E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
What Bond, Pom Wonderful, and Abramski Have In Common: The Enduring Mystery of the Canons of Statutory Interpretation
Abbe Gluck
Before the
final cases of the Term overtake us, it is worth pausing a moment on the connection
shared by three cases handed down earlier this month, each about radically different
subjects, but giving rise to the same misunderstandings about statutory interpretation: Bond
(about the reach of the Chemical Weapons Convention Implementation Act to a wife's attempt to injure her husband’s lover); Pom Wonderful (a deceptive labeling
dispute between two drink makers); and Abramski(about the straw purchase of
firearms).
In each
of these cases, the Court considered well-worn interpretive principles to get it
out of the interpretive jam—the federalism canon in Bond; the harmonization
canon in Pom Wonderful; and the rule of lenity in Abramski.What is surprising about the cases is that
they have, in fact, surprised anyone, as they have, given how utterly common these principles are. Also noteworthy is the way in which Court itself
in these cases seems to be having a much more explicit debate about the nature of these
presumptions and what triggers them it typically does.
Start
with Bond. Some commentators wereeagerly anticipating a major foreign
affairs/treaty power opinion. Instead, many were aghast that the Court avoided the hard constitutional questions raised by the case by applying a mundane principle of statutory interpretation. Others were even more infuriated that the Court allegedly “invented” the interpretive principle that it used for this case.
Commentators (see, e.g., this piece in the National Review) cheered on Justice Scalia for opposing application of this brand new "federalism
presumption”—the rule that ambiguous federal statutes be construed not to
intrude on traditional state domains.In
fact, that principle is neither new, nor does Justice Scalia oppose it.The principle is a first-cousin of the
presumption against preemption (which has been around at least since the 1930s)
and was itself announced in Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U.S. 452 (1991)(joined by Justice Scalia) and applied in
case after case since then.The canon is
so common that not teaching it would be malpractice in any statutory
interpretation course. The worlds of statutory interpretation and constitutional law are too inextricably intertwined at this point for any Court-watchers to be surprised about the existence of these interpretive presumptions or their decisive power in major, constitutional-law-implicating cases.
What
Justice Scalia was objecting to was not the canon's existence but what triggers
it. His argument was that the statute was not sufficiently ambiguous to
trigger the canon's application.That’s the important doctrinal question that comes out of the Court's opinion—whether
federalism or any of the other 100 common policy presumptions of statutory interpretation—require
ambiguity to trigger them or whether they can swoop in, armed with the mantle
of quasi-constitutional law, even if the text is clear.
Abramski
raises the same exact issue, in the opposite presentation. This time it was
Justice Scalia who was arguing for the application of a canon—there, the rule of
lenity.But the majority (through
Justice Kagan this time) clarified the
statute for itself using other tools—this time, statutory history and
purpose—and so did not need the rule of lenity.Like Bond, this is a fight about when
the many different interpretive presumptions that are already in play apply in any individual
case. As I have previously elaborated, the Court remains woefully
inconsistent about these matters.Justice Scalia himself recently co-authored a 500-page treatise that
passes judgment on many of the canons but fails to discuss any system of
applying them, any way to make their application more consistent or even what they are.Most commentators (not I) emphatically resist the idea that these interpretive
presumptions are some kind of judge-made law (indeed, that feeling is part of
what isdriving the outrage about Bond).But anyone following these cases should question
whether it can really be said anymore (if it ever could have been said) that
these rules are not deciding cases, are not in fact judicial creations and are
not precedential.The canons of
constitutional avoidance, lenity, federalism and many more decided not only
these cases but also the vast majority of statutory cases ranging from the
health reform case to the Enron case. Isn’t it time to reevaluate their legal status and
their importance?
A brief word about Pom Wonderful.
Writing for the majority, Justice Kennedy framed the case as resting on a potential
conflict between the Lanham Act and the Federal Food, Drug and Cosmetic Act.As he described it (internal citations omitted):
"[T]his
is a statutory interpretation case and the Court relies on traditional rules of
statutory interpretation. That does not change because the case involves multiple
federal statutes. Nor does it change because an agency is
involved. Analysis of the statutory text, aided by established
principles of interpretation, controls.
A principle of interpretation is “often countered, of
course, by some maxim pointing in a different direction.” It is thus
unsurprising that in this case a threshold dispute has arisen as to which of
two competing maxims establishes the proper framework for decision. POM argues
that this case concerns whether one statute, the FDCA as amended, is an
“implied repeal” in part of another statute, i.e., the Lanham Act. POM
contends that in such cases courts must give full effect to both statutes
unless they are in “irreconcilable conflict”... Coca-Cola resists this canon and its high
standard. Coca-Cola argues that argues that the case concerns whether a more
specific law, the FDCA, clarifies or narrows the scope of a more general law. The Court’s task, it claims, is to “reconcil[e]”
the laws...."
The
Court does not need to resolve this dispute. Even assuming that Coca-Cola is
correct that the Court’s task is to reconcile or harmonize the statutes and
not, as POM urges, to enforce both statutes in full unless there is a genuinely
irreconcilable conflict, Coca-Cola is incorrect that the best way to harmonize
the statutes is to bar POM’s Lanham Act claim." Slip at. 8-9.
What is so bizarre about
Pom Wonderful, and the reason I include it in this post, is first, that Justice
Kennedy begins the opinion with an almost elementary lesson in statutory
interpretation—noting that conflict between canons is typical, and that "traditional
canons" (whatever those are!) control in all statutory cases regardless of how many federal statutes
or federal parties are involved. This seems
to be quite a basic statement for the Court to feel compelled to make, and one it should not need to make in
an era in which the vast majority of cases the Court decides involve one or more federal
statutes and the potential application of the canons. Even so, and this is the
second puzzling aspect of Pom Wonderful, Justice Kennedy then completely avoids
answering the very question he presented--namely, how we are to resolve the recurring issue of
canon conflict. Instead, he adopts a purposive and functional approach that
discounts the canons altogether—but, really, implicitly favors the rule of
interpretation preferred by Pom Wonderful.
Where
are we in the so-called “statutory interpretation wars”? Commentators for years
have been arguing that the big fights between textualism and purposivsm are
over. That may be true when it comes to questions about those two interpretive philosophies, but, as this Term
has showed us, we have a long way to go before we arrive at any kind of doctrinal stability, much less a coherent approach to the endeavor.