Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Does Importance Equal Greatness? Reflections on John Marshall and McCulloch v. Maryland
|
Friday, November 15, 2019
Does Importance Equal Greatness? Reflections on John Marshall and McCulloch v. Maryland
Sandy Levinson
For the symposium on David S. Schwartz, The Spirit of the Constitution: John Marshall and the 200-Year Odyssey of McCulloch v. Maryland (Oxford University Press, 2019).
I was happy to contribute the following blurb for this excellent book:
“David Schwartz has written an indispensable study of the single most important Supreme Court case in the canon. As such, he delineates not only the meaning the importance of the case in 1819, but also the use made of it over the next two centuries as it becomes a central myth and symbol of the very meaning of American constitutionalism.”
I meant every word of it. It is indispensable, which means, as with earlier books that have been the subject of Balkinization symposia, such as those by Jonathan Gienapp or Michael Klarman, that it not only deserves to be read, but really must be read by anyone wishing to be truly literate in the subject of American constitutional law and its development over time. Jack and I published an essay in the Harvard Law Review some two decades ago about the various “canons in constitutional law,” where we distinguished among what we called the “pedagogical,” “cultural literacy,” and “contemporary constitutional theory” canons. That is, cases that legal academics choose to teach as part of introductory courses—or place in casebooks designed to initiate students into the study of constitutional law—may or may not register even in the memories of professional lawyers, let alone even well-educated laity. They are irrelevant to the actual practice of law and rarely, if ever, come up in general conversation so that it might prove embarrassing not to be aware of a case. And, separately, there are cases that are indeed well known that rarely, if ever, appear as the central focus of sophisticated treatments of constitutional theory, just as the cases that do appear in such articles may be, as a practical matter, both untaught in introductory courses and sufficiently esoteric that even a fully competent lawyer would be forgiven ignorance of the case in question.
Consider the chestnut case of Marbury v. Madison, surely part of the cultural literacy canon but otherwise, I believe, justifiably ignored. I have achieved a certain notoriety by refusing to teach Marbury, which I consider basically a waste of students’ valuable time in comparison with other cases—my stock example is Prigg v. Pennsylvania—that I think are far more important for students to grapple with. No one cares about the actual legal issue raised in Marbury—whether Congress can add to the original jurisdiction of the Supreme Court; it is not relevant to any contemporary litigation, nor, as a matter of fact, does Marbury truly feature as the centerpiece of contemporary articles on constitutional theory, including, for that matter, the propriety of judicial review. No one who believes in modern judicial review is truly convinced by Marshall’s arguments, and those persuaded by his rhetoric can find themselves quite critical of the contemporary Court. Given that Marbury is part of the cultural literacy canon, I usually did take literally five minutes to mention it to students before moving on to something I consider far more important for their education.
What is distinctive about McCulloch v. Maryland is that a full two centuries after its decision it remains part of all three canons. It is the only case, for example, that is printed unedited in the casebook that Jack and I co-edit, along with Akhil Amar and Reva Siegel, and I have conducted courses at both Harvard and the University of Texas in which the case was read aloud—and discussed—in its entirety over a twelve to fifteen hour period of classes. Perhaps that may be thought excessive, but I certainly know of no teacher of an introductory course—or editor of a casebook—who ignores the case. Eight years ago, when visiting the Yale Law School and teaching an introductory constitutional law course, I spent my usual several weeks on McCulloch and explained to the students that I fully expected it to intensely discussed in the Supreme Court’s much anticipated decision in the Obamacare case that came down in 2012. I was relieved, but not surprised, when my expectations were fully met. The discussion of the meaning of the Necessary and Proper Clause was as angry and disputatious in 2012 as it was in 1819, when James Madison, who had, after all, signed the Bill establishing the Second Bank of the United States, wrote Spencer Roane of Virginia that the Constitution never would have been ratified in 1787-88 had delegates to the various conventions realized that the Clause would take on the meaning assigned to it by Chief Justice Marshall. “Necessary,” as we all know, turned out to mean “convenient” or “useful,” with attendant liberation, as it were, of congressional lawmakers, a proposition that can still engender heated argument today.
To be sure, and this is an important theme of Schwartz’s book, that is not the only message one can take from the opinion. As is true of most of the canonical opinions, one can find mixed messages and, therefore, develop conflicting doctrines that ostensibly follow from the valorized opinions. For reasons that I literally do not understand, Marshall chose to begin his opinion by referring to Maryland as a “sovereign state,” which it most clearly is not, but there can be little doubt that by doing this he ended up giving aid and comfort to an anti-nationalist form of federalism that he was adamantly opposed to. Similarly, he writes fairly early on that “[t]his government is acknowledged by all to be one of enumerated powers,” which provides for many the basis of the proposition that the national government possesses only these “enumerated powers” rather than “at least” what is written down. (Richard Primus is writing what will be an equally indispensable book designed to lay to rest this commonplace conception that is all too often left unexamined, in part, perhaps, because Marshall is thought to have said it.)
If Paragraph 38 of the opinion—"Let the end be legitimate, let it be within the scope of the constitution, and all means which are appropriate, which are plainly adapted to that end, which are not prohibited, but consist with the letter and spirit of the constitution, are constitutional”—is often interpreted basically to license Congress to do whatever it wishes, then Paragraph 42, obviously only a few lines later, promises that the Court will monitor overreaching by a Congress that uses reference to assigned powers as only a “pretext” for what is not properly within that ambit. “Should congress, … under the pretext of executing its powers, pass laws for the accomplishment of objects not intrusted to the government; it would become the painful duty of this tribunal, should a case requiring such a decision come before it, to say, that such an act was not the law of the land.” Not surprisingly, almost every lawyer educated since 1942 knows Paragraph 38 because it was cited so often to justify the New Deal and to stave off accusations that Roosevelt's policies were "revolutionary" (at least in constitutional terms). It is worth noting that Bruce Ackerman's important rendering of the the New Deal as a "constitutional moment" amending the Constitution outside Article V in effect requires ignoring, or at least diminishing the relevance, of McCulloch.
As Marshall himself writes, a constitution is “designed to endure” and not to emulate, say, the “imbecilic” Articles of Confederation, which proved inefficacious; this necessarily means that the United States Constitution must be “adapted to the various crises of human affairs” rather than read as trapping us inside a collective iron cage that prohibits even the possibility of mastering these crises. In any event, it should be clear beyond dispute that McCulloch is of almost unique importance on its 200th anniversary even if, as Schwartz demonstrates, it was in fact often ignored. Therefore that any book delving as deeply into its history and later impact as Schwartz’s does will therefore be what the late Anthony Lewis described as “an event in the law.”
All of this being said, I confess that I do find myself, partly as the result of the stimulation of reading Schwartz’s book, more and more wondering whether McCulloch’s truly undeniable “importance” translates into its being as well a “great opinion” that establishes Marshall as a uniquely “great judge.” Why, after all, is he often referred to as the Great Chief Justice? Oliver Wendell Holmes gave a famously snarky address on “John Marshall Day” in 1901, celebrating the 100thanniversary of his appointment as one of John Adams’s “midnight judges” to the federal judiciary as presumed guardians against the Jeffersonian menace about to take power. What Holmes was willing to say, was that, like other ostensibly great men, Marshall "represented a great ganglion in the nerves of society"; he had the great advantage of being present at "a strategic point in the campaign of history, and part of his greatness consists in his being there." This is obviously very different from saying, for example, that his greatness consisted in his providing a role model for future judges or even that his opinions were necessarily persuasive, let alone convincing, on further reading.
Marshall was a rhetorical genius, but this is inevitably a mixed compliment once one sees through some of the rhetoric, including the presuppositions that are smuggled into the opinions and are, by the very nature of presuppositions, assumed rather than argued for. We know from one of the classic critiques of rhetoric, Plato’s Gorgias dialogue, that the acid test for the skilled rhetor is to make “the lesser appear the greater,” to persuade listeners that what is “in fact” the weaker argument is better than its challenger. To mention only undiscussed presuppositions, consider, for example, his declaration that the United States was destined to reach the Pacific Ocean and become a great empire in its own right, which necessitated (especially if one had a lax definition of “necessity”) congressional power to charter a bank (and, of course, much else). If one did not share such imperial ambitions, one might be satisfied to tend one’s garden, but that is never on offer, as it were.
Moreover, Marshall might have upheld the Bank on any one of multiple arguments: To name only three, in addition to the one he offered, he could have engaged in the equivalent of independent review and determined that there was indeed what we would today call a “compelling interest” demonstrating the “necessity” under a rigorous definition of chartering the Bank. Or, somewhat different would have been a review of the congressional debate regarding the Bank and the determination that, as with modern administrative agencies, Congress had indeed given a “hard look” at the cases for and against a Bank and, using the correct standard of rigorous “necessity,” determined that the General Welfare really would be enhanced by establishing a Second Bank after the lapse of the First Bank. Or, as Eric Lomazoff has argued in his own recent book Reconstructing the National Bank Controversy, he could have adopted the argument actually proffered by Madison and his allies, which is the propriety of the Bank under the Coinage Clause of Article I, something Marshall simply ignored in his desire to offer a far broader, Hamiltonian, reading of the Constitution. One reason that McCulloch repays close reading is precisely that Marshall is such a clever rhetorician. Watching him perform is a bit like observing a master of intellectual three-card monte. One might think one is following the moves and, therefore, can locate the ace, but one is almost always wrong unless one can slow down the action and observe the various feints and deceptions.
Is Schwartz’s book “definitive”? The answer is no, and not simply for the same reason that one can no more write a truly “definitive” study of McCulloch than one can of King Lear, especially if one is interested not only in what Shakespeare might have been thinking, but also in the historical reception of the play through the decades. After all, for almost a century, apparently, Cordelia lived, because it was just too sad to accept her cruel and unjustified death. Who knows what the future might bring with regard to directors “revisioning” the play? Cordelia might still die, but perhaps Regan and Goneril will be re-imagined as protofeminists in justified revolt against an almost stereotypically patriarchal tyrant. Richard Rorty once defined intellectual history as a process by which ostensible “interpreters” took culturally authoritative texts and “beat them” into forms that would be useful for new arguments in new settings. Whether or not that describes the history of philosophy, it is surely accurate with regard to the use of legal arguments in the development of legal doctrines. Lawyers are rhetors, committed not to some Dworkinian notion of “the right answer" but, rather, to presenting whatever arguments are thought to enhance the interests of one’s client. Judges may not have clients in a standard sense, but, as Jack and I have also argued, they do have distinct visions of what we call “high politics” as to what will best serve the interests of the United States—or perhaps the institutional interests of the Court itself, as in Marbury—and the arguments are crafted accordingly.
But there is one other major reason beyond the inability to foretell the future that Schwartz’s book, however truly invaluable, nonetheless has its limits: Like almost all modern treatments of McCulloch,it concentrates almost exclusively on what professionals have come to call McCulloch I, that is, the first 45 paragraphs of the opinion that uphold congressional power to charter the Bank. That is, to be sure, the part of the opinion that is of overwhelming importance, for good or for ill, in our world today. But McCulloch I is immediately followed by 30 paragraphs of McCulloch II, in which the lack of Maryland’s alleged “sovereignty,” proclaimed in the very first sentence, is made clear inasmuch as the Court invalidates the state’s attempt to tax the Bank on the basis of what Marshall identifies as the “texture” of the Constitution rather than anything in the text or even demonstrable history that might support the invalidation. For example, he rather ruthlessly dismisses the relevance of Federalist #32,in which Hamilton fully recognizes that the concurrent powers of both states and the national government to engage in taxation would almost inevitably create conflict; Hamilton appeared to suggest that such conflict would (and should) be resolved politically. There was not an iota of a suggestion that the conflict would be “legalized” and made the subject of cases to be settled by the federal judiciary. Instead, Marshall reached out to assert a significant new realm of judicial power. McCulloch I can be cited as an example of extreme "judicial restraint," whereas McCulloch II is just the opposite.
Moreover, Marshall justifies his conclusion that Maryland is without the power to tax the Bank of the United States by rhetorically presupposing that the Bank is unequivocally an instrument of the national government, akin, say, to an army base or the national Capitol. Not once, though, does he ever deign to inform the reader that the Bank is what we would today describe as a joint venture between the U.S., which owned 20 percent of the stock, and private investors who owned the other 80 percent. When vetoing the renewal of the Bank's charter in 1832, Andrew Jackson would make this a central point. But Monroe’s Secretary of the Treasury years earlier had made it clear to the president of the Bank, in a private letter, that his first loyalties should be to the private shareholders. As it happens, I will be delivering the Salmon P. Chase Lecture next month before the Supreme Court Historical Society that will examine in detail the problems with McCulloch II. Suffice it to say that there is little in that part of the opinion that should commend it to someone today looking for a model of “great” judging even if we put to one side the brute fact that no judges today write in what Karl Llewellyn identified as the “Grand Style,” substituting instead endless (and tedious) exercises in purported analysis of precedents (as against Marshall’s willingness to ignore almost completely any existing precedents).
Posted 9:30 AM by Sandy Levinson [link]
Comments:
Gerard Magliocca, who is cited in the book, would be an interesting addition to this discussion given his first two books, particularly "Andrew Jackson and the Constitution: The Rise and Fall of Generational Regimes."
I checked with Prof. Eric Segall -- who blogs at Dorf on Law -- and he flagged this article on teaching Marbury http://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1349&context=jcl
Post a Comment
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |