Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Double Trouble: Optimistic Originalism and Baude and Sachs (Part V)
|
Friday, July 17, 2020
Double Trouble: Optimistic Originalism and Baude and Sachs (Part V)
Stephen Griffin
This is the fifth and last post in my
series discussing issues raised by my article “Optimistic Originalism.” The article uses a historical lens to
critically assess a recent trend in originalism which claims the theory is
capable of handling a variety of problems posed by the modern jurisprudence of
the Fourteenth Amendment, principally the equal protection clause. In the process the article raises questions
about how we should understand the scope of the achievement of those who
sponsored and ratified the Reconstruction amendments.
In the last part of “Optimistic
Originalism” I discuss why Brown is commonly viewed as a “living
constitutionalist” opinion (Here and elsewhere in these posts I put living
constitutionalism in scare quotes because I think the real issue is how to
understand the process of constitutional change outside Article V). I supplement the argument I provided in an
earlier article called “Rebooting Originalism” as to why Brown was not
and could not have been based on an originalist understanding of the Fourteenth
Amendment. In the footnotes I mention
the idea, advanced recently by William Baude and Stephen Sachs, that Brown
was in fact an originalist decision despite the Court’s apparent determination
that historical evidence (a more neutral term than originalism) was no help.
Baude and Sachs evidently disagree with my
argument about Brown, but for all the work they have done to this point,
it is not clear why. They label their
position “originalism is our law.” In
what follows I will comment on their claims, particularly as set forth in their
recent article “Grounding Originalism,” from the point of view of the position
I take in “Optimistic Originalism.”
In “Grounding Originalism” Baude and Sachs
make clear that saying “originalism is our law” means originalism (which
version?) is a criterion for whether a law is valid in the present, “not a drafting
guide or decision procedure.” They
stress the relevance of the “official story” we tell ourselves about how a
given proposition of constitutional law is valid, a story that involves tracing
validity back to the eighteenth-century founding (or Reconstruction of course,
in the case of the Reconstruction amendments).
Although their critics have pointed to possible deviations from this
official story (including Brown), Baude and Sachs respond that our legal
system has “higher-order practices” that show originalism in some form is still
the founding stone of our law.
For longtime passengers on the
constitutional theory train, there are a number of puzzling features as to how
Baude and Sachs go about making their claims.
The general tenor of the way they make their
argument tends to collapse the distinction between the Constitution and
ordinary law. They use examples drawn
from the common law or statutory law and simply assume that constitutional law
works the same way. But their analysis
seems off-key for other reasons as well.
Last November Jack Balkin participated in a Federalist Society panel on
originalism in which, consistent with his approach in Living Originalism,
he described the Constitution as a “framework for politics.” This is a fairly common view, but one finds
no hint of it whatsoever in Baude and Sachs.
For them, the Constitution is for lawyers only.
A related puzzle is the absence of any
sense that Americans have often transposed political conflicts to the
constitutional sphere. Surely it is
apparent that Americans like arguing about political issues in constitutional
terms. In fact, it is a quality foreign
observers remarked on from the beginning.
But this produces controversies of the kind historical evidence cannot
definitively settle. There are well-understood
reasons for the failure of the text to be more determinative, among them that
the Constitution was the result of political compromise, the corresponding ambiguity
of many of its clauses, and the fact that certain key matters (such as the
presidential removal power, the focus of the recent Seila Law case),
were not discussed at all.
I suggest these puzzles relate to notable
features of how Baude and Sachs make their argument. They treat advocates of novel (“off the
wall”) positions in constitutional law as if they were akin to criminals. The reality that Americans have disagreed
over the Constitution in good faith, relying on arguments seen as reasonable at
the time, is missing. One wants to
reassure them that their fellow Americans are not criminals, we’re just engaging
in something totally normal for our polity, which is advancing political and
policy goals through constitutional arguments.
This is of course common ground with respect to important works of constitutional
theory that, like Baude and Sachs, highlight the issue of constitutional change
and (unlike Baude and Sachs) the role of political and social movements – for
example, Bruce Ackerman’s influential We The People series and Balkin’s Living
Originalism.
This avoidance of reasonable disagreement
over the meaning of the Constitution leads to Baude and Sachs having a hard
time with the notion of discontinuities in American constitutional history. To be sure, here they have plenty of
company. They are surely correct that
many contemporary lawyers and judges do see our history and “our law” as one
continuous story we all have in common.
Fortunately for those of us who have the time to profit from it,
constitutional and legal historians have come to our rescue, particularly since
the 1960s. I have literally never read a
work of constitutional or legal history published since then which caused me to
think the American constitutional story was essentially one of continuity. That’s one big reason for my interest in the
process of constitutional change. But
Baude and Sachs are undismayed by these findings. To my way of thinking, in stating their
claims they run this point right into the ground (I’m presenting only part of
this list):
“(1) We treat the Constitution as a legal
text, originally enacted in the late eighteenth century.
(2) This constitutional text regulates the
selection of legal officials, even when such regulations are unpopular or
contrary to tradition.
(3) Actors in our legal system don’t
acknowledge, and indeed reject, any official legal breaks or discontinuities
from the Founding.”
My target here is (3). Before I describe why this constitutes a
denial of the Civil War and Reconstruction (along with much else in our
constitutional experience), we should wonder who the “we” and the “actors” are
in this list. Are Baude and Sachs
appealing to contemporary views about the past or the views held at the
time? If contemporary views, this seems
odd for an originalist theory. If views
held by past actors, well, you’ll have to trust me, but there is plenty of
evidence that at various crisis points, Americans did in fact believe that the
Constitution itself was in question and that the only way to resolve the crisis
was to have a Second American Revolution or Founding presaging a fundamental
constitutional departure. If you value
what historians think, there are plenty of examples like Charles and Mary Beard
in the past and Eric Foner in the present who in fact regard the Civil War and
Reconstruction as a “Second Founding,” as Foner recently put it. In other words, that there was a fundamental
and official “legal break” and discontinuity in American constitutionalism
necessitating a refounding and, yes, thus a new Constitution.
Baude and Sachs’s position is an excellent
example of what I term “Civil War denialism” which I see as quite widespread
among judges and lawyers. Civil War
denialism is the treatment of the constitutional issues that surrounded the War
(such as the constitutionality of slavery and secession) as if they could not
be the subject of reasonable disagreement at the time. For instance, in light of Mark Graber’s
pathbreaking study of Dred Scott (a work too many constitutional scholars
have apparently not yet read), a good example is simply accepting the
Republican critique of that infamous decision as if there were no case to be
made against African American citizenship prior to the adoption of the
Thirteenth and Fourteenth Amendments. As
articulated in a memorable scene early in Steven Spielberg’s Lincoln,
however, there is a reason we needed multiple and foundational amendments.
Insisting without qualification on the
continuity of our constitutional experience arguably puts Baude and Sachs in poor
company. After all, in the wake of the
Civil War the people who were most determined to assert legal continuity were
former Confederates, not radical Republicans.
Here is what the Joint Committee
on Reconstruction had to say in 1866 about an argument they made similar to
that of Baude and Sachs: “It is more
than idle, it is a mockery, to contend that a people who have thrown off their
allegiance, destroyed the local government which bound their States to the
Union as members thereof, defied its authority, refused to execute its laws,
and abrogated every provision which gave them political rights within the
Union, still retain, through all, the perfect and entire right to resume, at
their own will and pleasure all their privileges within the Union, and
especially to participate in its government, and to control the conduct of its
affairs.” The Joint Committee knew a
constitutional discontinuity when it saw one.
This point about constitutional argument in
the wake of the Civil War serves to throw into sharp relief one signal
characteristic of how Baude and Sachs make their case – they focus almost
entirely on the world of case law, paying relatively little attention to the
“Constitution outside the courts.” But if
we were to focus on the contested issue of presidential war powers, for
example, what we would see (as I describe in my book Long Wars and the
Constitution) is members of Congress and (at least former) executive
officials openly acknowledging that the Constitution had to change informally
outside Article V in order to meet the challenge posed by the Cold War. Theories of informal constitutional change
should help us understand how this could happen and, if at all, legitimately –
but Baude and Sachs rule such theories out of bounds on originalist
grounds. As I argue in “Optimistic
Originalism,” what we should be doing is asking how an Article V-driven
positive law theory could have worked in an environment where everyone was
trying to avoid making formal amendments out of a concern for political
stability.
I think an extended analysis would show that Baude and
Sachs continually oscillate between two sets of two poles simultaneously (perhaps I should have labeled this post “quadruple trouble”). They assert that it is part of our system of
positive law that the Constitution is the supreme law of the land (which no one
disputes) and that this is equivalent to agreeing that an unspecified (though
broad) version of originalism is the only method of interpretation that has a
basis in the eighteenth century founding (which, as Jonathan Gienapp has
recently shown, is false).
At the same time, they oscillate between insisting
that any knowledgeable lawyer knows that originalism in their sense is our law
(the “official story”) and that understanding its deep structure involves
research into legal history with results potentially so esoteric that only a
select few could understand the mistake everyone has made deviating from that
same law for decades. This actually somewhat
parallels the structure of Ackerman’s theory, yet they reject it supposedly
because it does not conform to the official story.
Baude and Sachs challenge their critics:
“What, then, is our law? If not originalism, what? Positive law provides a lens
to judge not only originalism but its alternatives.” Here I think we should keep in mind that some
of the most prominent alternatives to H.L.A. Hart’s theory (the theory that
Baude and Sachs deploy), such as those from Ronald Dworkin in the past to Scott
Shapiro and Mitch Berman in the present, are motivated in part by the
differences the U.S. Constitution makes to our system of positive law. Hart had no reason to take any strong notice
of these differences and I, for one, doubt that theories of jurisprudence can
make a strong contribution to debates in constitutional theory unless they are
firmly grounded both in history and a historicist sensibility.
Posted 12:46 PM by Stephen Griffin [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |