Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts On being an American patriot “Plain Dumb Luck” and the War Power: A Story of Nuclear Roulette and Its Lessons Balkinization Symposium on Martin J. Sherwin, Gambling with Armageddon: Nuclear Roulette from Hiroshima to the Cuban Missile Crisis What is a Tax Cut, Anyway? Strange and Dangerous Attacks on the Recovery Plan’s Condition on State Tax Cuts Following Up on a Prior Post Recommended Listening: Amarica's Constitution Podcast Robert Jackson and the Non-Delegation Doctrine Joe Manchin, Hollywood Western hero Living Originalism at the University of Saskatchewan Meet Me in the Middle Podcasts on The Cycles of Constitutional Time and Regulating Social Media
|
Wednesday, March 31, 2021
On being an American patriot
Sandy Levinson
Steven B. Smith, who teaches political theory at Yale, has just published, with the Yale Press, an interesting book Reclaiming Patriotism in an Age of Extremes. A quite slender book, it does not purport to offer a comprehensive theory of patriotism across vast times or space; instead, it is basically a heartfelt missive to his fellow Americans (and, perhaps, fellow academics) about what can be said about American patriotism at this particular juncture in our history. He is clearly concerned that a mixture of multiculturalism and post-modernism--the former probably more of a genuine reality than the latter in the present intellectual moment--has eroded any genuine notion of patriotism. Prominent intellectuals like George Kateb or Martha Nussbaum esssentially deride the notion, the former in the name of Thoreauvian individualism, the latter evoking instead a commitment to a cosmopolitan identity as basically a citizen of the world. And the most prominent public purveyors of patriotism are often "nationalists" committed to dubious notions of Making America Great Again or America First (or simply shouting out "USA, USA" at the Olympics; it is clear that Smith, altogether properly does not want to be associated with the latter, even as he is critical of the former. I am interested in the book not only because I know Smith personally and respect him as a serious thinker (who, among other things, taught my daughter many years ago at Yale). It's also the case that I have long been interested in the phenomenon of patriotism as an academic; perhaps even more to the point, perhaps as a child of the 1960s, I often wonder exactly what that means in my own life. Many years ago, when Steve Macedo reviewed my first book, Constitutional Faith, in the New Republic, he referred to me as a "patriot" even though (or perhaps because?) I was quite critical of the Madisonian tradition of constitutional "veneration." I preferred to cast my lot with Thomas Jefferson and Woodrow Wilson as vigorous critics of any such veneration. What Macedo presumably recognized, though, was that I was indeed concerned with the future (as well as the past) of our country and believed that it was necessary to adopt a more Jeffersonian spirit of critique in order to serve our great national ends enunciated, for example, in the Preamble to the Constitution itself, or in the Declaration of Independence. Moreover, I concluded that book by writing of my visit to the Bicentennial Exhibit in Philadelphia in 1987, where everyone was given the opportunity to "sign the Constitution" and, presumably, reaffirm one's identity as a loyal American defined by accepting its particular importance in structuring not only American government, but also American identity. Longtime readers of Balkinization are well aware that I no long exhibit the "constitutional faith" that was perhaps present in 1987. My 2006 book, Our Undemocratic Constitution began with a chapter explaining why I did not sign the Constitution when given an opportunity to do during a visit at the opening on July 3, 2003 of the National Constitution Center (for which I had been a member of an academic advisory board). That visit concluded by entering "Signers' Hall," featuring life-size statues of all of the delegates to the 1787 Convention and an invitation to reaffirm one's membership in the American community by joining them, as it were, as signatories. A 2011 second edition of Constitutional Faith explained at greater length why I had lost any such faith. The answer is that I came, between 1987 and 2003, to view the "hard-wired" institutions and procedures set up in 1787, and barely amended thereafter, as having become impediments to realizing the aspirations nobly set out in the Preamble. Since, then, I have come to view them increasingly as a clear-and-present danger to our survival as a constitutional democracy. I increasingly have little patience for those who offer any kind of unreflective praise of the Constitution. So, frankly, I don't know exactly how I should read Smith's encomia to the Constitution. He writes, for example, "Our legal code based on the Constitution has been elaborated over the course of our national existence by our most prominent lawyers, judges, and legislators. Americans can justly take pride that their legal system has survived intact for well over two centuries and today may yet stand as a bulwark against a resurgent populism" (p. 192). Earlier he writes that "[m]any Americans, if asked will say they take pride in their Constitution and their constitutional tradition. This pride in a text or a textual tradition forms the core of American patriotism." To be sure, we can argue about the meaning of the Constitution, "and the argument--our self-questioning character--is a core aspect of American patriotism. This is what makes ours a uniquely enlightened patriotism. This is the true meaning of American exceptionalism" (p. 149). I confess that I don't see myself within this universe of American patriots and would encourage others to leave such a universe. I most certainly do not believe that our "legal system has survived intact for well over two centuries." Like Bruce Ackerman, Smith's colleague at Yale, I think this is a dangerous misreading of the actualities of our constitutional history, which has the ideological function--and often the purpose--of blinding Americans to the all-important history of significant change, some of its produced by "populist" movements like Abolitionism and the Civil Rights Movement. As I argued in Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance, I am increasingly less interested in the kinds of debates about constitutional "meaning" that obsess the legal academy and more interested--or even obsessed--by the (un)wisdom of a variety of aspects of the Constitution that present no real challenges of "interpretation," including, for starters, the allocation of equal voting power in the Senate or the sheer difficulty of amending the Constitution through Article V (and I assure you they are only starters). So do I count as a "patriot" in Smith's universe? Perhaps yes, inasmuch as both of us identify in profound ways as "Americans" and not really as a deracinated "citizen of the world," with equal "concern and respect" for anyone and everyone living anywhere and everywhere. But no, if one is to take truly seriously commitment to the United States Constitution, either in its 1787 form or even as amended--though not enough--in 2021, as a necessary condition of patriotism. So one problem I have with Smith's argument--much praised by David Brooks in a column in the New York Times--is what I find an insufficiently elaborated notion of what exactly he means by the Constitution and, therefore, the importance of being committed to it. But I have yet another important reservation: The central exemplar of enlightened American patriotism, for Smith, is Abraham Lincoln. "No one," we are told, "has captured the meaning of enlightened patriotism more beautifully than Abraham Lincoln, who gave American constitutional democracy its highest and most articulate expression. In his speeches and writings, Lincoln put forward a vision of American identity that brings out the principal basis of patriotism" (p. 150). Here, too, I can be said to share Smith's focus, perhaps even obsession, with Lincoln. This year I will teach "reading courses" at the University of Texas and Harvard Law Schools on Lincoln and Frederick Douglass. (Last year, I taught such a course at Harvard on Lincoln alone.) I certainly agree that no one professing to understand America can avoid grappling with our 16th President. But, frankly, I discern a far more complex, more troublesome Abraham Lincoln than Smith appears to find, at least in this volume. Mario Cuomo famously said that politicians campaign in poetry but govern in prose. It is not a coincidence that most evocations of Lincoln's greatness involve what might be described as his "poetic" efforts, including, for example, the Gettysburg Address and, even more certainly, the Second Inaugural Address. It is specialists who tend to concentrate instead of his actual decisions as a practicing politician, whether candidate for higher office or as President of the United States. So consider in this context Frederick Douglass's great speech delivered on "the Occasion of the Unveiling of the Freedmen's Monument in Memory of Abraham Lincoln" on April 14, 1876, the eleventh anniversary of his assassination. As one would expect, Douglass offered praise of Lincoln. But then we read the following: It must be admitted, truth compels me to admit, even here in the presence of the monument we have erected to his memory, Abraham Lincoln was not, in the fullest sense of the world, either our man or our model. In his interests, in his associations, in his habits of thought, and in his prejudices, he was a white man. He was preeminently the white man's president, entirely devoted to the welfare of white men. Another Yale colleague of Smith's, David Blight, begins his great biography of Douglass by quoting and discussing this speech. Was Douglass correct? And if he was, does this cast light, for example, on the increasingly bitter controversy over the "1619 Project" and the attempts to answer it not only by Donald Trump's "1776 Report," which similarly valorizes Lincoln (and even selected aspects of Douglass), but also by far more temperate historians like Princeton's Sean Wilentz? Is it true that any American patriot must recognize the extent to which white supremacy infects almost every aspect of our national history, including the thoughts and actions of even our greatest figures within what is accurately called "American civil religion"? To be sure, not every "white supremacist" supports the Ku Klux Klan, and Douglass recognizes Lincoln's sincere hatred of slavery and his willingness to refer to Douglass in public as his "friend." That is surely important. Lincoln could have been far worse, perhaps someone like the man he chose to be Vice President, Andrew Johnson in the belief that this Unionist Democrat would aid his re-election chances in 1864. But it was also Abraham Lincoln who convened a group of Washington leaders of the Black community and lectured them on the basic unlikelihood, if not impossibility, that Blacks and white could really live together amicably in one community; this was the basis of Lincoln's warm support of colonization as the "answer" to this quintessential American problem, At that meeting he particularly encouraged them to move to Panama, though, no doubt, he would also have been happy with emigration to Mexico, Haiti, Canada, or Liberia. One need not support the removal of the monument that Douglass so eloquently dedicated in order to recognize that Abraham Lincoln, like the author of the Declaration of Independence Thomas Jefferson, or each and every one of our national heroes, is radically imperfect, and not only because "to err is human." Theirs was what might be called a "structured imperfection," inasmuch as success within American politics has always required presentation, whether overt or tacit, of being "the white man's president." Today, perhaps except for Donald Trump, few would describe them as devoted "entirely" to the interests of whites. But let us not kid ourselves. Barack Obama, for whatever complex set of reasons, certainly did very little to teach his fellow Americans about the actual history of white supremacy and the concomitant duty to adopt political programs to try to alleviate it. Quite likely, he would have been perceived as "an angry Black man" and denied the office to which he aspired. And, of course, as with Lincoln, one can easily point to many good things he did as President. But to stop there, to take refuge that no one is perfect (including the author of this post or anyone reading it) is ultimately to dodge the kinds of conversations we must have--and actions following from those conversations--if we are, I am tempted to say, "genuine patriots" committed to the vision of an egalitarian America that Smith, to his credit, embraces. “Plain Dumb Luck” and the War Power: A Story of Nuclear Roulette and Its Lessons
Guest Blogger
For the Symposium on Martin J. Sherwin, Gambling with Armageddon: Nuclear Roulette from Hiroshima to the Cuban Missile Crisis (Knopf, 2020). Martin Sherwin’s Gambling
with Armageddon is a gripping, nail-biting account of the Cuban Missile
Crisis, and so much more. It would be
hard to overstate how quickly the book grabs your attention and provides a
frightening account of how close the world came to nuclear obliteration in
October 1962. But, if it is even
possible, the book’s larger account of what the author calls “nuclear roulette”
is even more frightening. Those of us who teach and write about the separation
of powers in the context of war spill barrels of ink debating such questions as
whether Congress has given away too much of its authority to the executive;
whether the courts have correctly stayed their hands with respect to a host of
questions surrounding war prosecution, including enforcement of the War Powers
Resolution; and more recently, whether Congress needs to bring up to date its
Authorization for Use of Military Force to address new enemies and new fronts
in the war on terrorism. Sherwin’s book
suggests that in the nuclear context, such debates may be, if my colleagues in
this symposium will forgive me, largely “academic.” Indeed, as Sherwin’s work lays bare, we have
built a nuclear infrastructure that can bring us to the brink of destruction
based on a handful of miscues and/or failures of diplomacy, and from which we
may only be saved by sheer luck and the good judgment of a single individual who
happens to be in the right place at the right time. That, in any event, is one of the key points that
Sherwin makes in the book. In his words,
the Cuban Missile Crisis “was the ultimate reality check: Nuclear threats could
lead to conflicts regardless of intentions.”
Quoting political scientist Scott Sagan, Sherwin goes further to suggest
that the crisis revealed the all-too real potential for “‘accidental nuclear
war.’” To make his point, Sherwin sets
forth in detail here the miscues and misunderstandings that caused the standoff
between Kennedy and Krushchev to escalate to the brink. Continuing, he walks the reader through how,
in the end, despite the desire of those leaders to “untie the knot” and reach a
diplomatic resolution (to borrow from Krushchev’s language in a letter to
Kennedy), it all came down to the sound judgment of a young Soviet naval
officer who happened by chance to be on a particular Soviet B-59 submarine approaching
the waters off of Cuba. In recounting
the events of the standoff, Sherwin tells us that he began a skeptic but emerged
in agreement with Dean Acheson’s earlier account of the crisis, concluding that
the world was saved only because of “plain dumb luck.” Now in this contribution, I do not want to spoil a
good story, and Sherwin is a master storyteller. Thus, I will refer the reader to his book so
that he can walk you through how the tale unfolds. What I can say is that it is hard to emerge
from reading Sherwin’s account of the crisis and his explication more generally
of the proliferation of nuclear weapons of war without coming to the belief
that the notion of stockpiling the same as a “deterrent” to war (so-called
“nuclear diplomacy”) is madness. This is, to be sure, the main contribution of the
book, and it is a deeply important one at that. All the same, I wish here to draw out another one of
the book’s contributions. Gambling with Armageddon underscores
that as much as we may wish to theorize as to how the separation of powers were
designed to work and/or how they should work, when it comes to nuclear
standoffs, none of that matters nearly as much as the character and judgment of
the relevant actors in the equation.
This lesson, moreover, applies not only to high-level political actors,
but extends all the way down the line to the naval officer far from home tasked
with making a split second decision about whether to unleash a weapon with the potential
for catastrophic consequences. In this respect, Sherwin adds to a body of
literature in the war context that has made this point before. But given the context in which he is writing
and the narrative he weaves, the point extends much further than prior
accounts. To flesh out what I mean,
consider a counterfactual. (As Sherwin
notes here, he loves counterfactuals. So
do I.) What if it had not been President
Lincoln at the helm in 1861 charged with maintaining the Union? And what if it had not been Lincoln at the
helm in 1863? Would another president
have issued the Emancipation Proclamation and begun then and there to address
the stain on our nation’s constitutional and moral fabric that slavery wrought? As the Supreme Court wrote in the immediate
wake of the war in Ex Parte Milligan,
“[w]icked men, ambitious of power, with hatred of liberty and contempt of law,
may fill the place once occupied by Washington and Lincoln; and if this right
is conceded, and the calamities of war again befall us, the dangers to human
liberty are frightful to contemplate. . . .” Lincoln had been dead but a year and the
Court was already ready to put him on Mount Rushmore, while also recognizing
his exceptionalness. In my own work, I have drawn comparisons between
President Roosevelt and Prime Minister Churchill during World War II. For his part, Roosevelt set in motion the
events that led to the mass incarceration during the war of some 120,000
Japanese Americans (over 70,000 of whom were United States citizens), disregarding
what he had been told by his closest advisers–namely, that doing so would
violate the Constitution. Roosevelt only
reluctantly agreed to closing the camps once he won reelection in 1944 and was
tipped off that the government would lose an important Supreme Court case that challenged
the legality of the camps, Ex parte Endo. By contrast, Churchill is most responsible
for winding down Britain’s domestic internment program under what was known as Regulation
18B. Invoking British constitutional
tradition, Churchill declared that “such
powers . . . are contrary to the whole spirit of British public life and
British history.” To be sure, there were
important differences that may account for the two executives’ contrasting
approaches, not the least of which were the ethnic make-up of those detained in
each program and the fact that Churchill did not have to stand in a general
election during the war. But the point
remains that Churchill took a leadership role in shutting down a wildly popular
program, while Roosevelt had to be dragged kicking and screaming to do so (and
despite being told repeatedly that the Japanese American incarceration would
and did violate the Suspension Clause). Here is what Sherwin’s account adds. It is not just the leaders in the oval office
whose character, judgment, and values matter when it comes to waging war. In an age when the push of a button can
unleash massive destruction, it is also the character, judgment, and values of
the individual on the front lines who staffs that button that matters. (Indeed, the story Sherwin tells is one that
history has witnessed happen more than once,
and underscores the dangers of taking humans out of the equation, as countless
viewers, including President Reagan, came to appreciate from watching the movie
War Games.) To borrow from Milligan, we may not always have a Washington or Lincoln, or in the
case of the Cuban Missile Crisis, a Captain Vasily Alexandrovich Arkhipov, to
save us. And, if this point “is
conceded, and the calamities of war again befall us, the dangers to human
liberty [and life as we know it] are frightful to contemplate. . . .” Amanda L. Tyler is the Shannon Cecil Turner
Professor of Law at the University of California, Berkeley School of Law. You can reach her by e-mail at atyler at berkeley.edu Balkinization Symposium on Martin J. Sherwin, Gambling with Armageddon: Nuclear Roulette from Hiroshima to the Cuban Missile Crisis
JB
Thursday, March 25, 2021
What is a Tax Cut, Anyway?
Joseph Fishkin
I’m not going to write a whole blog post today about the meritless (from the point of view of precedent and doctrine) yet also highly dangerous (because conservative constitutional politics may turn out to be way more important than current precedent and doctrine) states-rights legal challenge to the American Recovery Plan Act. Lawyers apply the ordinary tools of legal analysis to a lawsuits of this sort at their peril. Read David Super’s great post below for more about the precedents. If the current conservative supermajority in the Supreme Court decides to create a new principle that “if Congress offers states lots of money, it can’t attach too many strings,” then they’ll do that, using nicer words. I want to write instead about an issue deep in the weeds of the controversy, one that I’ve always found interesting and that this suit puts a fine point on. I am not a tax lawyer, just an interested outsider to this field, and I welcome input from those who know more. Sunday, March 21, 2021
Strange and Dangerous Attacks on the Recovery Plan’s Condition on State Tax Cuts
David Super
Quite remarkably,
some Republican state officials are attacking
the constitutionality of the new section 602(c)(2)(A) of the Social Security
Act added by section 9901 of the recently-enacted American Recovery Plan Act (ARPA). This provision reduces federal fiscal aid to
states by the amount of any state tax cuts.
Congress included the ARPA provision at a time when several
Republican
governors
were
advocating dramatic tax cuts despite the economic weakness caused by the
pandemic. The assertion that this condition
is unconstitutional is remarkable in at least two ways. First, it is utterly without foundation on
even the most aggressive reading of the Constitution and the Supreme Court’s
precedents. And second, this theory’s
implications, far from being an advance of states’ rights, are utterly
devastating for the autonomy and independence of states. Those making this claim therefore are
privileging the sugar-high of tax cuts over principles of federalism that the
Republican Party once insisted were sacrosanct.
When combined with widespread Republican acceptance of the Trump Administration’s
flippant
federalism, this suggests that we are entering an era when neither of the
country’s two major political parties have any deep commitment to protecting
the prerogatives of the states. That shift
could transform the structure of this country’s governance. On the merits, the challenge to the
ARPA condition is absurd. Nothing in the
Constitution limits the federal government’s ability to transfer funds to the
states to promote the general welfare, and nothing prohibits it from imposing
conditions on receipt of those funds. The
federal government has been making conditional grants to the states for a very
long time. For a textualist or an
originalist, that ought to be enough to dismiss this claim out of hand. Caselaw provides no support for
this claim, either. The Supreme Court
has recognized
limits to Congress’s
authority to command state or local governments to carry out a federal agenda
against their will. But ARPA does not command
anything: it merely attaches a condition
to money being offered to states. And the ARPA tax-cut provision falls
well within the range of what the Court has accepted as funding conditions. The post-New Deal Supreme Court brushed aside
challenges to Congress’s ability to make conditional grants to states, ushering
in the modern era of cooperative federalism.
It also upheld
congressional efforts to influence state tax policy, approving sections of the
Social Security Act that effectively increase a federal tax on employers whose
states do not assess them a state tax to support unemployment compensation benefits. Numerous social welfare,
transportation, environmental, law enforcement, and other programs have
operated on the basis of conditional federal grants. Quoting Chief Justice Burger, Chief Justice
Rehnquist noted
that incident to its spending power, “Congress may attach conditions on the
receipt of federal funds, and has repeatedly employed the power ‘to further
broad policy objectives by conditioning receipt of federal moneys upon
compliance by the recipient with federal statutory and administrative
directives.’" He also reiterated a
pre-New Deal holding that “the power of Congress to authorize expenditure of
public moneys for public purposes is not limited by the direct grants of
legislative power found in the Constitution. Thus, objectives not thought to be
within Article I's enumerated legislative fields, may nevertheless be attained
through the use of the spending power and the conditional grant of federal
funds.” More recently, the Court has
recognized three limitations on Congress’s ability to condition funding to
states. None of these limitations,
however, comes anywhere near causing a problem for the ARPA provision. First, the Court has held that
conditions must be open and obvious so that states know to what they are committing
when they accept the funds. The tax-cut
condition appears explicitly on the face of ARPA: the fact that it has become controversial
days after enactment, long before any state submitted the certifications required
to receive Fiscal Recovery Funds, demonstrates how open and obvious the
condition is. Second, the Court has held that conditions
on funding must be reasonably related to the purpose of the funding. Congress probably could not condition Medicaid
funding on a state changing its state bird.
In an opinion by Chief Justice Rehnquist, however, the Court upheld conditioning
federal highway funding on adoption of a 21-year-old drinking age. The Court found that Congress was reasonable
in its belief that allowing younger persons to purchase and possess alcohol
could increase drunk-driving deaths. The
Court brushed aside the state’s argument that controlling the sale of liquor
was a core state power secured by the Twenty-First
Amendment, noting that Congress had not denied the state that power but
merely reduced its support for highways that it believed would be more
dangerous as a result of a particular choice.
The ARPA condition has an even closer substantive relationship to the
funding provided than does the drinking age that the Court upheld: it constrains how the very funds being
provided are spent. Finally, in the Court’s first case
on the Affordable Care Act (NFIB v. Sebelius),
it held that Congress could not suddenly increase the conditions on federal Medicaid
funding by requiring states to expand eligibility to large populations that the
program previously had not served. The problem,
Chief Justice Roberts wrote, was that states had become so dependent on
Medicaid funding that opting out was no longer a plausible option for
them. With states in this position, Congress
effectively put “a gun to the head” of any state wanting to deny Medicaid to non-elderly
adults without a disability or pregnancy.
With no other federal program providing remotely as much money to states,
the “gun-to-the-head” standard may not apply outside
of the Medicaid context. But it
certainly does not apply to money that states have no legal right to receive
and in fact have not been receiving. This is where the Republican officials’
argument becomes so remarkable. To
invoke the NFIB principle, they essentially must argue that denying
states fiscal relief in this crisis is pointing a gun to the states’ heads. The Court found the ACA’s Medicaid expansion condition
coercive only because it found that states had become so dependent on Medicaid
funding that they had developed an implicit right to have it continue. ARPA’s fiscal relief is not continuing
funding at all: states received some
fiscal relief under last year’s CARES Act, but congressional Republicans and
President Trump steadfastly opposed providing any more, reportedly sinking potential
bipartisan agreements on further coronavirus relief measures because they so
adamantly opposed Democrats’ insistence on more fiscal relief. Had the Democrats not won the two Georgia senatorial
run-offs, states almost certainly would not be receiving any further fiscal
relief, conditional or otherwise. To say
that states were so dependent on this money that it cannot legitimately be
conditioned is quite detached from its recent history. These attacks also posit a model of
federal-state relations radically at odds with the states’ rights position
Republicans have taken for the past half-century. The model Republican attorneys general seem
to advocate is one under which states reduce their own revenue-raising and rely
on federal funds instead. This is hardly
consistent with states as fully equal sovereigns. And this hardly seems a model that the
Supreme Court’s conservative majority would want to embrace. Even an obsessive focus on state
tax cuts funded by state program cuts leaves more and more problems unaddressed,
eventually leading to greater federal involvement. But insisting that states have a constitutional
right to unconditional federal fiscal assistance to fund state tax cuts is very
difficult to square with any coherent conception of federalism and would leave
states increasingly as spending agents for the federal government. That leading Republicans are making this
argument suggests that their party is ceasing to be a consistent defender of
states’ role in our system in favor of a relentless pursuit of tax cuts (and
other its other substantive priorities).
Although the Democrats did steadfastly
press for state fiscal relief, I do not see that party taking up the states’
banner on any consistent basis, either.
In a political environment where loyalties to parties are far stronger
than those to particular institutions of government, having neither major party
deeply committed to states’ vitality could result in a lasting weakening of their
position in our system. Whether or not
one believes the states’ traditional roles should be maintained, that is a big
change. @DavidASuper1 Friday, March 19, 2021
Following Up on a Prior Post
Gerard N. Magliocca
The University of Kansas announced today that its University Press will not be shut down. The Press will instead proceed under new leadership and make various changes to its business model. Thanks to all of you who spoke out in favor of the Press. Monday, March 15, 2021
Recommended Listening: Amarica's Constitution Podcast
Jason Mazzone
In connection with his highly anticipated new book, The Words That Made Us: America's Constitutional Conversations, 1760-1840 (the first volume in a trilogy), Akhil Amar has started a fantastic podcast called "Amarica's Constitution." The most recent episode is on the constitutional misadventures of John Adams. All the details at akhilamar.com. Friday, March 12, 2021
Robert Jackson and the Non-Delegation Doctrine
Gerard N. Magliocca
I am working on a draft paper called "Robert Jackson's Non-Delegation Doctrine." The paper argues that Jackson thought that there was a non-delegation doctrine that applied to only congressional delegations to the President himself (as opposed to executive agencies and independent boards). I based this conclusion on two sources. First, a brief that Jackson wrote as Solicitor General in Currin v. Wallace (a 1939 case) in which he made this argument in a comprehensive fashion. Second, Jackson's concurrence in Youngstown, in which he said that Category One cases were subject to non-delegation limits, if you read the language carefully and consider what he says in Footnote Two of that opinion. Now I have a third piece of evidence--Jackson's draft of the Youngstown concurrence. Adam White, who wrote an excellent article back in 2006 about Jackson's drafts of the opinion, was kind enough to send me a scan of the early drafts. (He gets more than a hat-tip from me--more like a bow.). Here is what Jackson said in an early draft about what became Category One (I've underlined the relevant part): "Where the President acts in accord with an express enactment or policy of Congress, he can invoke for its support the sum of his own powers plus the sum of congressional powers at their maximum. Even so, it may be found unconstitutional. See Railroad Retirement Board v. Alton R. Co., 295 U.S. 330; Panama Refining Co. v. Ryan, 293 U.S. 389; Carter v. Carter Coal Co., 239; United States v. Butler, 297 U.S. 1; Schechter Poultry Co. v. United States, 295 U.S. 495. The inclusion of Panama Refining is especially telling here because (unlike the other cases) that holding was only about the non-delegation doctrine. Jackson emphasized in his Currin brief, though, that the case involved a delegation to the President himself (under the National Industrial Recovery Act) rather than to an agency or some other official. Later, Jackson reformulated this section and dropped the cites to these anti-New Deal cases. In Footnote Two of the opinion, which relates to Category One cases, he instead concentrated on other examples such as Curtiss-Wright and a fascinating opinion by Augustus Hand in the Second Circuit. Still, he made clear that the President could exercise only "all that Congress may delegate" and that there were "strict limits" on Congress's ability to delegate power over domestic affairs to the President himself. Anyway, I hope to have this draft ready for circulation by the end of the month. Tuesday, March 09, 2021
Joe Manchin, Hollywood Western hero
Andrew Koppelman
Sen. Joe Manchin (D-W.Va.) has the opportunity to become a Hollywood Western hero. He says he will “never” vote to abolish the filibuster. But with voting rights at stake, the nation may soon contemplate an episode reminiscent of the 1962 John Ford Western “The Man Who Shot Liberty Valance.” I explain in a new piece at The Hill, here. Wednesday, March 03, 2021
Living Originalism at the University of Saskatchewan
JB
Last month I gave a talk hosted by the Runnymede Society's University of Saskatchewan chapter about my theories of constitutional interpretation, and their possible application to Canadian constitutional law. Leonid Sirota (Auckland University of Technology) who founded and writes at the Double Aspect blog, offered his commentary.
Tuesday, March 02, 2021
Meet Me in the Middle Podcasts on The Cycles of Constitutional Time and Regulating Social Media
JB
This past month I did two podcasts on Meet Me in the Middle, hosted by Bill Curtis. The first podcast is on my new book, The Cycles of Constitutional Time and our current problems of constitutional rot. https://www.curtco.com/mmitm-53-jack-balkin The second podcast is on social media, and the right way to regulate (and not regulate) them.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |