E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Diego A. Zambrano Cases Without Controversies is the book
Justice Story would have written had he seen the development of Article III jurisprudence
in the 20th century. Since he didn’t, Jim Pfander has taken on the task.
And thank heavens that he has done that. The book begins with a familiar story for
students of federal courts: Article III of the Constitution extends the
judicial power to a series of “cases” and “controversies.” Despite the framers’
use of two different words, modern lawyers have been told repeatedly that these
words cover the same thing—a dispute among parties “having adverse legal
interests.” Justice Scalia emphasized the adverse-party requirement as an
“essential element of an Article III case or controversy” (p. 2). Hart &
Wechsler makes the same claim (p. 223). Over and over lower courts and
scholars have insisted that ex parte claims are not amenable to a judicial
resolution except in extremely narrow circumstances. Yet, as Pfander explains, this adverse-party
requirement co-exists awkwardly with serious departures from the adverse ideal:
bankruptcy administration, foreign intelligence warrants, habeas proceedings,
and other non-contested claims. Seeing the contradiction between these ex parte
proceedings and the adverse party ideal, generations of scholars have evaded
the problem, calling it an “anomaly” or “aberration,” perhaps just a “vestige”
of the past. Pfander rejects this evasion and, instead, crafts
a brilliant theory that explains non-adversarial proceedings as part and parcel
of Article III. The book’s central argument is that Article III does, in fact,
cover “uncontested matters” as “cases arising under federal law.” This means
that a single party can assert “claims of right in an ex parte proceeding that
[does] not entail any demand for redress from an opposing party” (p. 6-7). This
is possible “so long as Congress acts pursuant to its enumerated powers in
creating a right and assigns the federal courts final authority over
applications by parties to claim such a right” (p. 164). This seemingly
innocuous claim addresses some of the trickiest questions in the field of
federal courts: Is there an inflexible injury-in-fact requirement? Are bankruptcy
proceedings, prisoner petitions, settlement class actions, consent decrees, and
warrants constitutional exercises of the judicial power? Does the term “cases” in
Article III cover criminal and civil proceedings? Can courts presented with uncontested
cases engage in inquisitorial adjudication? What was the deal with Hayburn’s
Case? And is the domestic relations exception statutory or constitutional? The
book says: No; yes; don’t worry about it; yes; judicial dignity not
adverseness; both. To prove its claims, the book draws on a range of
history, early practice, and textual sources. Pfander gallops from Rome to France,
Germany, England, and the Early Republic. We learn that Roman courts allowed
parties to transfer property via a feigned case that would result in a consent
judgment. French, Italian, and German courts still allow several forms of what
they call “non-contentious jurisdiction.” And, as it turns out, non-contentious
claims were common in the Early Republic, too. Pfander wonderfully explains how early federal
courts hosted non-adverse claims as a matter of course, especially pension
claims, prize and salvage admiralty cases, warrant applications, and
naturalization proceedings. These cases were almost never contested in the
early 1800s. Yet judges did not call into question the judicial power over ex
parte claims. Justices Marshall and Story, unlike Scalia and 21st
century successors, recognized that non-adversarial claims could be amenable to
judicial resolution under certain circumstances. Indeed, as the book argues, these
cases were fundamentally judicial because they called on federal courts to
recognize a claim of right created by federal law. Despite this historic understanding, however,
Pfander describes how early 20th century progressives—including Justices
Brandeis and Frankfurter—embraced the modern adverse-party requirement in order
to limit the power of federal courts. Fearful of an activist and conservative
judiciary emboldened by Lochner and Ex parte Young, progressive reformers
turned to any tools they could use to block aggressive federal courts.
(Although, in Tutun v. United States, Brandeis upheld ex parte
naturalization proceedings). Their reinvention of standing requirements, in
turn, has left a long legacy. Instead of relying on Marshall and Story, modern
day lawyers listen to Brandeis and Frankfurter. The book tells us, then, that
we have lost our history. With this background in place, Pfander displays
his masterful ability to bring doctrinal history to every nook and cranny of
Article III. For example, in Spokeo v. Robins (2015), Justice Thomas
argued in concurrence that standing was limited in public actions to claims
analogous to the “common law forms of action.” To an originalist, this might
seem like a sensible claim. But Pfander points out that such an approach
completely ignores the “adjudicatory practices of the civil-law-inflected
courts of equity and admiralty” (p. 178). In those courts, of course, standing
was much broader and more flexible. One of the book’s best qualities is that it uses
history to comprehensively tie several strands of jurisprudence together into a
cohesive and parsimonious whole. With apologies to many, federal courts
scholars sometimes create theories that conveniently leave out “outlier” and
unexplained doctrinal “anomalies.” Cases Without Controversies refuses
to do this, resolving every open question in its sight. Again, the main thesis
bears repeating: Pfander argues that the word “cases” covered claims under
federal (and not state) law either contentious or not, while the word
“controversies” applied to diversity jurisdiction and similar adversarial
proceedings. The book then uses this distinction to set a clear way forward: courts
should “focus on whether the plaintiff has a litigable interest, rather than an
injury in fact” (p. 175). These “litigable interests” exist when a party seeks
redress both for injuries in fact but also in uncontested proceedings for a
recognized claim of right. With that in mind, courts can resolve almost any
puzzle related to Article III standing without leaving outlier categories. Still, setting aside the impressive historical
and doctrinal work on Article III, Cases Without Controversies is not
just a book about standing. It is a fabulous and important book about
constitutional history and the politically contingent evolution of the federal
courts. It is also an incisive and convincing book on the role of original
meaning, tradition, and judicial practices. All of these are crucial topics for
our time. And especially so when the Supreme Court continues to issue
decisions—see Transunion LLC v. Ramirez—that puzzle federal courts
scholars. Before closing, let me offer some minor critiques
of the book, mostly focused on the need for more clarity. To begin, while Pfander’s
appeal to precedent, fit, and pedigree is appropriate, I think he misses the
opportunity to focus on the consequences of his proposal. In his effort
to bring a parsimonious synthesis of Article III text, history, and practice,
the book does not fully address whether we would live in a better world with an
open recognition of uncontested adjudications in our federal courts. Although
Pfander clarifies that he is not arguing “that the legislature should assign
more uncontested work to the federal judiciary” (p. 191) surely placing
uncontested adjudication on firmer constitutional grounds might spur more
Congressional activity. What problems might an open recognition of uncontested
adjudication create? And how will judges adapt? Pfander mostly punts on these
questions. He speculates that even if judges are not used to inquisitorial
procedures they may improve in the long run (p. 191-215). But is there
something normatively desirable about having Article III judgesdecide
both contested and uncontested proceedings? Consider, for instance, that a proliferation
of uncontested proceedings could increase our reliance on the judiciary, and
consequently, the importance of inquisitorial skills. Would we have to start
looking for different kinds of judges? Pfander only partly answers this
question. One place to look for preliminary answers might be
state courts, where standing is more flexible and judges are thus accustomed to
handling administrative matters and even advisory opinions. The book’s
reluctance to fully address consequences also comes through in the concept of a
“litigable interest.” Pfander tries to specify when it would apply but still
leaves a lot open to a future when “the Court could revisit” its current
doctrines. One feels that Pfander wants to make it possible
for Congress to create uncontested adjudication but is not sure whether
this will be a good thing on net. But as opponents of originalism embrace
alternatives that are synthetic and ecumenical, it would have been a great
opportunity for Pfander to show how consequentialism can work alongside
text, history, and practice. Still, I can’t blame Pfander too much for this
fault—federal courts and civil procedure scholars all operate under a general
assumption that making our adjudicatory systems more legible and accessible
will, eventually, enhance welfare. Relatedly, another need for clarity comes near
the end of the book, where Pfander alights on the concept of epistemic
humility. He argues that even if the Court rejects the notion of a “litigable
interest,” it can still accommodate our long tradition of uncontested adjudication.
Doing so would “acknowledge[] that legal ideas must fit well within the
surrounding judicial ecosystem” (p. 229) and that “pedigree, precedent, and
fit” are fundamental to our constitutional tradition. Pfander warns that
“stout-hearted originalists” (p. 230) and the “epistemically confident” (p.
231) will find it challenging to update based on new historical evidence. But,
here again, I wished Pfander had further explained what a good constitutional
Bayesian should do in the face of new historical evidence. How much weight
should we assign a re-emphasis on admiralty proceedings in the early 19th
century? Are there threshold levels of confidence that should make judges
decide one way or the other? I think Pfander missed an opportunity here to
provide a fuller description of his constitutional views. Finally, as a civil procedure professor, I am
happy to call for more attention to the effects of preclusion and compulsory
joinder. Some of the danger in uncontested adjudication is its preclusive
effect on third parties. On the one hand, a strong preclusive effect is
probably unconstitutional as a denial of a non-party’s due process rights. On
the other, a weak preclusive effect means that absent non-parties can
constantly revisit uncontested adjudication. So perhaps there is little room
for uncontested adjudication to operate even if we accept the book’s proposals.
Pfander at first responds that for most single party claims to a federal right
or benefit “third party rights are unlikely to be implicated” (p. 200). That
sounds right to me. Pfander then also warns that to the extent non-contentious
jurisdiction “does pose a potential threat to the rights of third parties . . .
federal courts must be especially vigilant to ward off the entry of judgments
that unfairly burden” (p. 200) absent parties. But in the small subset of cases
that do pose a threat to third parties, I think Pfander is missing even better
solutions. We could rely on more aggressive sua sponte assertions of
Rule 19 necessary joinder, forcing uncontested applicants to join absent
parties. Or, alternatively, rely again on Congress. Recall that Pfander’s main
proposal is thatCongress should have the leeway to create rights and
assign federal courts the power to hear uncontested applications to such a
right. Well, whenever Congress does create such a right, it could also do what
it did in the 1991 Civil Rights Act: bar collateral attacks on uncontested
adjudications where third parties had notice and an opportunity to object. Authors who produce iconic legal ideas are
sometimes turned into adjectives. Pick up a Ronald Dworkin book and you’ll
immediately feel the arguments as Dworkinian. Read a law and economics article
and you might see a Coasean approach. Not for nothing this blog is named
“Balkinization.” Pfander may have joined the list with this book. He has shown
us, yet again, that he is a Jedi master of doctrinal history and federal
courts. Opinions about Article III must now wrestle with powerful Pfanderian
arguments about text, history, and practices surrounding the phrase “cases” and
“controversies.” (If you think this new adjective doesn’t easily roll off the
tongue, well, I don’t make the rules). Diego A. Zambrano is an Associate Professor of Law
at Stanford Law School. You can reach him by e-mail at Dzambran@law.stanford.edu.