case because Bell’s
effort to read the classical legal tradition in light of Confucian legal theory
is a subject that I will have to study more deeply before I can say anything in
a serious academic register — although I have expressed some informal
preliminary reactions. I
begin with Sandy Levinson, whose contribution helpfully engaged the ideas from
the inside, as it were, rather than assessing them from an external standpoint
for conformity to a laundry list of progressive positions (a chronic hazard for
the progressive mind, which is dominated by the practical as opposed to the
speculative reason). I do have some quibbles with Levinson’s discussion.
Levinson, for example, seems to suggest that natural law theory is either just
coterminous with Catholic legal theory, or at least necessarily presupposes
Catholicism. But this is both historically and theologically erroneous.
Historically, natural law theory originates with the pagan Greeks, finds its
way by complex pathways to Rome, and is already brought to a high pitch of
sophistication by the Roman lawyers of the late Republic and early Empire,
largely before Christianity became dominant. When Gaius, a famous jurist of the
second century A.D., says (as later reported in Digest 7.5.2.1) that it
is impossible to establish a usufruct in perishables even by positive decree,
because “natural reason cannot be altered [even] by the authority
of the Senate,” he is not speaking from specifically Catholic premises, but
rather about the intrinsic nature of the relevant legal principles.
Theologically, Catholicism itself holds that the natural law is written in the
hearts of all men, and is in principle accessible to the universal natural
reason common to all, even the unbaptized. Yet this is inessential to the main
points of Levinson’s larger discussion. Despite
these minor missteps, Levinson understands and helpfully explains that the book
has both a general and a particular part (CGC 11); it proposes a
methodological framework for approaching questions of constitutional lawmaking
and interpretation, a framework within which reasonable debates may be had as
to how the principles of the classical legal tradition cash out. An example is
a useful discussion between Jamie McGowan
and Michael Foran
about how exactly judicial review of rights works on classical premises. As
Foran puts it,
“[the book] relies on the common good as a justificatory lens of analysis,
focusing on what the overarching point and purpose of constitutionalism should
be.” A corollary, which the book explains at some length (beginning at CGC
3), is that the project is definitely not to take particular laws and customs
from a point in time and apply them uncritically today. Some historically
existing rules and customs were justifiable and others were unjust, according
to the criteria of the classical approach itself, even taking into account that
fit with extant legal materials is an aspect of justification. Rather the
methodological project is to translate and adapt the principles of the
classical legal ontology into our world and to elicit the justificatory
structure they imply. Linda McClain misses this distinction, which leaves me
unable to say anything about her contribution. That
the book argues for, or more precisely recalls, the classical structure of
justification explains Levinson’s observation that it proposes a master
“standard” or principle for constitutional government rather than a congeries
of rules. Putting aside the constraints provided by the duty to avoid intrinsic
evils, this is correct, but it is also itself a major point or feature of the
classical tradition: subject to those and other constraints the book outlines,
the theory does not even purport to specify the particular institutional rules
of any given polity, but leaves those to determination within that polity -
first at the level of constitutional law (written and unwritten), and then at successively
more specific levels of legislation, administrative action, and judicial
application to particular cases. I do go on to offer my own interpretations of
the specific determinations that have come to characterize the American
constitutional order, both in its written and unwritten aspects, but these are
(as I said at CGC 12) detachable from the book’s general methodological
theses; one can subscribe to the latter while agreeing, or contesting, the
analyses of American particulars. The
methodological generality of the classical approach also explains my rather
puzzled reaction to the contributions of Balkin and Stephen Griffin, whose main
effort is to reduce the American instantiation of the classical framework to
the civic republican tradition. Balkin seems to think that a master concern for
the common good of the res publica is in some sense uniquely civic
republican. In fact it was and is the common property of all participants in
the classical legal tradition, whether before or after the flowering of civic
republicanism in the 15th and 16th centuries, and whether they were (in the
conventional modern sense) republicans, or instead monarchists, or, like many
of the leading lawyers of the Roman and continental ius commune,
imperialists. As the comparativist Elisabeth Zoller put
it, citing the 3d century A.D. imperial lawyer UIpian, “Public law,
in the sense first defined by the Romans, is the law of res publica, literally the public
thing, that is, the public interest or common good.…The content of the res publica in Rome
was well articulated in the opening statement to the great compilation of Roman
laws that form the Digest [of the Emperor Justinian I]: ‘Public law is
that which has reference to the administration of the Roman commonwealth;
private law is that which concerns the interests of individuals; for there are
some things which are useful to the public, and others which are of benefit to
private persons’” [publicum
ius est quod ad statum rei Romanae spectat, privatum quod ad singulorum
utilitatem: sunt enim quaedam publice utilia, quaedam privatim]. Griffin,
if I am reading him correctly, rather oddly assumes that the common good is
exclusively a concept of high-level political morality, rather than a legal and
constitutional concept. In fact it was always the latter first and foremost,
and is so treated in the book; the very office of the Roman praetor was linked
to and justified by his legal mandate to
promote the bonum commune (common good). So
too, the lawyers
of the late medieval ius commune in the 12th to 15th centuries, both
before and after the advent of civic republicanism as usually defined, engaged
in endless debates over the legal relationships among empire, monarchies like
that of France, and the paradigmatic republican city-states of Italy and
elsewhere. Some took one view, some another. But they engaged in these debates
within a larger, longstanding framework and vocabulary of jurisprudential
concepts, in which the legal principle that the law of the res publica
should serve the communis utilitatis (common benefit) or bonum
commune was shared by all parties. The basic legal ontology of the
classical tradition was set long before, and independently of, the civic
republicanism of the Renaissance and early modernity that influenced (some of)
the framers. In
other words, Balkin has made a kind of category error: the classical legal
tradition and civic republicanism occupy different levels in the hierarchy of
relevant concepts. The classical legal tradition offers an ontology of legal
norms, including and subsuming both the positive written law (lex) and
background principles of legality (ius), not only the the civil law but
also the natural law and law of nations. (And of course divine law, which I do
not discuss in any detail, confining myself to the temporal ends of the civil
community. Pace a suggestion by Richard Primus, the point of this, as
explained at CGC 29, is not at all to bracket the question of ultimate
ends for the sake of civil peace and out of respect for comprehensive
disagreements, but rather on grounds of the scholarly division of labor, in
order to respect the limits of my own competence as a civil lawyer rather than
a canon lawyer or theologian). Although the classical tradition incorporates a
subset of political morality within law, namely the subset bearing on the
virtues of general justice and regnative prudence, of which the common good is
the object, the classical legal ontology is compatible with a wide range of
broader commitments at the higher level of political morality and political
theory tout court. To the extent that the framers were classical
lawyers, they might also be civic republicans, but were not the latter because
they were the former, nor the former because they were the latter. They participated
in the classical legal tradition qua lawyers drawing upon the common
fund of jurisprudential concepts available in their time, the mainstream
Western legal ontology, which could be and was used by lawyers with all sorts
of higher-level commitments of political morality. If
that ontology was agnostic on some dimensions, it was not at all so on others.
What is clear, for example, is that the framers’ legal ontology was simply not
that of the modern positivist, and it is a wild distortion of their public
understandings and arguments to read them as though they were modern
positivists. This point explains my reaction to the thoughtful contribution of
Richard Primus, who correctly says that at the stage of lawmaking, as well as
that of legal interpretation, not just any legislation (or constitutional
lawmaking) is compatible with the classical conception of the common good as
the proper and natural end of constitutional government. Legislation rightly
understood represents a determination of background principles of the natural
law, ordered to the common good. Conversely, legislation aiming, for example,
to maximize the freedom of individuals from all unchosen constraints, including
the constraints of political and social obligation, familial relationships and
perhaps even of the human body itself, would on the classical view fail to make
law in the fullest sense, at least insofar as it is ordered solely to the
private good of individuals rather than the public good of the community. Such
legislation would represent a kind of violent pseudo-law, a perversion of law,
as Aquinas puts it - although as Aquinas also notes, the common good may
require that pseudo-law must be obeyed anyway, if the harms of disobedience
would be greater than the benefits. Furthermore, there are separate
institutional questions, which different polities may answer differently, about
which actors in the legal system are authorized to identify pseudo-law, and
what if anything they are authorized to do about it. My
difference with Primus, if we have one, is that I do not think that invocation
of the non-positivist category of pseudo-law is confined to self-identified
classical lawyers, by any means. It is just that classical lawyers are uniquely
transparent about it and uniquely willing to explain how the category follows
from the other parts of their theory. When Professor Neil Siegel and Dalia
Lithwick write
that Dobbs v.
Jackson is a “lawless” decision, it irresistibly brings to mind the
natural lawyer’s shorthand that “an unjust law is no law at all.” The
progressive lawyers who dominate the American legal academy and commentariat
have their conceptions of ius and of higher law just as much as natural
lawyers do, when push comes to shove. It is at best unclear that there are any
consistent positivists on the American legal scene, and even whether there could
be any. As the book argues, positivism is essentially illusory, not only for
the jurisprudential reason that considerations of legal justice inevitably
become necessary both to make and to interpret positive law, but also because
positivism is ultimately an academic theory in the pejorative sense, one that
is immediately discarded when real stakes emerge. The only jurisprudential
question, in the end, is whose conception of ius is correct, and the
only political question is which conception will prevail. Let
me end with another important point raised by Levinson, which deserves more
detailed discussion elsewhere: the issue of “nationalist parochialism.”
Levinson correctly discerns that I am not a “nationalist,” in the sense that I
believe (and the book argues, following the tradition) that the public
authority of particular national states is founded on the ius gentium, a
transnational common enterprise developed by and among recognizably lawful
constitutional polities. As the Digest (1.1.5) famously put
it, “as a consequence of this law of nations, wars were introduced, nations
differentiated, kingdoms founded, [and] territories distinguished” [ex hoc
iure gentium introducta bella, discrete gentes, regna condita, dominia
distincta]. This classical conception is explicit in our law as late as the
Curtiss-Wright
case in 1936, in which our Supreme Court, finding “the warrant for its
conclusions not in the provisions of the Constitution, but in the law of
nations,” held that the the external sovereignty of the United States “did not
depend upon the affirmative grants of the Constitution” and that “[t]he Union
existed before the Constitution.” Although in limited circumstances,
nationalism can serve as a useful second-best and temporary expedient for
resisting the impositions of a larger liberal order, such as that of the
current European Union, if nationalism is taken as a first-best master
principle of the constitutional order, it is a betrayal rather than an
application of the classical tradition. In their modern incarnations in the
19th century, nationalism and liberalism were born twins, and often became the
incestuous parents of legal positivism. I
would add, however, that the main purveyors of nationalist parochialism, at
least on the American legal scene, are not the figures that Levinson mentions.
Rather nationalist parochialism appears in a particularly virulent form in
American originalism and the conservative legal movement that surrounds it. At
panel after panel run by the Federalist Society, one can actually hear legal
scholars claim with a straight face that originalism is the only way to do law qua
law — a view whose startling implication is that no one was doing law in the
Western legal tradition until roughly yesterday, and that throughout vast
stretches of Europe, Latin America and Asia, “from
China to Peru,” no law is done today. This puts mere parochialism to
shame. Likewise, reputable American lawyers can actually be heard to claim that
the United States’ constitutional oath entails originalism, ignoring (or
perhaps simply unaware) that the world is full of constitutional systems that
require very
similar oaths, yet that also utterly eschew originalism in anything
like its American sense. As a broad generalization, legal systems in Europe, Latin America, and
other parts of the world influenced by the classical tradition retain a lively
sense of participating in a larger transnational legal enterprise, to which the
conservative legal movement in the United States — largely for reasons
involving the unique historical and intellectual position of the American
empire and its elites after World War II — is unfortunately oblivious. Adrian Vermeule is the Ralph S. Tyler, Jr. Professor of Constitutional Law at Harvard Law School. You can reach him by e-mail at adrian.vermeule@icloud.com.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |