Reconsidering Revolution
Guest Blogger
For the symposium on Gary Jeffrey Jacobsohn and Yaniv Roznai, Constitutional Revolution (Yale University Press, 2020).
Emily
Zackin
Jacobsohn
and Roznai begin their important look at constitutional revolution with the
observation that, while this term appears throughout the literature on
constitutional change, there is very little agreement about what it actually
means. They point out that most definitions of the term “constitutional revolution”
privilege form over function—that is, they require a violent, illegal, and
rapid rupture. That focus on process, they explain, is a mistake. The reason we
care about constitutional revolutions—arguably the reason that concept is so
ubiquitous—is that we care about outcomes. People who study constitutional
revolutions are trying to examine transformations so profound that what emerges
from them are not merely the old constitutions with some alterations, but
actually brand new constitutions. This, our authors tell us, should be our
focus—the emergence of constitutional understandings and practices so different
that they uproot and dislocate the old practices and understandings. We should
investigate, rather than posit, the process through which such radical transformations
occur.
Phrased
in this way—as a question about how constitutions are transformed—I think we can begin to appreciate the
importance of this work. If we get too focused on one model of constitutional
change, and here I think Ackerman’s model of constitutional moments is a good
candidate, we tend to spend our energies arguing about whether a certain
process meets the requirements of that one particular model. As I read it, this book is a call to
re-orient the scholarship on constitutional change away from a fixation on any
particular model of change and toward a more open, honest, and capacious
inquiry into how these near-total transformations actually occur. Scholars of
constitutional politics should endeavor to understand all of the possibilities,
and theorize constitutional revolution by examining them together.
After
all of that conceptual heavy lifting, Jacobsohn and Roznai then actually embark
on the project they have proposed—examining constitutional transformations that
have occurred through a range of different processes in different countries. They
demonstrate that there have been many different avenues to giant changes. Such
serious, deep engagement with so many constitutional systems is a rare and
valuable contribution to the literature on constitutional development in its
own right, not to mention a massive scholarly achievement. But the results of
their richly textured comparative work also leads them to propose a general
theory of constitutional revolution: disharmony accumulates within a constitutional
system and, in either a rapid process or through a more gradual one, a new
paradigm then emerges and displaces its predecessor.
This
theory reminded me of the philosopher of science Thomas Kuhn, who famously
described scientific revolution as the displacement of an old paradigm by a new
one. Those revolutions, according to Kuhn, are also driven by something I think
we could call disharmony. As existing paradigms begin to accumulate problems,
things they can’t explain or reconcile, shared worlds of understanding and
practice give way to new ones. According
to Kuhn:
When
“the profession can no longer evade anomalies that subvert the existing
tradition of scientific practice—then begin the extraordinary investigations
that lead the profession at last to a new set of commitments, a new basis for
the practice of science. The extraordinary episodes in which that shift of
professional commitments occurs are the ones known in this essay as scientific
revolutions. They are the tradition-shattering complements to the
tradition-bound activity of normal science.”
I
think this analogy to constitutionalism might work pretty well. Most of the
time, constitutionalism is a tradition-bound practice. To have a constitution is
to share a set of assumptions about how political institutions operate. And yet,
sometimes, those assumptions give way so completely, and are replaced with such
a wholly different web of understandings and practices that the old and new are
actually incommensurable. At that point, we might well say that a revolution
has occurred.
I
couldn’t find Kuhn’s name in the book, but I wondered whether his work had
figured into the conceptual framework offered here.
I
also wondered whether a critique of Kuhn might apply to this argument too—that
is, that there is actually no such thing as a revolution. Or perhaps a softer
version of this critique might go something like this: surely there aren’t just
little changes and big changes, but a continuum from trifling alterations on
one end to near-total transformations on the other. What is the value in
drawing a line somewhere along that continuum and calling everything to one
side of it “a revolution”?
The
book’s own account of constitutional development acknowledges that it is always
characterize by both change and continuity. The roots of the new are always
planted in old soil, so that abrupt and total rupture is usually more of a
fantasy, or founding myth, than a reality. Some changes happen in shorter
periods and in larger increments than others, but the old always gives rise to,
and is reflected in, whatever comes next.
Jacobsohn
and Roznai reject the terminology of “evolution” to describe the radical
transformations in which they are interested, but it struck me that evolution was
actually a good description for the developmental process they describe—a
process of change with continuity. Land mammals evolved from fish. And the land
mammals are definitely new—they’re almost wholly different fish—but no rupture
was required to achieve this massive transformation. Despite the continuity,
however, we can fruitfully talk about all the new features the land mammal now
possesses, and the way those features have transformed (revolutionized?) its identity.
Jacobsohn and Roznai so successfully document the varied paths to large-scale constitutional
transformation that it left me wondering whether constitutional scholars should
simply jettison the concept of revolution entirely. Why not simply acknowledge
that change with continuity marks all constitutional development, that some changes
are more gradual than others, that some will not lead anywhere much, that others
will have very big consequences, and that even very gradual development can result
in totally new paradigms? I am convinced by all of these features of Jacobsohn
and Roznai’s argument about the nature of constitutional change, but I am not
sure how the concept of revolution fits in, or helps us, here.
My other
question was what it is that Jacobsohn and Roznai argue is being transformed by
a constitutional revolution. They describe constitutional revolutions as
transformations in “the conceptual prism through which constitutionalism is
experienced in a given polity”(34). To me, this definition suggests a focus on
ideas, assumptions, or perceptions. One thing I find appealing about this
ideational focus is that it captures the Tinkerbell-like nature of
constitutions. They’re real, they constrain politics, but only because (and
only if) we believe that they’re real constraints. At times, though, I wondered
whether ideas are really all that is at stake in revolutions. What about
transformations in the structure of governing institutions or even in material
conditions? At the moment, I think the book remains tantalizingly ambiguous on
this point.
Let
me conclude by saying that I learned an enormous amount from this ambitious and
impressive work. It will certainly be a resource and touchstone for my own work
on constitutional development, and I suspect the same is true for everyone who
grapples with the concept of constitutional revolution.
Emily Zackin, is Assistant Professor of Political Science, Johns Hopkins University. You can reach her by e-mail at ezackin1 at jhu.edu
Posted
9:30 AM
by Guest Blogger [link]