Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts On New Autocrats, Imitation and Flattery
|
Friday, September 24, 2021
On New Autocrats, Imitation and Flattery
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Rosalind Dixon and David Landau, Abusive Constitutional Borrowing: Legal globalization and the subversion of liberal democracy (Oxford University Press, 2021). Kim Lane Scheppele Oscar Wilde could well have been
talking about a new generation of autocrats when he penned the aphorism that
“imitation is the sincerest form of flattery.” Earlier
generations of dictators toppled constitutional-democratic governments by
ordering tanks into the streets. But
coups are largely a thing of the past.
The new generation of autocrats topples constitutional-democratic
governments by ordering lawyers into action to write copycat constitutions and copycat
legislation designed to subvert the rule of law. By
imitating liberal constitutionalism (even as they are undermining it), the new
autocrats indirectly acknowledge that “[liberal] democracy is the only game in town.” They wouldn’t do what they do if they didn’t
recognize the normative power of the model that they mimic. New
autocrats aim not at revolution through force but at subversion through mimicry. Abusive
Constitutional Borrowing by Rosalind Dixon and David Landau documents the rise
of autocratic
legalism by showing how new autocrats now “borrow” constitutional ideas and
structures from “good” constitutional systems in order to use them in “bad” ways
(hence the “abuse”). From Venezuela to
Poland, from Rwanda to Thailand, from Hungary to Ecuador, from Fiji to Israel, the
pattern is clear. Aspirational
autocrats win elections – often freely and fairly the first time – and then set
about to destroy the bases of constitutional democracy that allowed them to come
to power in the first place. As these
autocrats dismantle constitutional democracy, however, they take pains to keep
up appearances, which masks to both domestic democratic publics and
international observers what is really going on. By the time that constitutional democracy is fatally
wounded, it is often too late to revive it. Dixon and Landau build their
powerful argument by developing a normative model against which to test the
transformations they document. They
identify a “minimum core” of constitutional democracy that includes regular,
free and competitive elections; respect for basic rights and freedoms; and the protection
of the institutions that guarantee both.
Then they assess the changes that they document against that
framework. Their model is elegant,
helpful and admirably neutral among different forms of liberal constitutional
order. For example, they don’t give
pride of place to “free speech” as American analyses often do, nor do they
check for “separation of powers” which can often be rather hard to identify in
parliamentary systems. Their thin
theory of constitutional democracy provides a clear anchor for their idea of
“abuse.” In their framework, constitutional-democratic
norms used to undermine constitutional democracy are deployed “abusively.” Dixon and Landau illustrate abusive
constitutionalism with cases from all over the world. In the countries I know well, their accounts
are spot-on, which leads me to trust their accounts of the places I know less
well. I doubt that anyone working in
this increasingly crowded field knows as much about as many places as
they. With Landau’s deep knowledge
Latin America and Dixon’s
detailed knowledge of many Asian cases (and more), plus their prodigious
reading of everything in sight on all of the countries they track, they work
from deep understandings of many cases at once. The footnotes alone are worth close
attention as they are a rich source of inspiration for further reading. The alarm Dixon and Landau sound about
the declining fate of constitutional democracy is well argued and urgent. Constitutional democracies the world over
are falling victim to aspiring autocrats.
By alerting constitutional experts to the reality and pervasiveness of
these stealth attacks on constitutional democracy and providing a framework to
use in diagnosing what is happening, Dixon and Landau hope to generate both professional
concern and political action to stop the backsliding. Because there is no such thing as a
perfect book, however, let me quibble about the title of the book: Abusive Constitutional Borrowing. In my view, all three words are problematic
in ways that suggest how the authors might have improved their argument inside
the book. First
– borrowing. I know that borrowing
is the way that most of our field discusses the movement of ideas from one legal
space to another. But, as I
wrote nearly two decades ago: Borrowing,
in its most literal sense, means that the borrowed good in question belongs to
someone else, and one intends to give it back. Moreover, manners dictate—and
custom or law often require—that one ask and be granted permission to borrow
something in the first place. Borrowing implies that a borrowed good is in
one’s possession temporarily and that, as the property of another, one should
treat it with care and attempt to restore it in the condition in which it was
initially lent. One holds the thing borrowed by grant of a favor, not by right. In the cases that Dixon and Landau
elaborate in their book, autocrats take (without permission) ideas from other
places and use them in ways that break the ideas and bend them to the
autocrats’ will. Autocrats don’t treat
these ideas as if they had any obligation to keep them in good working
order. Precisely the opposite. Moreover, very often countries from which the
ideas are taken object to the “abusive” uses without having any way to stop the
abuse. If you had lent something to people
who then broke it, you could probably call them to account. Not so here. Borrowing is not what is going on. As many who contributed to Sujit
Choudhry’s 2007 edited volume argued, the “migration of constitutional
ideas” is a better metaphor for conceptualizing this process. We live in an era of migration, in which migrants
are often transformed in the process of moving – sometimes for the better and
sometimes for the worse. Migrants are
either well-treated or abused depending on where they go. But “migration” is a placeholder for a whole
set of movements whose overall assessment relies on many contingent facts. Moving
from metaphor back to the study of legal ideas, the migration of legal forms can include the movement of both
constitutional and “anti-constitutional ideas,” as
I argued first with regard to national security laws that multiplied after
9/11. Some ideas are pushed by sending
countries and international organizations onto reluctant receiving countries while
others are eagerly grabbed by receiving countries with or without the blessings
of their originators. As they travel,
legal concepts can move from being highly supportive of constitutional
democracy to undermining constitutional values at the next stop – and vice
versa. Just as migration describes
many different sorts of reasons for travel, types of transformations and varying
outcomes, so legal migration may be a
better framework for understanding why legal ideas move, how legal ideas are
changed as they travel and how they are transformed in the process. If
Dixon and Landau had thought explicitly in terms of migration, they would
realize that it is not so easy to distinguish abusive from non-abusive uses of
legal ideas. Almost all ideas change as
they move even without any malign intent from those who move the ideas from one
place to another. The purpose of a norm
in one place may not be that norm’s justifiable (or good) purpose in
another. But that doesn’t make the new
use abusive. For
example, when the Hungarian Constitutional Court claimed to be following the
German Federal Constitutional Court in the 1990s, the Hungarian judges no doubt
thought that German judges declared laws unconstitutional all the time, because
those were the cases they knew. In fact,
the German court was far less assertive in practice than the Hungarians
thought. The Hungarian Constitutional Court,
however, declared nearly one-third of all the laws they reviewed in those early
days unconstitutional, in an effort to make the constitution as real in daily
life as it was in Germany. But was that
abusive borrowing? The
Dixon and Landau emphasis on “abuse” implies that one should focus on the
relationship of the norm to a single underlying purpose. The Hungarian judges win on intent because
they were trying to strengthen Hungarian constitutional democracy. But many people argue even now that the hyperactive
Court stunted democracy, ultimately weakening it. A focus on effects in context rather than on
purposes of norms may be better at showing where constitutional democracy runs
off the rails and how it can be put back on track again. Second
– constitutional. In stable legal
systems, the idea of “constitutional” is relatively well-behaved. A set of norms is placed above the others, becomes
entrenched with more difficult amendment rules and is binding on all in their
purview. But in legal systems undergoing
autocratic transformation, the idea of “constitutional” is anything but
stable. The autocratizing governments in
both Hungary and Poland captured
their constitutional courts first, so that no one could tell them that what
they were doing was unconstitutional. They
then scrambled what “constitutional” meant so that topics regulated by the
constitution were overridden by ordinary laws or even by executive decrees
without a peep from the constitutional courts.
Constitutionalism has been destroyed from below by a parade of executive
orders and ill-conceived laws, all occurring beneath the radar of
“constitutional” law but hollowing out the constitutional order nonetheless. For
example, Viktor Orbán declared a “state
of migration emergency” in 2015 (which is still in effect six years later)
and then another “state
of medical emergency” in 2020 (again, still in effect). Even though the Hungarian constitution (including
the new one he rewrote in 2011) has a long section regulating states of
emergency, Orbán simply acted in both cases as if the constitution had nothing
to say on the subject. The
Constitutional Court said nothing either.
Eventually (in late 2020), Orbán changed the constitution
to retroactively legalize what he had done and to give himself more room for
issuing decrees without consulting the parliament. But if one had only focused at the
constitutional level, one would have missed the way that Orbán used other
layers of law to consolidate his power until the constitution was formally
changed five years into the use of extraordinary emergency powers. One might say the same about the way that the
PiS government in Poland has attacked the independence of the judiciary by passing
statutes in clear violation of the constitution allegedly in force and by
installing loyalists in a new disciplinary chamber of the Supreme Court, all
without touching the constitution and all without a peep from the
Constitutional Tribunal. To
analyze how democratic-constitutional governments become autocracies, then, it
is important to monitor the whole legal system and not just the most “constitutional
“parts. When I made this comment at a
panel on the book, Ros Dixon responded by saying that she and David Landau of
course were interested in more than constitutions, narrowly defined. And indeed the book has examples where
sub-constitutional laws are discussed.
But I do think it is better for analysis of the problem of budding
autocracies to be more explicit about the fact that inverting the hierarchy of
norms within a legal system may be one of the ways that autocrats upend the
constitutional order, particularly when they are consolidating power. Focusing our attention on the
constitutional level alone may miss how autocratic consolidation works. Finally – abusive. Dixon and Landau clearly define “abusive”
and stick strictly to that standard throughout the book.
But fixing abstract normative standards against which autocrats’ conduct
is assessed plays into the autocrats’ game. The
autocrats read what we write and adjust accordingly. Like US law school deans who
game the system to score high on the US News rankings, autocrats know that their
international reputations (and flows of foreign investment) rest on surface
compliance with external standards. If
we give autocrats the precise normative standards that we will judge them by
when those standards are merely means to the ends that we care about, it will provide
autocrats a checklist
for how to keep up appearances while still undermining constitutional
democracy. If, however, we insist on
measuring effects of autocratic rule –
like whether people are free to be authors of their own lives or whether they
can change governments when they want to – then we measure what we ultimately care
about in a manner that is less gameable by autocrats. As
I was writing this review, an example popped up in Hungary. Six otherwise incompatible political parties have
pledged to work together to defeat Orbán in the Hungarian parliamentary
election in 2022. They are holding primaries in fall 2021 to determine which one
candidate from the opposition will stand alone against Orbán and his loyalists
in each district so that the anti-Orbán vote is not divided. Four hours into the first day of primary voting,
the servers
tallying the votes were hit by a distributed denial-of-service (DDOS) attack,
requiring postponement of the election.
Opposition-affiliated computer experts quickly traced the hack to Chinese
sources. The Hungarian government denied
any involvement. Did
Hungary fail the free, fair and contested election criterion that Dixon and
Landau develop as crucial to their analysis?
Not on a formal review of the
situation. Six parties were competing
freely and the government made no overt attempt to interfere. An external hack halted the proceedings, not
the Hungarian government. The problem
wasn’t unique to Hungary. Potential DDOS
attacks were flagged in the US in
the last election to warn the public.
The effect of such a warning was to make
DDOS attacks could look like something that could happen to any
democratic government at election time. With
the DDOS attack in Hungary, however, the opposition believes it knows precisely
what is going on. In recent years, China
and the Orbán government have been cozying up to each other and China
will get what it wants in Hungary only if Orbán wins next year. You can see why China might want to do
Orbán “a
favor, though.” Before this most recent attack on the
integrity of elections, Orbán had done everything he could in the last two
election cycles to adjust the law to rig the elections
in his favor. It seems that Orbán will
stop at nothing to stay in power even if he endures the charade of
elections. A DDOS attack on the first
primary day, especially when China seems to be the source of the attack, looks like
something from the Orbán playbook. But
what is a normative democracy rater to do?
Should the democracy rater just believe that bad things sometimes happen
to good democracies? Or should the
democracy rater understand, as Oliver Wendell Holmes famously wrote in The Common Law,
that “even a dog distinguishes between being stumbled over and being kicked”? The
Hungarian election hack example illustrates that, in the new autocracies,
actors other than the government in question – private actors, foreign actors –
are often the primary agents who speed the path to autocracy. If oligarchs friendly to the prime minister
buy up the independent media and turn them into propaganda outlets for the
government or if the private sector refuses to hire people affiliated with
opposition parties or if foreign governments friendly to the governing party hack
into opposition primaries, is the autocratizing government to blame? Is this constitutional abuse? If
we focus not on abstract criteria but on what the system feels like to those who
are in it, we might better understand when constitutional democracy is being
undermined. An election is clearly not
fair when it is hacked by a foreign government working under the table with the
powers that be and a media environment is not conducive to democratic debate if
the main private news outlets are all signing from the government’s song
sheet. But a focus on constitutional
norms and their purposes may not flag these cases as problems. We
need to look at the whole context rather than creating and deploying checklists
of norms that a government can game by outsourcing its bad behavior to others. In
fairness to Dixon and Landau, many of the cases they elaborate in the book are
quite textured. Among other things, they
are not fooled by the normative outsourcing that autocratic governments
do. But the idea of constitutional abuse
is less flexible than the idea of studying deleterious effects for the
practical realization of constitutional democracy, and I worry that their
normative checklist provides another gaming opportunity for autocrats. All
that said, Dixon and Landau have provided a very important and useful focal
point for the next round of debate about democratic decline. Should
we proceed by developing norms and identifying abuses of the norms? Or should we proceed by identifying practical
harms and finding remedies? If I take a different view of the matter than
Dixon and Landau, it is not because I haven’t learned an immense amount from
them. We differ over how best to study (and
to turn around) the alarming things happening in altogether too many
constitutional democracies today. But Dixon and Landau have done us all a great
service by documenting the problems and offering a creative framework for
understanding what is going on. Abusive Constitutional Borrowing should
be on everyone’s reading list. And let the debate begin! Kim Lane Scheppele is the Rockefeller Professor of Sociology and Public Affairs at Princeton University. You can reach her by e-mail at kimlane@princeton.edu.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |