Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Unoriginal Joke (Part III): Living Constitutionalism and Social Progress
|
Friday, June 26, 2020
Unoriginal Joke (Part III): Living Constitutionalism and Social Progress
Guest Blogger
Charles Barzun
In the last Part of this series, I suggested that the essential nugget at the heart of “living constitutionalism” is the idea that part of what grounds the constitution’s authority for us is its capacity to adapt (i.e., to respond appropriately) to changing circumstances. I called this the adaptability claim.
Different versions of living constitutionalism fill out the adaptability claim in different ways, for different reasons. But in my view, one quite traditional version has not been given the attention its due, even though it is, to my mind, the one that most closely tracks the way the Supreme Court itself talks about and produces constitutional change. It also more closely ties the method of judicial reasoning it recommends to the phenomenon that seems to me to motivate all versions of living constitutionalism: social progress.
Despite its emphasis on progress, though, the view I describe is consistent with, and perhaps even requires, originalism (or at least one version of it).
I.
How so? Well, let’s begin—outside the constitutional context—with the common law. The authority of the common law has long been justified by reference to something like the adaptability claim. The idea is that the law is authoritative because judges are able to revise, alter, and extend it in ways responsive to the facts they confront in new cases.
The method of reasoning envisioned is thus “bottom up,” rather than merely “top down.” It is inductive, rather than deductive. Judges need not always merely apply fixed rules to new facts; instead, they can let their pre-reflective intuitions about the proper outcome in any given case suggest a modification to, or revision of, the relevant “rule.” Hence Oliver Wendell Holmes’s famous statement that “it is the merit of the common law that it decides the case first and determines the principle afterwards.“
At the time of the founding (and well into the nineteenth century) the analogy to science that the term “inductive” suggests was taken quite seriously. The founder James Wilson wrote that “common law, like natural philosophy, when properly studied, is a science founded on experiment. The latter is improved and established by carefully and wisely attending to the phenomena of the material world; the former, by attending, in the same manner, to those of man and society.”
Why not then base constitutional adjudication on this model, so that it, too, may evolve like the common law? Of course, some have argued for doing precisely that. But there are two obvious, and related, objections to doing so today.
First, Wilson and others in his day thought judges were perceiving natural principles of “man and society” with a human faculty they called the “moral sense.” But today we tend to be more skeptical about the reliability, and even existence, of such a faculty. That is true both because people’s intuitions about just outcomes vary widely across society and because they seem to change dramatically over time.
Second, once we move to the constitutional context, it seems harder to justify authorizing courts to engage in judicial review of democratic legislation based on their “intuitions” about just outcomes. That’s especially true if those intuitions that vary widely. Besides, when interpreting the Constitution, courts are interpreting written law. Thus, it calls for “top down,” not “bottom up” reasoning.
This, of course, is precisely why originalists have traditionally rejected living constitutionalism.
II.
One can see some of the main versions of living constitutionalism as ways of filling out the adaptability claim in ways that do not fall prey to these objections.
Some views offer a different rationale for the adaptability claim altogether. Under these views, the constitution must be amenable to change to ensure that it maintains its democratic legitimacy. Popular Constitutionalism and Bruce Ackerman’s theory of “constitutional moments” are examples of this approach. Since the Constitution was ratified over 200 years ago by a process that excluded women, African-Americans, and Native Americans, in order for the Constitution to maintain its legitimacy it must be capable of giving voice to more recent and more democratic expressions of popular will.
These views thus see living constitutionalism as less a claim about the content of law itself than one about who authors it. Thus, popular constitutionalists counsel judicial deference and responsiveness to public opinion, while Ackerman encourages judges to read certain texts (whether statutes or cases) that have been ratified by constitutional politics in the right sort of way.
Ronald Dworkin’s “moral reading” of the constitution is far closer to the traditional common-law theory. For Dworkin, the Constitution must be able to adapt through case-by-case adjudication to respond to changing conditions. It is thus “content-sensitive” (in philosophical jargon) in a way that the Wilsonian view is and Ackerman’s theory is not. Judges engage in “justificatory ascent” in order to properly discern those principles of political morality (embodied in the Constitution) that best “fit and justify” the relevant sources. Judges then apply those principles to the current case.
Dworkin’s approach seems vulnerable to the same skeptical worries that plague the Wilsonian view. Are moral principles part of the fixture of the world in the way that physical laws (allegedly) are? If not, why trust them? Dworkin’s answer to such questions is controversial, but the gist is that he dismisses such “meta-ethical” worries as “external” threats. Moral arguments can only be met by other moral arguments.
In my view, Balkin’s Living Originalism can be seen as an effort to combine these two approaches (and render them both consistent with originalism). Like Ackerman and the popular constitutionalists, Balkin treats the Constitution’s adaptability as important for reasons of democratic legitimacy—enabling it to respond to social movements and political mobilizations. Yet Balkin endorses a method of interpretation that is essentially Dworkinian (what Balkin calls the “method of text and principle”). I have some questions about whether these approaches can be combined in this way, but I leave that issue aside.
What about David Strauss’s version of Living Constitutionalism? His approach is indeed an effort to explain and justify constitutional law on the common-law model. And he seems to gesture towards something like the Wilsonian view when he explains that the common law prizes the judicial attitudes of “humility and cautious empiricism.” But when it comes to describing how judges actually decide cases, Strauss’s picture sometimes seems to be a conventional, positivist one in which the precedents are mostly clear and, where they are not, courts simply resort to “things like fairness and social policy.”
It seems to me that Strauss’s account is on the right track. Perhaps he is reluctant to embrace the Wilsonian view for the reasons stated above. But in the remainder of this post I want to suggest that the Wilsonian view can be revised in a way that renders it both more plausible and more radical than typically recognized.
III.
The general spirit of Wilson’s approach can be maintained, with some modification, in a way that is responsive to the objections raised above. Let me first explain and defend the kind of reasoning it involves in general (first objection). Then I will take up the question of whether it fits the constitutional context.
Recall that Wilson’s core idea is that when making practical decisions of the sort judges make, one may have intuitions about proper outcomes and that those intuitions are often reliable guides to decisionmaking. Like a scientist, the decision maker relies on experience, but it is experience in a wider sense—one that includes sensory perception and emotional or intuitive reactions.
It seems undeniable that most people have such moral reactions and that they pervasively rely on them in their personal lives. Moreover, theorists use them to develop moral and political theories, sometimes through a process of “reflective equilibrium” (a process that was itself first articulated to justify induction in the scientific realm). And they take those theories to be correct.
At the same time, though, most of us recognize that our intuitive responses to phenomena are largely determined by our social environment, which may make us suspicious of them. The cause for suspicion is only heightened when we realize how much our own reactions and attitudes can change over time. If our intuitions aren’t trustworthy, then neither are the theories we base on them.
This produces a dilemma: We often are convinced that our own moral intuitions and theories properly pick out and evaluate the morally relevant facts. But we also know that our intuitions and theories would be otherwise were our social conditions different.
Dworkin offered one response to this dilemma. He considered it an illusion and the questions that give rise to it “bogus” ones. Our moral views do not depend for their standing on any quasi-perceptual faculty that could be distorted. They stand on their own feet. All we can do is to engage in first-order, moral argument with each other.
But there’s another approach. One could instead face the dilemma squarely and try to reconcile its two horns. To do so, one would infer from one’s substantive moral judgments that the process which led to your having those judgments was an epistemically healthy one. Perhaps it’s because you listened to people you’d never heard, read a book on some topic—or simply watched an 8:46 minute video of a brutal murder. Whatever the series of events, the process resulted in you “seeing” something in a different way—a clearer way. You’ve learned from experience.
When we make the judgment that some historical process has improved society-wide moral views about how to treat each other (or animals or the planet), we conclude that the process produced “progress.” That conclusion depends in part on an historical judgment about the epistemic value of the process: We conclude that our current attitude is the product of free and open discussion, debate, and discovery of new facts, rather than something produced through intimidation, oppression, or mass hysteria.
Note that this method of reasoning does not assume social progress necessarily occurs with the passage of time. That would drain the concept of all meaning. Indeed, the opposite is true: It is precisely because progress cannot be guaranteed that the kind of self-reflection envisioned is necessary. The task is to reconcile one’s substantive moral convictions with one’s judgments about the nature of the process that likely produced those convictions.
This may sound like a strange way to reason, but it’s quite familiar in other contexts. To confirm an experimental result, a scientist must ensure that it fits with her scientific theory and that the experiment was run correctly and not corrupted in some way. In weighing a witness’s testimony, the juror must assess the plausibility of the testimony itself and the sources of bias the other party’s lawyer identified on cross that could be distorting that testimony.
IV.
Does such reasoning have any role to play in constitutional adjudication? Some evidence that it does lies in the fact that it describes, better than most other forms of living constitutionalism, how the Supreme Court itself treats constitutional change.
The Court does not generally talk of “constitutional moments” or “ratifying elections.” It usually does not purport to be relying on its own “moral reading” of the constitution. It does not say, “the precedents aren’t clear, so look to fairness and policy.”
What it does do—at least in some areas—is talk about the need for constitutional doctrine to respond to changed circumstances—even when the change involved is one of the “understanding” or “perception” of the relevant facts.
Consider, in this light, the Court’s most explicit (and controversial) discussions of the nature of constitutional change in Planned Parenthood v. Casey (1992). In defending its decision to uphold Roe, the Court explained that it did so on the ground that there had not been a change in the “understanding of the facts” related to abortion since Roe in the way that there had been a change with respect to segregation between Plessy and Brown.
Implicit in the joint opinion’s analysis was the assumption not only that the Brown Court interpreted the equal-protection clause correctly, but also that the change in the “understanding of the facts” was a progressive one. Society—and, therefore, the Court—had learned from experience (which included the witnessing of what racist ideology had wrought in Germany).
So Plessy was “wrong the day it was decided,” but it was wrong primarily because the Court had misunderstood the facts (i.e., the social meaning of segregation), not the relevant constitutional principles. One day the same might be true of Roe, the Court seemed to allow, but not yet—at least not in 1992.
In other words, the Court explained the Constitution’s ability to adapt to changing circumstances not by reference to democratic legitimacy (as Ackerman and popular constitutionalists do), nor even by direct reference to the constitutional principles of political morality themselves. Instead, it explained the need to revise constitutional interpretations—or not to do so—by reference to social progress.
This view has both conservative and radical implications. It is conservative because the organic metaphor it trades off implies some degree of social consensus. There must be something approximating “society” that can “live” and adapt by responding to changed circumstances. After all, there is always part of the society that has long understood the relevant facts all too well.
But it is also potentially radical because it looks to our history—our whole history, not just the founding—with the recognition that history is always open to question, doubt, and reinterpretation. To quote a former Supreme Court Justice, there are “no resolutions immune to rethinking when the significance of old facts may have changed in the changing world.”
Both aspects of this kind of living constitutionalism have been on full display in recent days. If there is ever a time that seems to be simultaneously demanding more societal unity and radical change in light of the significance of old facts, that time is now.
III.
The approach I’ve just described is far from novel. Its roots lie in American pragmatism and in its subsequent development in the postwar legal-process school. The running theme throughout, which owes more to Dewey and James than to Holmes, is that society is always in transition, always in a state of “becoming”—and that any effort to understand what society is becoming requires an inquiry that is at once factual and evaluative, historical and moral, procedural and substantive.
As we’ve seen, though, the essential logic of the approach goes all the way back to the founding generation.
Which brings us back to originalism. Some have argued that the “official story” of our legal system has it that all our law must be traced back to the founding. The inductive approach I’ve just described has such a pedigree, as do the constitutional doctrines it has yielded. Those doctrines fit naturally with originalism because they are conceptualized as changing applications of constitutional principles in light of new facts—or new understandings of facts.
We might even go further. It’s hard to make sense of the idea of “progress” or, for that matter, a “living constitution,” if we do not have some relative constant against which to compare it. Perhaps that constant is our “official story.”
If so, then we have a response to the objection I raised above but have so far ignored: What justifies judges in using this method of reasoning to engage in judicial review?
The answer: It is our law, and judges take an oath to support it.
Charles Barzun is the Horace W. Goldsmith Research Professor of Law at the University of Virginia. You can reach him by e-mail at cbarzun at law.virginia.edu
Posted 9:30 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |