E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
This is a much belated comment on Jonathan Gienapp’s truly marvelous work
TheSecond Creation: Fixing the American Constitution in the Founding
Era.I regret that I couldn’t
participate in the Balkinization symposium last fall.Reading back through Gienapp’s book and the
symposium made me think I could usefully add a few points.
Reading through the Balkinization posts one could be forgiven for
thinking that Gienapp wrote a book about the relation between the adoption of
the Constitution and originalism.The
book may certainly have implications in that quarter.But that’s not the major import of this
analytically precise work that dives deep into the origins of the American
constitutional tradition.A scholarly
work like Gienapp’s is long overdue.I
wish that it had existed when I was writing my first book, American
Constitutionalism: From Theory toPolitics.True, Gienapp’s material is mostly familiar.Scholars like Larry Kramer and Sylvia Snowiss
have previously advanced ideas that are similar in some ways.But the angle Gienapp takes and his
comprehensive approach to familiar material creates a new conceptual space for approaching
how the Constitution came to be understood in the early republic.
There are three important strands to Gienapp’s narrative.
First, in invoking the constituent power of
the people to enact a single-document constitution that had the status of
supreme law, the founding generation was doing something completely
unfamiliar. I don’t think this point can
be emphasized enough and there are still far too many scholars who fail to
recognize its significance. Although the
Constitution had the form of a written law, at the same time it could not be easily
analogized or reduced to any other kind of legal enactment. This made the nature of the Constitution
inherently problematic, making it difficult to grasp what the Constitution
really “was.” Nonetheless, as I argue in
American Constitutionalism, this did not prevent subsequent generations
of American lawyers from trying to “legalize” the Constitution by doing what
the founding generation tried consciously to avoid – namely, collapsing its
status down to that of an “ordinary,” albeit foundational law. Every time the Constitution’s “essential”
character is invoked, for example, in analyses that stress its “writtenness,” (or
think about every time you have read “after all, the Constitution is a kind of
statute”), we are making the very mistake the founders tried to avoid.
Avoid, that is, until Congress hit the first series of policy disputes in
which the Constitution could be arguably implicated.Here Gienapp throws a sharper than normal light
on the constitutionalization of American politics.The phenomenon is familiar, but again
Gienapp’s angle of attack is different.He discusses the inherent tension that results from on the one hand treating
the Constitution as the arena in which governmental action takes place as
contrasted with using the Constitution to influence or even dictate the terms
of policy debate.It certainly seems
natural to press the Constitution into service to support or condemn policy
proposals.But this can cut against the advantages
of having the Constitution serve as a relatively apolitical framework for
government.Gienapp’s narrative forces
us to ask the question of whether the concept of a framework Constitution is compatible
with its being treated as a political trophy.
Finally, Gienapp shows persuasively that the idea of the fixed
Constitution as a textual, “archival” document was itself contingent on a
historical process.So things could have
been different.This is something to keep
in mind in a time when the original public meaning approach seems to be encouraging
(as Victoria Nourse argued in a recent fascinating lecture she gave at Tulane
and elsewhere) an intense textual reductionism – what John Hart Ely called a
“clause-bound” approach.Yet this is exactly
what many framers, influential Federalists included, repeatedly warned against
when they doubted the utility of written fixity by condemning reliance on
“parchment barriers.”We need to remind
ourselves of the relevance of a holistic, structural approach to the
Constitution that keeps its purpose and design elements firmly in view.Such an approach was very much on display
during the founding as Gienapp shows and, as Mark Graber demonstrates in his
article “Constructing Constitutional Politics,” during Reconstruction as well.
This is by way of saying that in contrast to some of the symposium
participants, I see a number of significant similarities between the “older”
originalism of original intention and the “newer” originalism that stresses the original meanings of the legal text.Although an inquiry into intentions could in
theory range more widely, both views focus on the text.Both are centered around what amounts to a
rational reconstruction of the past rather than facing the historical messiness
of the clash of views at the founding and during Reconstruction.And in part to deal with this messiness, both
inherently involve the exclusion of evidence that historians, at least, (and
possibly lawyers too!) would find relevant to assessing what was achieved in
both periods through formal constitutional change.There is also a difference, but it does not
necessarily work to the advantage of the original meaning perspective.It has more recently become clear that the avoidance
of “subjectivity” in the original meaning approach means that it can generate
interpretations that not only did not occur to anyone during the founding, but
arguably could not have occurred. Yet originalists
are presenting this as an advantage of their point of view rather than
something that’s deeply problematic from a sound historical perspective.All
of this is pretty telegraphic, but I hope to elaborate on these points in a forthcoming
article on Reconstruction and perhaps in some future posts this summer.