Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Stiff Joints Don’t Bend Anymore The Parliamentarian’s Curious Definition of “Merely Incidental” On Friendship, Tolerance, and Religious Liberty Wrestling with Religion in Law LevinsonFest on Wrestling with Religious Diversity The Common Good as a Universal Framework
|
Sunday, July 31, 2022
Stiff Joints Don’t Bend Anymore
Guest Blogger
This
post was prepared for a roundtable on Wrestling with
Religious Diversity,
convened as part of LevinsonFest 2022—a year-long series
gathering scholars from diverse disciplines and viewpoints to reflect on Sandy
Levinson’s influential work in constitutional law. Carol Nackenoff ‘there is room for play in the joints’ between what the Establishment Clause permits and the Free Exercise Clause compels.[1] It is an honor to
participate in this celebration of Sandy Levinson’s 40 years at the University
of Texas at Austin. Sandy’s enthusiasm for interacting with smart
undergraduates led him to accept my invitation to serve as an examiner for my
Constitutional Law honors seminar at Swarthmore, and he has also been
Swarthmore’s Constitution Day speaker. In Wrestling with Diversity (2003), Sandy
Levinson is especially concerned with the arrangements through which Americans
might interact peaceably with other Americans with religious and cultural
worldviews different from their own. Even in the founding era, a number of
influential people thought those in the new United States were diverse enough
to be worrisome—there were those German-speakers in Pennsylvania; there were
Quakers, Catholics, and Jews; people living in southern states and those on the
western frontier were seen as having such different values from those in the
northern Atlantic states that it was hard to imagine how they might form a
single union.[2]
Sandy argues there was no singular “People” in whose name the Constitution of
1787 was created. Since 1787, more elements of the population have been
included in the U.S. citizenry, and the nation is comprised of a much more
diverse array of people (religiously, culturally) than at the founding. Sandy
searches for solutions that might achieve “some kind of unum among the pluribus
of American society.”[3]
Toward this end, he finds exposure to other worldviews necessary—secular
perspectives for those in insular religious communities and diverse religious
perspectives for those who live in highly secular ones. Today, this looks
like an increasingly tall order, and the Court might even be impeding, rather
than aiding, such goals. A focus on recent constitutional struggles illuminates
some difficulties and stakes in wrestling with religious diversity and diverse
views about the place of religion in the public realm. The Court has weighed in
on quite a few blockbuster religion clause cases since Wrestling was published. Not only are Establishment and Free
Exercise Clause cases favorites on the Roberts Court’s docket, but many cases
involve their intersection. Friday, July 29, 2022
The Parliamentarian’s Curious Definition of “Merely Incidental”
David Super
Now that Sens. Schumer
and Manchin have reached agreement on the Inflation Reduction Act (IRA), the
Senate Parliamentarian’s role again comes to the fore. She will have two crucial functions. First, she will
rule on which provisions on the agreed legislation meet the Congressional
Budget Act’s requirements for inclusion in a “reconciliation” bill (the
so-called “Byrd Rule”). This is crucial
because, with united Republican opposition, the IRA can only pass through the narrow
exemption from filibusters that the Act provides to budget reconciliation
bills. And second, the Parliamentarian
must decide which amendments to that legislation may be offered on the Senate
floor. Although the Act caps the amount
of time that may be spent on floor debate, it does not limit the number of
amendments put to a vote so long as those amendments comply with the Act’s rules
for germaneness and its restrictions on the contents of reconciliation
bills. Senate Republicans have expressed
no interest in improving the legislation, but they do seek to force Democrats
to cast politically damaging votes to defeat their amendments. And because the Democrats’ majority is so
narrow, every single Democrat must vote against every single “poison pill”
amendment for the legislation to survive.
Several of the Congressional
Budget Act’s restrictions on reconciliation legislation enforce the congressional
budget resolution that authorized the bill.
Because the budget resolution under which Democrats are moving this bill
passed over a year ago, when hopes were much higher, the IRA will easily fall
within all budgetary constraints. Republican
amendments could theoretically be ruled out of order for breaching budgetary
ceilings, but Democrats likely would be only too happy to vote down “budget-buster”
amendments that would shrink the $300 billion in deficit reduction the IRA
contains. As a result, the provisions
of the Congressional Budget Act most likely to affect the IRA debate are those
designed to keep non-budgetary matters from hijacking the reconciliation vehicle
when they lack the support to move as regular legislation. In particular, she will have to apply section
313(b)(1)(D), which declares that “a provision shall be considered
extraneous if it produces changes in outlays or revenues which are merely
incidental to the non-budgetary components of the provision”. Neither the Parliamentarian
nor the Senate as a whole have articulated a clear definition of what it means for
a budgetary effect to be “merely incidental” to non-budgetary components. Obviously one could not rewrite the
Endangered Species Act or the Civil Rights Act of 1964 and slip it into a reconciliation
bill by adding some trivial fee somewhere.
But how should less extreme cases be decided? No minimum dollar threshold
can do the job: small revenue increases or
spending cuts can add up to have a significant impact on the deficit. And surely a small fiscal effect could be
merely incidental to an overhaul of the nation’s telecommunications statutes
yet not merely incidental to the treatment of import duties on day-minders. Several years ago,
the Parliamentarian rejected Republican efforts to exclude Planned Parenthood
from Medicaid on reconciliation legislation.
She acknowledged that doing so might save some money but believed that
restricting abortion, rather than lowering Medicaid’s costs, was the primary
motive of the provision’s authors. On the other hand,
she allowed Republicans to gut protections for the Arctic National Wildlife
Refuge on the 2017 reconciliation act. A
strong argument could be made that aiding oil and gas companies, and weakening
environmental protection generally, were far more central to the proponents’
multi-year campaign to drill in the refuge than the relatively meager federal
revenues anticipated. The
Parliamentarian concluded, however, that the revenues were enough to defeat a “merely
incidental” point of order. Throughout much of 2021, the Parliamentarian batted down several proposals to liberalize
immigration laws as part of the Build Back Better reconciliation bill under consideration
at that time. Legalizing undocumented
immigrants outside of reconciliation is very difficult because the
Congressional Budget Office scores many such measures as having a large cost because
it believes the immigrants’ family members (many of whom are U.S. citizens) would
then feel more at ease accessing human services programs. This would seem a
classic case of the nation deciding on its fiscal priorities, the very purpose
of the reconciliation vehicle. The
Parliamentarian ruled, however, that because many people passionately support helping
immigrants and are largely indifferent to the fiscal impact of doing so, those
fiscal effects were “merely incidental” to the non-budgetary effects on
immigrants. I disagreed
with that ruling at the time – and uncertainties about its basis contributed to
Democrats’ disastrous decision to delay moving the Build Back Better
reconciliation bill – but it is now established precedent.
Republicans seem
unlikely to try to provoke votes on abortion next week, but the other two
precedents could be important. The deal between Sens.
Schumer and Manchin contains so provisions for oil and gas leasing on federal
lands. Many environmentalists could do
without expanding fossil fuel consumption, but leading groups recognize that
these provisions are essential to holding the whole package together, with its
transformational initiatives supporting renewable energy development. Based on her ruling on the Arctic Refuge, the
Parliamentarian ought to allow this provision.
Republicans surely
would like to force Democrats to vote on various anti-immigrant measures. For example, they may try to force the
Administration to restrict persecution victims’ ability to claim asylum in this
country, as international law requires.
The fiscal effects of these provisions are likely to be quite trivial. Moreover, much of their fiscal impact is
likely to be on programs funded with discretionary appropriations, which does
not count for reconciliation purposes because those programs budgets are fixed
in appropriations bills. These would seem
to be straightforward examples of proposed changes in law with a large
real-world impact and a “merely incidental” fiscal side. These also would fit the Parliamentarian’s
rationale for rejecting immigration proposals a year ago: their motivation is hostility to immigrants –
or, more precisely, seeking to mobilize voters who are hostile to immigrants –
rather than any impact on the public fisc. More broadly, if
the Parliamentarian were to allow any anti-immigrant amendments to come to a
vote after blocking all pro-immigrant legislative proposals a year ago, she
would create a procedural regime with a deeply unbalanced substantive effect: immigrants’ opponents may pursue their
passions through reconciliation while immigrants’ supporters may not. For a Parliamentarian who cares more than some
judges about avoiding the appearance of favoritism, deviating from her strict
exclusion of immigration law changes from reconciliation could raise serious
concerns. Once the current
legislation has been completed, the Parliamentarian could do a great service to
the Senate – and to those (including the House of Representatives, the White
House, the Congressional Budget Office, and the Joint Committee on Taxation)
who depend on the Senate – if she would publish a clear, systematic statement
of how she interprets “merely incidental”.
Whatever the merits of a case-by-case method of statutory interpretation
may be in the courts, her failure to issue opinions explaining her rulings is
causing considerable confusion and wasted effort while damaging confidence in
her office. @DavidASuper1 On Friendship, Tolerance, and Religious Liberty
Guest Blogger
This post was prepared for a roundtable on Wrestling with
Religious Diversity, convened as part of LevinsonFest 2022—a
year-long series gathering scholars from diverse disciplines and viewpoints to
reflect on Sandy Levinson’s influential work in constitutional law. Douglas Laycock Sandy Levinson has
been my friend and colleague for more than forty years. We were hired at the
University of Texas Law School more or less simultaneously in 1980. We were
both in our thirties, we both came with tenure, and we were both deeply
interested in constitutional law. I delayed my arrival for a year, because my bride
was heavily pregnant that summer. Once I arrived, Sandy
and I sought each other out. I probably know as much about his views on law and
religion from things he has said in private, and on the Conlawprof list serve
(private in the sense that I am forbidden to quote it or cite it), as from
anything he has formally published. But I will not breach any confidences;
Sandy has published his own account of the biographical history I draw on here,
in a 1993 lecture at the University of
Richmond Law School. Sandy is an eclectic
essayist, seemingly interested in just about everything—and in problematizing
everything. His essays generally raise questions and only sometimes offer even
tentative answers or solutions. He accepts nothing at face value, and rarely
finds any text clear. He admits to having become a constitutional crank, fearing the many
defects in our eighteenth-century Constitution more than he fears a Trumpist or
hard-right takeover of a new constitutional convention. My approach to
scholarship and to lawyering is very different from his. But with respect to
the law of religious liberty, Sandy and I have much in common. We are both
firmly committed secularists who are broadly willing to protect people with
religious beliefs that we often find wildly implausible and, sometimes,
abhorrent or even dangerous. Sandy credits personal biography for his religious
tolerance, and as it turns out, we share a very similar formative experience. Thursday, July 28, 2022
Wrestling with Religion in Law
Guest Blogger
This post was prepared for a roundtable on Wrestling with Religious Diversity, convened as
part of LevinsonFest 2022—a year-long
series gathering scholars from diverse disciplines and viewpoints to reflect on
Sandy Levinson’s influential work in constitutional law. John Olusegun
Adenitire In the last
chapter of Wrestling with Diversity, Sandy Levinson and Rachel
Levinson ask ‘why should practices rooted in religious belief be treated
differently than "cultural norms," whether for good (…) or
potentially even for ill (…)?’. Their conclusion can be fairly summarised as
stating that religion and culture are not really distinguishable so that there
is no persuasive reason for treating the former differently from the latter. Never mind
that the law, including the US Federal Constitution, places special privileges
(Free Exercise) and disadvantages (Non Establishment), over things that judges
label religious rather than cultural. But, in line with Sandy’s encouragement
not to idolise the US Constitution, they prod us to think beyond this brute
fact which is only of interest to positivist lawyers. Accordingly, they argue
that as a matter of first principle, it is wrong for state officials to treat
worse parents who refuse to treat their child with effective Western medicine
because they favour ineffective traditional Chinese medicine compared to
parents who favour ineffective Christian Science prayer. My view is
that the sentiment behind, and many of the arguments of the chapter, are
correct. Ineffective traditional Chinese medicine and ineffective Christian Science
prayer should be equally penalised if they lead to the same amount of harm for
a child. Yet, as the chapter in Wrestling
with Diversity attests to, in the United States the latter is treated with
more magnanimity by state officials because it is considered religious. The
Free Exercise Clause, Federal and State level Freedom of Restoration Acts, as
well as some statutes protecting faith healing would cut the Christian Science
parents some slack; but not the parents who prefer traditional Chinese
medicine. Surely, this state of affairs is deeply unfair, especially if you
agree with Sandy and Rachel that religion and culture are not easily
distinguishable either in theory or in application. I agree with
this view. Yet, the argument in that chapter seems to me to concede more than
it is due. The issue is not that ineffective Christian Science prayer and
ineffective traditional Chinese medicine should be treated equally because
religion and culture are too similar. The issue for me is that the chapter
concedes in the first place that there is something in the world that the law
should recognise as religion, even though, as it turns out, it is difficult to
differentiate from culture. That concession should not be made: the law should
not recognise in the first place the category of religion for reasons of
conceptual clarity and fairness. Let me explain. LevinsonFest on Wrestling with Religious Diversity
Guest Blogger
Ashley Moran We’re pleased to share a fascinating
and timely set of essays from our recent LevinsonFest 2022 panel, exploring
constitutional challenges related to religion in plural societies. The roundtable includes essays from
John Adenitire (Queen Mary, University of London) on whether the law
should recognize religion as a unique category, Douglas Laycock
(University of Virginia) on friendship, tolerance, and religious liberty, Carol
Nackenoff (Swarthmore College) on religious liberty at the intersection of
the Establishment and Free Exercise clauses, Jaclyn Neo (National
University of Singapore) on whether state neutrality toward religion can hold
amid increasing religious diversification, Intisar Rabb (Harvard
University) on pluralistic legal interpretation amid multiple constitutional
faiths, Mark Scarberry (Pepperdine University) on whether minority
faiths have fostered American unity, and Nomi Stolzenberg (University of
Southern California) on bridging the divide between secularists and anti-secularists. A response from Sandy Levinson
(University of Texas at Austin) addresses all of these themes in assessing the
relationship between law and religion over the last forty years. The event discussion also
included remarks from Sally Barringer Gordon (University of
Pennsylvania), tracing the legal battles that shaped postwar Black spiritual
life, and is available on the panel webpage. We hope
you enjoy the discussions! Ashley Moran is a Postdoctoral
Fellow with the Comparative Constitutions Project and Distinguished Scholar
with UT’s Robert Strauss Center for International Security and Law. You can
contact her at ashleymoran@utexas.edu. Wednesday, July 27, 2022
The Common Good as a Universal Framework
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Adrian Vermeule, Common Good Constitutionalism (Polity Press 2022). Adrian Vermeule I
thank Jack Balkin for his good offices in organizing the symposium on Common
Good Constitutionalism (CGC), and also thank the participants
for their thoughts. In this brief contribution, I will offer some thoughts in
reply. My discussion will by no means be comprehensive, with the understanding
that silence as to any of the points the participants have raised is not
necessarily to be taken as signifying either agreement or disagreement. Rather
I will address some points that seem to me of the greatest general interest,
and on which I have currently have something to contribute. Thus I pass over in
silence the excellent contributions of Conor Casey and Daniel Bell, not because
I disagree with them, but simply because in the former case I have no impartial
standpoint from which to assess Casey’s suggestion that there is a deep
continuity to my own work over time, and in the latter case because Bell’s
effort to read the classical legal tradition in light of Confucian legal theory
is a subject that I will have to study more deeply before I can say anything in
a serious academic register — although I have expressed some informal
preliminary reactions. I
begin with Sandy Levinson, whose contribution helpfully engaged the ideas from
the inside, as it were, rather than assessing them from an external standpoint
for conformity to a laundry list of progressive positions (a chronic hazard for
the progressive mind, which is dominated by the practical as opposed to the
speculative reason). I do have some quibbles with Levinson’s discussion.
Levinson, for example, seems to suggest that natural law theory is either just
coterminous with Catholic legal theory, or at least necessarily presupposes
Catholicism. But this is both historically and theologically erroneous.
Historically, natural law theory originates with the pagan Greeks, finds its
way by complex pathways to Rome, and is already brought to a high pitch of
sophistication by the Roman lawyers of the late Republic and early Empire,
largely before Christianity became dominant. When Gaius, a famous jurist of the
second century A.D., says (as later reported in Digest 7.5.2.1) that it
is impossible to establish a usufruct in perishables even by positive decree,
because “natural reason cannot be altered [even] by the authority
of the Senate,” he is not speaking from specifically Catholic premises, but
rather about the intrinsic nature of the relevant legal principles.
Theologically, Catholicism itself holds that the natural law is written in the
hearts of all men, and is in principle accessible to the universal natural
reason common to all, even the unbaptized. Yet this is inessential to the main
points of Levinson’s larger discussion. Despite
these minor missteps, Levinson understands and helpfully explains that the book
has both a general and a particular part (CGC 11); it proposes a
methodological framework for approaching questions of constitutional lawmaking
and interpretation, a framework within which reasonable debates may be had as
to how the principles of the classical legal tradition cash out. An example is
a useful discussion between Jamie McGowan
and Michael Foran
about how exactly judicial review of rights works on classical premises. As
Foran puts it,
“[the book] relies on the common good as a justificatory lens of analysis,
focusing on what the overarching point and purpose of constitutionalism should
be.” A corollary, which the book explains at some length (beginning at CGC
3), is that the project is definitely not to take particular laws and customs
from a point in time and apply them uncritically today. Some historically
existing rules and customs were justifiable and others were unjust, according
to the criteria of the classical approach itself, even taking into account that
fit with extant legal materials is an aspect of justification. Rather the
methodological project is to translate and adapt the principles of the
classical legal ontology into our world and to elicit the justificatory
structure they imply. Linda McClain misses this distinction, which leaves me
unable to say anything about her contribution.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |