Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts John Locke, Justice Gorsuch, and Gundy v. United States
|
Monday, July 22, 2019
John Locke, Justice Gorsuch, and Gundy v. United States
Richard Primus
An earlier post
on this blog by Mark Tushnet explained that Justice Gorsuch’s dissent in Gundy v. United States, which fires a loud
shot across the bow of the administrative state, contained something like a
fictionalized account of the facts behind Schechter
Poultry. In Gorsuch’s presentation, the
Schechters were caught between the regulatory demands of the New Deal and their
own religious commitments. “Kosher
butchers such as the Schechters,” Gorsuch wrote, “had a hard time following
these rules. Yet the government
apparently singled out the Schechters as a test case[.]” In other words, the Schechters were victims
of the government’s failure to accommodate their religious beliefs. Worse yet, the government deliberately went
after them, the people whose
violations arose for religious reasons.
But as Tushnet explains, none of this is true. Nothing about the Schechters’ violations of
the New Deal’s Codes of Fair Competition arose from any need to comply with the
rules for kosher butchering. For the
details, I highly recommend Tushnet’s
post.
It’s
not hard to see why the fictionalized version of Schechter would be appealing to Gorsuch, who has both a skeptical
view of administrative governance and a robust view of the accommodations that
government should make for religious believers.
But one ought also to presume that Gorsuch would not tell the story of Schechter this way if he knew it to be
false. The opinion-writing sin here,
I’ll stipulate, is more likely confirmation bias than deliberate distortion:
someone (Gorsuch cites the writer Amity Shlaes as his source) offered an
account of Schechter that was
congenial to Gorsuch’s views, and Gorsuch accepted it without sufficient
interrogation. That fallacious account now
appears in the U.S. Reports as if it were factual.
I
rehearse all this as prologue to pointing out a second and likely similar problem
in Gorsuch’s Gundy opinion. This second problem is about John Locke, the
Founders, and the separation of powers. Unlike
the hiccup about the Schechters, which is a matter of atmospherics at the
periphery of Gorsuch’s opinion, Gorsuch’s treatment of Locke is part of his
animating substantive argument. It
contributes directly to Gorsuch’s case for the proposition that broad
legislative delegations to administrative agencies are at odds with the
Constitution.
Part I
of Gorsuch’s dissent is introductory. In
Part II, Gorsuch builds his theory about nondelegation from the fundamentals of
constitutional argument, going back to the text and the Founding. In the third paragraph of his account, by way
of explaining how the Framers thought about the separation of powers, Gorsuch quotes
a passage a bit more than a hundred words long from John Locke’s Second Treatise of Government. Locke was not a Framer of the Constitution:
he lived in the wrong century and also in the wrong hemisphere. But Gorsuch nonetheless confidently presents
the passage from Locke as a statement of the “particular arrangement” on which
the “framers insist[ed].” Locke, says
Gorsuch, was “one of the thinkers who most influenced the framers’ understanding
of the separation of powers[.]”
Was he
really? Gorsuch’s dissent, which has a
hundred and seven footnotes, cites no authority for the proposition that Locke shaped
the dominant Founding conception of the separation of powers. Other than his say-so, Gorsuch gives the
reader no reason to think that the Framers meant to erect just the system of
separated powers that Locke articulated in this quoted passage, written a
hundred years before and three thousand miles away. And there is serious reason to doubt that the
Framers had any particular commitment to following Locke on the point. Locke was, to be sure, an influential thinker
in the English-speaking world during the eighteenth century: there’s a famous
phrase in the Declaration of Independence that sure seems like a riff on his
work. But the fact that Jefferson riffed
on Locke in the Declaration does not mean that Locke was pervasively
influential in the formation of the Constitution.
For
several decades now, leading scholars have cast considerable doubt on the idea
that Locke’s political writing was particularly influential for the Founders. (John Dunn and Mark Goldie are good examples,
and what follows in this paragraph largely tracks their work.) As a general matter, Locke’s high reputation
as a philosopher in the first century after he wrote was mostly a function of
his non-political work, especially his Essay
Concerning Human Understanding.
Pro-independence Americans seem to have become significantly more
interested in the Two Treatises of
Government in the decade leading up to 1776, and it isn’t hard to
understand why an argument by a renowned English philosopher that could be used
to justify political revolution would have seemed attractive to that population
at that moment. But once independence
was achieved, American interest in Locke seems to have declined
precipitously. When the project at hand
was constructing a working government rather than rebelling against one,
Americans looked elsewhere. In this
connection Goldie cites Duncan Forbes, who
remarked about Locke that it is inappropriate to build a theory of marriage
upon the occasional necessity of divorce.
In short, even if Locke was influential in the 1770s, he does not seem
to have been a major influence in the formation of the Constitution. Gorsuch’s opinion does nothing to meet, or
even acknowledge, the accordingly problematic nature of turning to Locke as an
explicator of the Framers’ ideas.
The
choice to use Locke as a guide to the Framers’ ideas about the separation of
powers in particular is perhaps more problematic still. Even if one is unaware of the historiography
about the relationship between Locke’s various works and Americans in different
decades of the eighteenth century, a reader of Locke’s political writings
should realize that Locke’s view of the separation of powers differed in basic
ways from the scheme embodied by the Constitution. This isn’t a subtle point: Locke and the
Founders used different categories to describe the powers that are distributed
among institutions of government. The
Constitution distributes legislative, executive, and judicial powers. Locke didn’t think in those terms. He described the distribution of legislative,
executive, and federative powers—“federative”
powers being, basically, the powers of foreign affairs. Locke and the Founders also disagreed about
who should exercise some important specific powers within those general
categories. In Locke’s view, foreign
affairs (that is, “federative”) powers should be lodged in the same place as executive
power, even though the two kinds of power are conceptually distinct. The Constitution, of course, divides what
Locke would have recognized as the national government’s federative powers
between the President (who is commander-in-chief of the military, and who receives
ambassadors) and Congress (which declares war and regulates commerce with
foreign nations). None of this is to say
that the Framers’ views of the separation of powers was wholly different from
Locke’s. But it is odd to claim that a
thinker who didn’t even use the categories legislative, executive, and judicial
to carve up a government’s power is also a thinker whose writings specify the
view of the separation of powers on which the framers particularly insisted. The org chart of the separation of powers articulated
in Locke’s Second Treatise is not the
org chart that the Constitution established.
The
link between this problem and the Schechter
Poultry problem should be clear enough.
I do not wish to charge Gorsuch with deliberately misrepresenting the relationship
between Locke and the Framers. I think
it likely that Gorsuch found a passage in Locke that articulated a view
congenial to the one he was pressing in Gundy
and, perhaps from a general sense that Locke was an important thinker, helped
himself in good faith to the inference that Locke’s view on the point was also
the view animating the Framers at Philadelphia.
But as with Schechter, what
results is a distortion. And this time,
it is a distortion that claims the authority of the Founders for a call to
remake American law in a pretty significant way.
Everyone
makes mistakes. And there is nothing new
about Supreme Court Justices handling historical materials badly. But one might hope that Gorsuch would strive
to handle them with care. He is, after
all, prominently committed to the originalist view that the content of the law
today is importantly determined by historical facts from long ago. If so, he should insist on getting the
history right.
Many originalists, Gorsuch included,
claim that one virtue of originalism is its capacity to generate legal rules
that do not depend on the views of the decisionmakers. (Not all originalists claim this, but many
do, and Gorsuch is one of them.) In
practice, however, originalist interpretation tends to feature judges reading
historical sources to mean what those judges would like the sources to mean. Some originalists hold out hope that judges
can learn to handle historical materials better than most judges have in the
past, and more than a few people think that Gorsuch might become an exemplar of
such a better way. His choice to write
an opinion with more than a hundred footnotes suggests an aspiration of that
kind, or at least a consciousness of the virtues of being well-grounded in the
sources. But if Gorsuch is to vindicate
originalism against the charge that in practice originalism tends to function
as a vehicle for the preferences of the interpreter, he will need to be more
careful—perhaps in particular, more inclined to think critically about whether
the sources actually support his preferred positions—than he seems to have been
in Gundy.
Posted 11:27 AM by Richard Primus [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |