Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Secession – in America, and America: Part One
|
Monday, May 25, 2020
Secession – in America, and America: Part One
Guest Blogger For the Symposium on Timothy William Waters's Boxing Pandora: Rethinking Borders, States, and Secession in a Democratic World (Yale University Press, 2020) and F. H. Buckley's American Secession: The Looming Threat of a National Breakup (Encounter Books, 2020).
Timothy William Waters
As
Socrates said, “I only know general things.”[1]
Boxing Pandora’s argument is general. But if it works,
it should work for America too – at least for a world with America in it.
If the world were America, my book would be very
different; I might not even have bothered. But the world’s more, the problem Boxing
Pandora addresses is real, and the reasons it is have something to do with a
global order which America, more than any other country, has shaped. Even if
secession isn’t fit or wise for this country, it’s worth considering what America’s
role might be in shaping a solution to what most assuredly is a problem for the
much of the world.
I’m gratified
by the thoughtful engagement in this symposium. For scholars who disagree with
my thesis to take it seriously is a high compliment. I see six themes across their
critiques – two about practical outcomes, two about history and process, and
two about America. Namely:
* secession
makes things worse, and other things work better;
* peoples
are historical, and customs preferable to rules; and
* secession
can’t work in America, and America won’t tolerate secession in the world.
I’ll deal
with the four general critiques in Part One, the two about America in Part Two.
Several of them depend on curiously static assumptions – fixities, the
interrogation of which is the point of Boxing Pandora. That’s a
theoretical purpose – but not ideal theory: I am consciously making a normative
argument in light of realist assumptions about power and law.
The
reviewers are thoughtful, their views serious. So I’ll end with a suggestion of
how, if they’re right, an exceptional America, in which secession is neither
possible nor desirable, might nonetheless contribute to a practical right of
secession.
1. Worse. . .
Does secession make things worse? What if new states
enact bad laws, or oppress new minorities? What if the mere possibility of
secession makes minorities threaten exit to blackmail the state?
Some things only look worse. The ‘undeserved concessions’
Tsai worries about are the politics any sensible theory of secession should
count on. (Coase might agree.) After all, what is ‘undeserved’? Why would we
assume things are deservedly distributed in the existing state? This objection sounds
less empirical than normative: its ‘efficiencies’ only make sense if you
assuming the existing state.
Somin’s fear that secessionists might be “severely
oppressive” shouldn’t concern us. Not because they won’t, or because small is
better. (I
argue at length against assumptions that smaller states are worse, but avoid
Buckley’s claim that they’re necessarily better. Better is the state
whose people desire it.) It’s because there’s
no data to support the fear that they’ll be worse – besides, we have few
ways to ensure good behavior by existing states. It’s less a prudential
objection, more a default preference for the status quo.
And Somin
suggests an ameliorating move I favor: nothing precludes additional
requirements – human rights, minority protections, denuclearization. A right of
secession isn’t self-actuating, it needs diplomatic support – so secessions are
moments of leverage (which we don’t have over existing states).
But change is risky: Why vote on such momentous questions,
when people are so demonstrably ignorant? Somin worries people will make
foolish choices. But that’s a concern for democracy in general. Existing states
are often ethnicized and no more likely to promote unbiased decision-making; at
most, they have the grim virtue of stable expectations. Yes, the stakes are
higher in secession – which is precisely why it’s desirable to ask the people
directly. To say people cannot be trusted is to say that the most essential
question of governance cannot be asked. (Nothing prevents states from incorporating
elites or legislative input. And Somin’s point suggests something I didn’t emphasize
in Boxing Pandora: the best referenda will be two-staged. A confirmatory
vote would have dramatically reduced Brexit’s dysfunction.)
2. And Better
Even if secession doesn’t make things worse, don’t
other tools work better? Why secession, when federalism and voting with your
feet don’t break up the state?
We needn’t prefer secession. They aren’t mutually
exclusive; a state can offer minority rights and allow secession. But secession
has a unique feature: Other tools ameliorate the problem of being in someone
else’s state; secession allows a community to take on the role of a
state – subsidiarity at the system level.
Other tools don’t magically operate – they are
domestic political bargains, made in particular circumstances and in the shadow
of global norms. The deal’s predictably less good for minorities because the bargaining’s
done in a locked unit. A
key insight of Boxing Pandora – one that follows from negotiations and
game theory – is that communities make better bargains if they can exit.
Secession isn’t just about leaving, but about better deals for staying.
It’s true
a right of secession increases the chance of secession. For some, this is a
harm, because we should prefer ‘voice’ to exit, but that’s a false choice. Allowing
exit creates incentives for states to give communities ‘voice’ so that they
won’t leave. Besides, while states should give citizens greater voice, making
that shared voice a moral good precludes the very question at issue:
Ought this be a people?
‘Voice’ is ironic, because behind many
objections to secession is an unvoiced assumption: Breaking up the state is
failure, a bad thing. But there is nothing inherently good about the states we
happen to have; they are even less likely to be good if their own people don’t
want them.
3. A People isn’t an Election: The Uses of
History
And who
are those people? Boxing Pandora relies on referenda to identify and justify
new states – a thin, procedural liberalism that ignores the thick, historical
drivers of belonging and identity.
Lind
worries I’m in thrall to social constructivists. But I agree with him (and
Nicoletti) that identities form by historical processes. They’re sticky –
constructed, but not just as we please. (That’s Renan’s point: historical
foundations and the need to affirm them. It’s history and the
plebiscite.)
The problem
is not how a people comes to be, but how we respond to it in politics. (It’s a
classic risk for the social sciences – how to move from description to
prescription.) Identities form in historically grounded ways, but if some group
says ‘we wish to form a state,’ the practical response isn’t ‘No you don’t
because you aren’t historically situated.’ That’s like asking what’s the matter
with Kansas; you may wonder why people vote against their interests, but you
count their votes.
That’s why
I advocate a thin model – I believe in the rootedness of identity, but observe
that there’s no agreement on these things. Reasons matter, and reasons given
publicly matter even more. Kurds claiming statehood based on blood would elicit
one response; based on ballots, quite another.
My model
doesn’t “ban[] as illegitimate any acknowledgement of objective criteria of
membership. . .and any appeals based on historical grievances” (Lind). The
reasons people choose independence will be precisely those kinds of things. Thick
identity is allowed – expected; just not required. Groups can communicate their
desires through a clear vote on a clear question. (Catalan separatists have
been quite disciplined in making territorial arguments that leave out speakers
in Valencia, the Balearics, Andorra and France. They’re nationalists, not
idiots.)
A people
is more than an ephemeral numerical majority – but the way to show that is not
to bang on about one’s blood or Spartanness, but to win elections. Voting is a
mere moment, but everything that really matters – the blood and history and
money and pettiness and principle that engender identity and desires – are
present in the politics, the debate and the decision that moment represents. We
have no better.
My
argument is strategic, and Lind has discovered my intended audience: not
secessionists (who typically love me), but governments, policymakers and
intellectuals in that North Atlantic world so suspicious of them. They’re the
ones who need convincing.
4. And Historical Custom is Better than Liberal
Rules
Boxing Pandora proposes a
new rule – a new right. Tsai, Nicoletti, and Lind prefer tradition, socially
and historically grounded customs, thick with meaning, over thin liberalism and
codified, formal rights.
I agree. Law works better when it reflects and arises
out of pre-existing social understandings – when it “recognizes rights” (Tsai)
rather than conjuring them. I’d prefer
custom over codification. The problem is, we already codified the rules in 1945.
The norms and practices of territorial integrity produce a bleak negotiating
field for communities locked inside states. That isn’t the natural order – it’s
an artifact of a particular, quite recent design choice.
Similarly,
I’d prefer to entrench a practice of secession without the rigid language
of rights. But we already have a human rights regime – the other half of the
bargain struck in 1945 – and it’s the least implausible tool for making an
explicit break with existing norms and practice. (That’s precisely what rights
are good at.)
The
alternative to legal rights isn’t some genteel realm of custom and informed tradition.
I reach for ‘rules’ because the alternatives – Tsai’s “shows of strength” and Balkin’s
unmediated Melianism – are so brutal. De
facto practice and local traditions are formulae for suppression: Most states
have territorial integrity norms, explicit or implicit, so the domestic
machinery yields a predictable answer. In fact, as Spain shows, it makes things
worse, because unionists righteously point to legality as a reason to resist,
even though the legal order is the very thing being contested.
The rules
need to be thin because identities are thick. Lind wants a more useful guide to
“to how to think about the difficult relationship of ethnocultural nations to
territorial states in the contemporary world.” Me too. Someone should write it.
In
Part Two, we’ll turn to America.
Waters is professor at Indiana University
Maurer School of Law. You can reach him by e-mail at tiwaters@indiana.edu.
[1] Steve Martin, “The Death of Socrates,” Comedy
is Not Pretty (NBC: 14 February 1980), https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=RVc8jwYexjE.
Posted 1:30 PM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |