Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Presidential Elections in the House?
|
Saturday, May 09, 2020
Presidential Elections in the House?
Guest Blogger David Schwartz
Next week, in Colorado Dept. of State v. Baca, the Court will decide whether to invalidate state laws binding presidential electors. The “faithless electors” won their case in the Tenth Circuit based on an originalist argument. Since there is no obvious partisan advantage to either side of the case—both the Democratic and Republican parties have filed briefs opposing the faithless electors claim—the Court’s conservatives might relish the opportunity to showcase their “principled” originalism and hold that presidential electors have a constitutional right to vote for whomever they choose.
The faithless electors’ case focuses on the meaning of Article II, section 1, clause 2: “Each state shall appoint, in such manner as the Legislature thereof may direct, a number of electors…” The faithless electors argue in essence that “electors” means persons with full voting discretion so that the “manner” of appointment cannot include instructions on how to vote—for example, binding the electors to vote for the state’s popular vote winner, or, as the National Popular Vote Interstate Compact movement would have it, for the national popular vote winner.
In this post, I’ll first discuss the pragmatic side of the faithless electors case, and then the constitutional history. The best reading of the text, structure, and history of the Presidential Electors’ clauses, I believe, is that the majority of the Framers probably didn’t care whether electors were bound by state law or not, because they assumed that contested elections would usually end up in the House of Representatives either way.
The Pragmatic Side
The consolidated cases out of the Tenth Circuit (Baca) and Washington state (Chiafolo v. Washington) arose because three Democratic electors in each state tried to vote for prominent non-Trump Republicans rather than Hillary Clinton, the popular vote winner of both states. )The Coloradans voted for John Kasich, and the Washingtonians for Colin Powell.) This was apparently a coordinated effort by these electors to stop Donald Trump. Calling themselves “Hamiltonian,” because Hamilton argued in The Federalist No. 68 that electors should use their discretion to prevent demagogues from becoming president, these electors presumably hoped to set an irresistible example that would somehow persuade a sufficient number of Republican electors to vote for non-Trump Republicans as well.
Though well intentioned, the effort seems idiotic, both now and then. No sane person could have expected 264 Trump electors to switch to Kasich at the last minute to swing the election outright; the hope was apparently to throw the election into the House, by shifting at least 37 Trump electors thereby depriving him of a majority. But the House was controlled by Republicans. In the end, not a single Republican elector switched, which surprised no one, since the Republican Party had definitively closed ranks around Trump as soon as it became clear that GOP voters were sticking with him after the “Access Hollywood” video episode.
Intriguingly, lead counsel for the faithless electors is none other than Lawrence Lessig, who presumably hopes that unbound electors will stop Trump in 2020. It’s worth pausing to consider how that might work.
At present, 32 states plus the District of Columbia have laws binding electors in some manner to vote for the state’s electoral vote winner. The remaining states rely on party discipline to align electoral with popular vote.
A Court victory for the faithless electors will not by itself transform presidential elections into the purported “Hamiltonian” system of 538 electors free to vote their consciences. To be sure, such a decision would send a signal by judicially blessing elector discretion. Yet, throughout U.S. history, there have been only 180 or so “non-conforming” electoral votes, in which an elector voted against the state popular vote winner, even though state laws formally binding electors are a relatively recent development and have never been uniform throughout the states. Therefore, the most that could be reasonably expected from a faithless electors’ victory is that some small handful of electors will take the Court’s encouragement and cast non-conforming votes.
Then what? The “best case scenario” from the faithless electors’ point of view is that a Trump electoral majority would be thrown into the House. There, despite the Democrats’ current lead of 30+ seats, Republicans control majorities in 25 state delegations. (The Democrats control 24, with Michigan split.) Absent party cross-over votes, neither party would command a majority, so that no president would be chosen (see Amendment XX), resulting in a potential constitutional crisis, or, or a legitimacy crisis in the form of a Nancy Pelosi presidency with no template for whether or when to hold an interim presidential election. And of course it is always possible that a faithless elector scenario could snatch a victory away from the Democratic candidate. (Think of a handful of Bernie Sanders spoilers in a close election.)
Perhaps Lessig or others are pursuing a monkey-wrenching strategy: if the 2020 election is disastrous enough, it might spur a movement to amend the Constitution to adopt a straight popular vote system for the president. On the other hand, the faithless electors’ claim would preclude the other route to fix presidential elections, the National Popular Vote Interstate Compact.
Constitutional History and Interpretation
Given that the plain evolutionary trend in two centuries of presidential elections has been toward pledged or even bound electors, the argument that electors should vote their free and conscientious choices requires a reversion back to some “original meaning.” The originalist argument for faithless electors has both a linguistic and “structural” component.
The linguistic argument maintains that “elector” means someone free to vote his or her choice, as with “electors” for the House of Representatives (i.e., ordinary citizen-voters). An excellent rebuttal to that argument is found in John Vlahoplus’s essay demonstrating the indeterminacy of that language. Suffice to say here that the two conflicting interpretations are found in The Federalist essays themselves. Compare The Federalist No. 68 (Hamilton) (presidential electors would be those “most likely to possess the information and discernment requisite” to the “complicated” task of choosing the president) with The Federalist No. 39 (Madison) (asserting that the president would be elected “by the States in their political characters”).
As is often the case with originalist arguments in the era of “original public meaning” originalism, Framers’ intentions are smuggled into the presidential electors analysis under the rubric of “structural” arguments. Lessig’s lead brief for the faithless electors asserts that “The electoral college…. was crafted initially because the Framers did not want an executive dependent directly upon Congress nor upon the state governments.” (Consolidated Opening Brief for Presidential Electors, at 18.)
“Crafted” is hardly the right word for the patched-together compromise reached at the eleventh hour of the Philadelphia Convention—a compromise designed to accommodate three divergent views on presidential selection rather than to work well. But as long as we’re asking what “the Framers [did and] did not want,” let’s look at the odd drafting history of the Presidential Selection clauses and at the final approved language.
It’s true that some Framers did not want congressional election of the president, out of a concern for presidential independence, but many Framers preferred congressional election. In fact, wide majorities voted for congressional election multiple times. The Philadelphia Convention flip-flopped repeatedly between section by “the national legislature,” or by electors chosen by the state legislatures. On June 2, 1787, the Convention voted by eight states to two that the president should be elected by the national legislature for a non-renewable seven-year term, rejecting unanimously James Wilson’s motion for direct popular election of the president. A week later, the Convention strongly reaffirmed that view, voting 9-0 to reject a motion to elect the president by the decision of the states’ governors. Returning to the topic on July 17, the Convention, by an 8-2 majority, rejected a motion by Maryland delegate Luther Martin that the president should be selected by electors chosen by the legislature of each state. Two days later the Convention flip-flopped, deciding by a 6-3 margin that the president should be chosen by electors “appointed” by the state legislatures. But the next week, on July 23, the Convention voted 7-3 to reconsider this decision. After two further days of debate, on July 26, the Convention flip-flopped again, reinstating by a 6-3 vote the decision to have the president chosen by the national legislature. That resolution was incorporated into the Committee of Detail Report on August 6.
The Convention turned back to presidential selection on August 24. The delegates again rejected Wilson’s renewed motion for direct popular election, as well as a motion to elect the president “by electors chosen by the people of the several states,” and reaffirmed selection by the national legislature. But the Convention bogged down on the details of how Congress would choose the president: would it be by ballot (i.e., by the legislators voting as individuals) or by state? Would the House and Senate vote separately, or jointly? With these difficulties, the question was turned over to the Committee on Postponed Parts, which reported on September 4 with the provision that was ultimately ratified—except that the Convention replaced the Senate with the House as the body that would choose the president in the event that no candidate had an electoral majority.
The flip-flopping was undoubtedly due in part to the fact that at least some delegates linked the selection method with the president’s term of office and his eligibility for more than one term. For example, the June 2 resolution specified that the president would be chosen by the national legislature for a single seven-year term. As the presidential term of office and re-eligibility were moving targets during the Convention debates, some delegates’ views of the best selection system may have shifted as well. (Since neither the Convention Journal nor any delegates’ notes broke out the individual votes, we can’t answer this question.)
But the numerous votes approving congressional selection of the president make it unlikely that a majority of delegates insisted that the election system bolster presidential independence from Congress. The final version of Article II, section 1, clause 2 represented, not a rejection of congressional involvement in presidential selection, but a compromise between the congressional selection camp and the state electors camp—with a nod even to the popular election fringe-- though leaning ultimately toward the congressionalists.
Article II, section 1, clause 2 provides: “if no person have a majority, then from the five highest on the list” of candidates receiving electoral votes “the said House shall in like manner choose the President.” The five … highest? Today, it is inconceivable that more than two or three candidates would receive any electoral votes. But the Framers apparently anticipated that there could be more than five, and that that scenario would occur with sufficient frequency to provide for it expressly.
This is consistent with the view of many historians, that the Framers predicted that most contested elections would wind up in the House. Except in those cases where a single great man, like Washington, would be elected more or less by acclamation, the Framers likely believed that presidential elections would be non-partisan free-for-alls in which each state would nominate its favorite son. Their concern about favorite sons is evident in their ill-conceived provision giving each elector two votes for president, requiring one to be cast for a candidate from outside the elector’s own state. That provision, by failing to account for disciplined national parties, produced a tie as Jeffersonian electors dutifully cast their two votes for Jefferson and Aaron Burr, and was partially patched up by the Twelfth Amendment. But the Amendment nevertheless carried forward the Framers’ version of the House’s role, a role that the Framers most likely believed would be substantial, and the electors’ role marginal, rather than the other way around. If that is the case, then the Framers would have had little incentive to clarify the relationship between the electors and their respective state legislatures.
The election that most closely approximated the “Framers design” was that of 1824. With no viable opposition party in existence—thus approximating the Framers’ expectation that there would be no political parties--the four Jeffersonian Republican party leaders vied for the mantle of the presidency: Secretary of State John Quincy Adams, Secretary of War John C. Calhoun, Treasury Secretary William Crawford, and House Speaker Henry Clay. A fifth candidate, Tennessee favorite son Andrew Jackson, ran as a Washington outsider and won a popular and electoral vote plurality. But no candidate won a majority, and the election was thrown into the House where a deal was struck between Adams and Clay that swung the election to Adams. The result was a legitimacy crisis—fomented by Jackson supporters who decried the “corrupt bargain” that ended with Clay appointed Secretary of State—that undermined Adams’s presidency. Another unintended consequence of the Framers’ presidential election system working as designed.
The Framers’ strongly anti-democratic leanings—James Wilson’s two motions for direct popular election of the president never won the support of a single state delegation—together with their failure to account for the eminently foreseeable rise of political parties, produced a terrible presidential election system. It was only the evolution of state laws binding electors and of political party discipline that has refashioned the framers presidential election system into something even remotely tolerable in a democracy. The evolved form of presidential elections has kept the vast majority of elections away from the House, where whose presidential voting rules are far greater departures from “one-person, one vote” than the Electoral College. In the Electoral College, Wyoming’s voting strength as a function of population compared to California’s is 3.7-to-1. In the House of Representatives, where each state delegation gets just one vote for president, that disparity becomes 68-to 1.
The purported Hamiltonian system of unbound electors is neither a clear original meaning nor a system that existed in practice: as early as the first genuinely contested election in 1796, electors were already beginning to vote by party rather than by individual discretion. A Supreme Court decision to “restore” that system will either make no difference in presidential elections, or make them worse.
David S. Schwartz is Foley & Lardner-Bascom Professor of Law at the University of Wisconsin Law School. You can reach him by e-mail at dsschwartz at wisc.edu
Posted 9:30 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |