Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Reason, Feeling, and Religion: A Response to Linda McClain
|
Friday, June 12, 2020
Reason, Feeling, and Religion: A Response to Linda McClain
Guest Blogger For the symposium on Linda McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020). Cathleen Kaveny
Linda McClain’s book is a meticulously researched and
compellingly presented study of moral and political language. She illuminates
the different ways in which the term “bigot” has been used in American
constitutional law, from the battles over slavery in the nineteenth century to
the skirmishes over same sex marriage in the twenty-first. As they are
currently configured, contemporary legal controversies pit the religious
freedom of devout Christians against the rights LGBTQ Americans to be treated
with dignity and equality in the public square.
As a theologian as well as a law professor, I have found
myself increasingly frustrated with the way in which religion is framed in
today’s free exercise litigation. Religious belief is presented as adamant,
full of feeling, and insulated from both intellectual content and broader
critique. This view of religion is supported not only by those skeptical of its
value in American public life, but also by its purported friends, such as the
Becket Fund. In the long run, I believe conceptualizing religion in a way that
divorces feeling from reason will be harmful for both religious communities
themselves and for a nation that continues to include many religious believers.
McClain’s book has helped me understand why this is the case.
The Charge of Bigotry
as Prophetic Indictment
As McClain describes so well, deploying the term “bigot”
shuts down the discussion, it does not open it up. One’s target is left with
only two options. On the one hand, they can indignantly deny the charge, often
reversing it. (“I’m not the bigot, you’re
the bigot!”). On the other hand, they can humbly admit guilt, repent, and
promise to reform. Human nature being what it is, this does not happen quite as
often as it should happen.
What kind of term is the word “bigot,” then? In my view, it currently functions as a term
of prophetic indictment, a charge that someone is not acting in accordance with
the basic moral-legal charter of our polity. Just as the biblical prophets
indicted people for violating the terms of their fundamental national covenant
(between God and Israel), so those who use the term “bigot” are condemning
people who violate the terms of our national covenant, the Constitution. Prophetic indictment is undeniably moral language. It is not, however, the
language of moral deliberation. It
does not facilitate or even endorse finely drawn moral distinctions. Instead,
prophetic indictment asks us to see and clearly repudiate a fundamental
violation of our moral covenant.
The use of prophetic indictment is an important part of
American political discourse. Its origins are equally religious and political,
because it was born in a theocracy—the Commonwealth of Massachusetts. More
specifically, its roots are in Puritan jeremiads, which are in turn modeled on
the fiery indictments of Isaiah and Jeremiah. Warning of the dire consequences
divine wrath, they castigate the people for their sins, and call for repentance
and reform. As the country became secularized, the jeremiad expanded, and its
basic framework of indictment for violation of a covenant requirement became
broadened and secularized. While the days of the Puritans are long behind us,
the jeremiad remains a strong and flexible staple of American political
discourse. It has been used by liberals, conservatives, and radicals to make
their point in the public square. (See, e.g, James Darsey, The Prophetic Tradition and Radical Rhetoric in America, 1999).
I’m Not a Bigot, By
God!
Precisely because they do not invite definitional precision,
the exact meaning of terms of prophetic indictment can be hard to pin down.
McClain’s book helped me tremendously in thinking about who labels whom a
“bigot” and why. At the same time, I remained a bit fuzzy about the actual
meaning of the term. So I consulted the Oxford English Dictionary, which
provides some etymological background, as well as some sense of why religious
people might be both especially sensitive and especially susceptible to the
charge. According to the OED, the term means either a) a religious person who
is too devout or committed to the tenets of faith; or b) a religious hypocrite.
The source of the word is unclear; some suggest that it comes from the German
“bei Gott” (“by God”), and thereby refers to oaths that religious people would
take; others have suggested that it pertains to the Beguines, a Belgian order
of lay women which was suppressed for heresy and which were associated with
other groups who used misused religion for their own gain.
A fundamental question that McClain raises throughout the
book is whether bigotry is a matter of bad reasons or a bad motive. The
etymology of the term helps explain the confusion. To say that someone is too
religious is to say that one’s specifically religious beliefs are held in a
disordered way—they are too intense, too judgmental, or too unbalanced. To say
that someone is a hypocrite is to say that they are willing to put burdens on
others in public that they themselves do not follow in private. These two
character flaws seem distinct; how could they possibly be related enough to fit
under the same label? One way to do make
them fit is to assume that people who are too religiously committed and
judgmental about others cannot possibly be willing to apply the same standards
to themselves, at least in private. Another way is to operate through the
Golden Rule: no one who applies their religious standards to other people in
such a severe way would be willing to have analogous standards applied to them
in the same way.
Yet putting those two definitions together, no matter how
uneasily, helps us see why the charge of bigotry is so explosive: In essence,
the charge means that the target’s reasons for acting are so flawed that they
are either intellectually obtuse or could not possibly be acting in good faith.
So the charge freezes the targets between the Scylla of stupidity and the
Charybdis of hypocrisy. That is not a comfortable place to be. No wonder those
targets aren’t in the mood for moral self-reflection and self-criticism, as
McClain’s work shows.
The meaning of the term “bigot” has evolved, of course.
According to the Merriam-Webster on line dictionary, a “bigot” is “a person who
is obstinately or intolerantly devoted to his or her own opinions and
prejudices especially: one who regards or treats the members of a group (such
as a racial or ethnic group) with hatred and intolerance.” Although the reach
of the term is broader, as McClain shows, its application continues to raise
the question between reasons and motives, soundness of judgments in categorizing
other people and probity of purpose in making such judgments.
In the cases currently under discussion, which pit rights of
religious freedom against the non-discrimination rights of the rights of the
LGBTQ community, the prevailing understanding of religion in American law
compounds the problem.
Motive and Rationale:
Reason, Feeling, and Religion
As many scholars of religious studies have pointed out, that
definition is highly influenced by the country’s Protestant origins. It is
defined in terms of individuals rather than communities, and tends to speak of
belief in terms of a strong feeling rather than rationally held commitments.
Indeed, faith is often set over and against reason in this conception.
Moreover, on this picture, religion tends to be a “private” matter. It is not
something that is discussed in public, especially not in the political sphere.
In public, it is viewed more as a matter of emotional attachment than
intellectual commitment. It can be applauded or derogated, but not intellectually
interrogated.
This view of religion is reinforced in the context of First
Amendment litigation. American courts steer clear of making any assessment of
the rationality of litigants’ religious claims, and even of their religiously
based moral claims. When tasked when evaluating free exercise claims, the
operative question facing the courts is whether the claimants are sincere. In the context of a McClain’s
question, sincerity not only shows that a person is religious, but also that he
or she is not a hypocrite—that he or she does not fit one of the two key prongs
of the original definition of bigot. But
what exactly is sincerity and how
does one show or test it? In the contexts litigating American religion,
sincerity seem to be equated with depth and intensity of personal feeling,
rather than coherence of intellectual and moral judgment.
In some ways, this equation of sincerity with honest and
deep emotional commitment is understandable, given the dominance of Evangelical
Protestantism in the United States. In that strand of Christianity, the
subjective connection with God is an important part of being saved from
damnation. Nineteenth and twentieth
century liberal theology also emphasized feeling rather than reason; the great
German Protestant theologian Friedrich Schleiermacher influentially defined
religion as a “feeling of absolute dependence” as a strategy for reconciling
Christianity with Enlightenment conceptions of reason.
But Christianity, even Evangelical Protestantism, was never
a matter of mere feeling. Even John Wesley, who described his salvific
encounter with God as having his heart “strangely warmed,” recognized that
discerning the content of Christian belief was far more than a matter of
consulting one’s own feelings. He articulated what is now known as the
“Wesleyan quadrilateral,” which directs believers to examine emerging ethical
questions in light of the insights of Scripture, tradition, and reason, as well
as experience. Experience might include feeling, but was not limited to it—it
is best understood as reflective living in the light of faith. Moreover, these
sources are not hermetically sealed from one another. Discerning how to
interpret Scripture is an intellectual conundrum itself. In his fascinating
volume The Civil War as a Theological
Crisis (2015), American religious
historian Mark Noll describes two divergent ways of approaching the Bible to
deal with slavery: those opposed to it tended to emphasize the “spirit” of the
text, and its pervasive themes of love, human dignity, brotherhood, etc. Those
who supported slavery focused on the “letter” of particular biblical passages
that seemed to support (or at least not to oppose) the practice.
As I noted above, the charge of “bigotry” presents
conservative religious believers with a choice: they can accept the Scylla of
irrationality or cling to the Charybdis of hypocrisy. Encouraged by the current
shape of religious liberty litigation, they opt to be irrational (or perhaps
arational) rather than hypocrites. By stressing their sincerity, they insulate
the substance of their claims about how human beings should live and human
societies should organize themselves from judicial scrutiny. They also
increasingly think their claims should be insulated from scrutiny from their
fellow citizens and fellow believers.
But no normative
tradition that makes claims about how human beings should organize their
individual and collective lives can be so intellectually insulated, whether it
is religious or secular. And most of the mainstream religious traditions in the
United States do not see themselves as so isolated: they train their leaders in
divinity schools, many of which are attached to universities. The Becket Fund
and other religious liberty groups are doing American religious groups no favors
by encouraging them to frame themselves as sincere well-meaning naïfs, escaping
the charge of bigotry by emphasizing sincerity rather than rationality of
belief.
Competing Normative Traditions
The issue of rational belief raises a larger question.
According to what framework is a religious or moral framework to be judged
rational for purposes of constitutional adjudication? McClain’s book suggests
that the ultimate touchstone is the normative framework of the Constitution
itself—she reads it as a political charter for promoting individual dignity,
equality, and respect for difference, which progressively implements a democratic
egalitarian vision over the course of generations. Ironically enough, the
Puritans would be sympathetic to the vision of the Constitution as a political
covenant implementing a general moral vision for the nation as a whole. I am
sympathetic to that vision myself.
But there are at least three obstacles to using this vision
as the touchstone to adjudicate cases of discrimination. First, not everyone
reads the Constitution in that fashion. Originalists tend to view it more or
less as a blueprint for limited government, incorporating procedural checks and
balances and protection for a basic and somewhat static set of individual
rights—especially the right of religious freedom. Second, the era in which a
liberal political philosophy could effectively work hand in glove to support a
liberal constitutional jurisprudence has come and gone in both academia and the
culture. As one recent book argues, we are long past the era of “peak Rawls”
(See Katrina Forrester, In the Shadow of
Justice, 2019). And the victory of Donald Trump, in part based on his
promise to appoint originalists to the bench, suggests that a sizable minority
of the population is not totally comfortable with a developmental liberal
approach to jurisprudence. Whatever its merits, we are at most one Supreme
Court vote away from a repudiation of the progressive vision of constitutional
interpretation McClain outlines.
In the context of these three obstacles, how might tensions
between religious liberty and anti-discrimination rights for LGBTQ citizens
evolve in the future? One possibility is that church teaching will develop on
these issues in the way that it has on racial issues. For example, I know many
theologians and philosophers working out of many different branches of
Christianity who do not rest content with sincerity; they are doing the hard
intellectual work of trying to integrate new insights into their religious
traditions. They are not consulting their feelings. They are making their
arguments. Such development is not unprecedented. Inspired by the success of
the American experiment in democracy and religious freedom, the Roman Catholic
Church authoritatively developed its teaching on church –state issues in the
Second Vatican Council.
A second possibility is that intellectual coherence is
sacrificed for civic peace and political expedience. Some say that the nature
and scope of exemptions to generally enacted anti-discrimination laws is not
justified on the basis of principle, but as the price of not provoking a
backlash. Eventually, the old generation will die off, and a new, more
open-minded generation will take its place. I am not sure this is the case,
even with respect to race, as recent tragic events indicate. Church teaching
may have developed to condemn racism. That does not mean church-goers have
extirpated it from their hearts.
The third possibility increasingly worries me, based upon my
reading around religious blogs and twitter feeds. If polarization and
alienation continues, I would not be entirely shocked to see certain strands of
originalism developing into even more robust calls for states’ rights. If
conservative religious believers see themselves as living within a moral
tradition that is not only fundamentally incompatible with, but also unable to
communicate effectively with the Rawlsian tradition of liberal democracy, they
may think their best option is to set up their own political communities,
guided by their own religiously infused normative commitments. The First
Amendment’s prohibition of establishment of religion was only applied to the
states in the mid-twentieth century (Everson
v. Board of Education, 1947); it would not be too hard for a determined
originalist to undo this extension. This would help clear the way for states to
establish a vision of the good life, as well as the rights and duties of both
believers and non-believers, which was unapologetically inflected with
religious belief. While all states would be tolerant, at least some states
would no longer maintain the pretense of being religiously neutral in their
definition of the nature and scope of toleration.
If this happens, the mid-twentieth century version of the American
dream of a strong, robust, and compassionate solidarity in pluralism will have
died, or at least have transformed beyond recognition. I like this dream. And
it probably won’t happen. It’s probably just an unfounded fear rooted in the
anomie and anxiousness of this pandemic. Or so I keep telling myself.
Cathleen Kaveny is Darald and Juliet Libby Professor of Law
and Theology at Boston College. She can be reached at cathleen.kaveny@bc.edu.
Posted 9:30 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |