Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Mad Love: Kopel’s Defense of Originalism
|
Thursday, June 02, 2022
Mad Love: Kopel’s Defense of Originalism
Andrew Koppelman
Don’t marry someone expecting to change them. If you aren’t happy with the way they are,
and you won’t be able to endure their company unless they radically remake
their lives, then they are entitled to suspect that you don’t really love them
at all. And if your professed love is
tied to a desire to destroy what they care about, then your love becomes hard
to distinguish from hatred. You’re in
love with a fantasy, not the real person. David Kopel recently posted
on the Volokh Conspiracy blog an extended critique of my article, Why
Do (Some) Originalists Hate America?. In it he purports to reject, but inadvertently
confirms, my central claims. He writes:
“I can tell you for sure that everybody at the think tank where I work, the Independence
Institute, loves America.” But in fact
they love a fantasy America, not the country we actually live in. They reject the actual, post-New Deal America
that exists today, which is one of the best places in history for human beings
to inhabit. I like it here. Does he? In my article, I critique a prominent group of originalists,
among whom I name Kopel. (Incidentally, he lists Samuel Bray
among the writers I critique, but nothing I say is critical of Bray.) These writers, I say, aspire to a regime whose
fundamental law is only to be found in ancient archives. Their mysterious contents take years to
unearth, layer by layer. With new
discoveries, bodies of established law are unexpectedly invalidated and
discarded. Others, previously rejected,
spring back into life as the scholars revise earlier conclusions. The operations of government are in constant
confusion. This state of affairs is
likely to persist indefinitely. This is, I argue, a “weird political
ideal.” It is so distant from the regime
we inhabit that one can embrace it only if one regards the status quo as
radically defective. The originalist
attack on Obamacare, of which Kopel was a principal proponent (notably in an
extended exchange I had with him in the Yale Law Journal Online),
contemplated such a severe narrowing of Congressional power so severe as to
require amputation of large parts of today’s federal government. Kopel never quite owns up to the radicalism of his views. Instead, he makes a number of points that
sound anodyne but have scary entailments.
“History shows that critics
of perceived unconstitutional federal action are sometimes right.” Yes, but that abstracts from just what the
critics are claiming. He writes, with
respect to Randy Barnett’s narrow reading of the commerce power: Koppelman
accurately states, "If Barnett's discoveries mean what he thinks they
mean, then much of present federal law is unconstitutional." Agreed,
especially for the extension of federal criminal law into entirely intrastate
activity. He thus draws your eye toward
federal prosecution of harmless private users of medical marijuana. But he also acknowledges that his originalism
“would create major changes in the law” of the Commerce Clause. Those whose
liberty is thus vindicated would include polluters of the air and water,
operators of dangerous workplaces, securities fraudsters, and any employer who
would like to pay less than the minimum wage.
None of them are engaged in “commerce” as Barnett (and Kopel) understand
it. Kopel reassures us that
originalism does not mandate what he concedes would be disastrous. The best current originalist research shows,
for example, that paper money is not unconstitutional, and so we are safe from the
massive economic catastrophe that a judicial declaration to the contrary would
bring about. But this is a pure
accident. Adrian Vermeule has cogently criticized “common-good originalism"
for subordinating the good of the nation to archival research: “What happens
if and when the original understanding and the common good diverge?” Vermeule’s conception of the common good
isn’t mine, but here he is right. Even
if one takes the original meaning to produce fixed and determinate results (a
doubtful proposition, as I explain in the article), nothing guarantees that
this meaning will suit the needs of modern society, or supports the legal
structures on which today’s peace and prosperity depend. Kopel
thinks that, even if this is true, it is nothing to worry about: Adherence
to the original meaning of the powers that the people have granted to the U.S.
government has never prevented the people from choosing to grant additional
powers. Eight times the people have enacted new amendments granting Congress
power "to enforce this amendment by appropriate legislation." Thus, for example, he is untroubled by the
possibility that new research on the paper money question could lead to "a
catastrophic worldwide depression." He responds: Fear not. Even if
future research overturned current understanding of the Coinage Clause, and the
Supreme Court followed suit, the Court would, for the reason Koppelman states,
likely stay its mandate, and give Congress sufficient time to make appropriate adjustments,
or for the people to make an amendment, if they so chose. In other words, although his method might
produce a constitutional crisis, the country obviously would unite in the face
of financial disaster. (Never mind that
such a judicial decision might precipitate financial catastrophe before
Congress could act.) No politician would
be reckless enough to hold the world economy hostage for some petty, short-term
gain. Oh, yeah? Consider the now-routine behavior of
Republicans every time the national debt ceiling needs to be raised. Kopel concedes that it is “partly true”
that his originalism contemplates, as I write, "a
regime whose fundamental law is only to be found in ancient archives." But, he says, “The ‘archives’ do progress
year by year. The archives are public, not mysterious.” Perhaps someday we will reach a stable consensus
on original meaning. (Since historians
still dispute some points of ancient Greek and Roman history, and since
clarifying the sources of originalism will require synthesizing, at least,
“a body of more than 70,000 documents,” we may be waiting a while.) In my article, I illustrate the point about unknowable law by
citing Kopel’s coauthored response to my defense of Obamacare, which relies on
a previously obscure understanding of the Necessary and Proper Clause. I observe that their constitutional objection
to the statute “was not even an
element of Randy Barnett’s constitutional attack on the law, the eventual basis
of the lawsuit, which was unveiled as the law was about to pass in the Senate.” I observe that their argument entails that “Congress,
at a time when it was laboriously constructing major legislation, did not know
and could not have known what the limits of its powers were.” I add: “It is perhaps illustrative of this article’s claims that I was astounded by
their initial article, which was based on constitutional objections that were
previously unknown, not only to me, but also to the other scholars who were
attacking the statute and to the judges who first declared it constitutionally
invalid.“ Kopel is unmoved. He tells
us that “in fact, Congress ‘could . . . have known what the limits of its
powers were,’ although the idea that the congressional majority cared about
constitutional limits when enacting Obamacare is fanciful.” (As I’ve noted, Congress certainly did not want
its law to be subject to legal challenge, and could easily have navigated
around the constitutional objections that were later litigated, had it known
about them.) The limits were right there
for anyone to see, in articles that had been published in the Duke and Case
Western law reviews, and in the online edition of Vanderbilt! Evidently it is irresponsible for Congress to
rely on the account of its powers that appears in the U.S. Reports. If it really cared about the Constitution, it
would not only adjudicate debates in constitutional theory, but decide that
Kopel and his colleagues are right about everything. I remain as puzzled as I ever was
by Kopel’s reasoning with respect to Obamacare.
He writes, echoing Chief Justice Roberts’s opinion in NFIB v.
Sebelius: The
power to force people to engage in
interstate commerce (to buy Obamacare insurance) is not a mere incident of
regulating existing commerce. A power to compel commerce would be a
"principal" power—"a great substantive and independent
power." No such power was granted. Neither Roberts (as I explain here) nor Kopel explains how one can
tell whether something is "a great substantive and independent
power." This is one of many places
in which originalism, originally advertised as a guarantor of judicial
restraint, ends up being a recipe for unbounded judicial discretion. Kopel writes: “Professor Koppelman was wrong to denigrate
the patriotism of people who disagree with him.” I certainly
don’t doubt his idealism, or his loyalty to America as he imagines it, but I
question whether “patriotism” is the right label for it. Steven B. Smith has recently offered a sustained
defense of patriotism, which arises from “a sense of gratitude to one’s
birthplace” and is “rooted in a rudimentary, even primordial love of
one’s own: the customs, habits, manners, and traditions that make us who and
what we are.” He regretfully observes that “The political right has
weaponized patriotism, turning it into a litmus test for determining who is a
real American.” I admit that my snarky
title parodies this weaponization. But it
is not merely snarky. It points to a
real truth. Kopel doesn’t seem to
understand what makes him what he is, and what he should be grateful for. He breathes clean air, drinks clean water,
and enjoys all the other benefits of a big federal government. He doesn’t seem to know it. Sometimes people pick the wrong
things to love. I admire Kopel’s moral
seriousness and scholarly care, qualities that the world could use more
of. But he loves and hates the wrong
things. In the Obamacare struggle, he
was one of many who honestly believed that taking health care away from millions would make Americans
freer. Libertarianism like his is routinely abused by
predators, who eagerly embrace limits on government power because they would like to defraud and injure people without being bothered by
the police.
You need to learn not to love your abuser.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |