Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts A Conversation with Clark Neily about Judicial Engagement
|
Monday, October 21, 2013
A Conversation with Clark Neily about Judicial Engagement
JB
This week I interviewed Clark Neily about his new book, Terms of Engagement: How Our Courts Should Enforce the Constitution's Promise of Limited Government. Here is our exchange:
JB: Your book is about the idea of judicial engagement. What is judicial
engagement and how does it differ from other familiar views about the
judicial role?
CN: “Judicial
engagement” is a term we coined at the Institute for Justice, the
nation’s leading libertarian public interest law firm, to distinguish
between cases
where judges make a serious effort to enforce constitutional limits on
government power and cases where they do not.
For
example, when the government imposes an advertising restriction on a
particular product or service, such as interior design (true story!),
alcohol, or cigarettes,
courts will apply a deferential but still meaningful level of scrutiny
referred to as the
Central Hudson test for commercial speech. Even though it is only considered an “intermediate” form of scrutiny, the
Central Hudson test bears all the hallmarks of real
judging: i.e., a genuine quest for truth in which the constitutionality
of the challenged regulation will be determined by identifying the
government’s true end, assessing
the relationship between that end and the means chosen to advance it,
and considering whether there is some fairly obvious way the government
could have achieved that end with less of an imposition on liberty.
Notably, the government carries the burden of
proof and persuasion on all of those points, and that burden cannot be
satisfied with “mere speculation and conjecture.”
By contrast, if the government were to ban all
sales of the same product or service, a reviewing court
would apply the rational basis test—or, as Solicitor General Donald
Verrilli referred to it more precisely in his recent DOMA argument, “Lee
Optical rational basis review.” This is the
most deferential standard of review in all of constitutional law, and it
is the one applied to most economic regulations, including occupational
licensing laws. As a public
interest lawyer who has been litigating occupational licensing cases
for thirteen years under rational basis review (as well as commercial
speech cases under
Central Hudson and myriad other constitutional cases), I can say from firsthand experience that what General Verrilli referred to as “Lee Optical
rational basis review” bears none of the hallmarks of real judging.
Unlike the
Central Hudson test and other forms of so-called “heightened”
scrutiny (I say “so-called” because I believe “heightened” in this
context is simply a euphemism for “real” or “genuine”), the rational
basis test does
not involve a genuine search for truth, and judges in rational basis
cases act more like advocates than neutral adjudicators.
Among
other things, the Supreme Court has held that the government’s true end
is irrelevant in rational basis cases, and the government need not
support any
of its factual assertions with evidence.
Instead, the government may base its actions on “rational speculation,”
and the plaintiff must “negative” every conceivable justification for
the law. Of course,
even a moment’s reflection makes clear why it is impossible to negate an infinite set of purely hypothetical justifications.
(Imagine what discovery would look like if plaintiff’s counsel
were serious about trying to satisfy that burden. What am I supposed to
do, send the government a list of every object, substance, phenomenon,
and condition known to man—from aardvarks and
angioplasty to zebras and zygomatic arches—and ask the government to
admit or deny whether each particular item has anything to do with the
challenged law?)
But
wait, it gets better (or worse, depending on your perspective). If the
government lawyer proves insufficiently creative to invent a
hypothetical justification
for the law, the judge is supposed to help out by inventing her own
imaginary explanation.
Is there any other area of law—breach of contract or employment
discrimination, for example—where we would countenance ostensibly
neutral judges inventing justifications for potentially wrongful conduct
in order to help the government win?
I can’t think of any. And let’s be honest: that’s really
not judging; it’s advocacy.
To
be clear, the rational basis test is not the only form of fake judging
(or “judicial abdication,” as I refer to it in my book,
Terms of Engagement).
But it is perhaps the most glaring example, and more importantly I
believe it is a learned behavior—a kind of “dog ate my homework”
approach to judging that has gradually seeped (slunk?) into other areas
of constitutional law, such as enumerated-powers
federalism cases, administrative law, and eminent domain, as we saw in
Kelo v. City of New London (2005).
So judicial engagement means nothing more than real judging—what current doctrine calls “heightened” scrutiny—in all cases.
To be clear, it does not categorically reject tiered scrutiny
(though I confess I am uneasy about it, as are the Chief Justice and
many other thoughtful commentators), but it does reject the radical
disconnect between standards of review where judges
make a sincere evaluation of the government’s conduct and cases they
deliberately turn a blind eye instead.
JB: You argue that it is important for judges to take judging seriously in
every case. What does that mean? Do you feel these days that
judges are not sufficiently serious about judging? Can you give an
example of some cases that might come out differently if judges were
properly engaged with the Constitution? Are judges who
don't approach the Constitution this way violating their oaths of
office?
CN: I do believe judges should take judging seriously in
every case, and I’ve tried to provide my litigator’s-eye perspective on what that means in my preceding response.
I
also believe that judges these days are not sufficiently serious about
judging in many constitutional cases, but I hasten to add that
they have been instructed—even ordered—by the Supreme Court to adopt a non-serious approach in
cases involving supposedly nonfundamental rights, as well as other
limits on government power deemed unworthy of meaningful
judicial enforcement.
As for examples of cases that might (would) come out differently if judges properly engaged with
the Constitution, the examples are legion.
I will offer three from a virtually endless list.
Federalism.
In December 2012, just six months after the Supreme Court upheld
the Affordable Care Act as a valid exercise of the federal government’s
tax power while supposedly laying down a marker on the almost infinitely
elastic commerce clause, the Eleventh Circuit
upheld a purported exercise of commerce power by the U.S. Department of
Agriculture so whimsical as to be downright humorous.
Long story short, there is a federal law that regulates “exhibitors” of animals.
The law was originally enacted to empower the feds to regulate laboratories that use primates in scientific experiments.
Fair enough—presumably most lab chimps actually have moved in foreign or interstate commerce at some point.
But could the law also be applied to non-paripatetic animals like
the polydactyl cats of the Hemingway Home and Museum in Key West,
Florida—none
of whom had ever been bought or sold in interstate commerce and all of
whom were in fact marooned on an island at the very southern tip of
Florida?
Yes, said the Eleventh Circuit! Why?
Because the museum featured the cats on its website and sold
cat-related merchandise in its gift shop, which means they
“substantially affect[ed] interstate commerce.” 907 Whitehead St., Inc. v. U.S. Dep’t of Agric.,
701 F.3d 1345 (11th Cir. 2012).
Medical Self-Determination.
In 2003, a group of terminally ill cancer patients filed suit
asserting a constitutional right of access to potentially lifesaving
experimental drugs that had completed FDA Phase I testing, meaning the
drugs were safe enough for widespread human trials
but had not yet been determined to be efficacious.
After initially upholding the patients’ claim, the D.C. Circuit
reheard the case en banc and reversed, concluding that there is “no
fundamental right . . . of access to experimental drugs for the
terminally ill.”
Besides
being textually, doctrinally, and morally insupportable, I find that to
be an extremely upsetting conclusion for personal reasons,
as I suspect do many other people with family members who are battling
or who have recently succumbed to cancer.
I will therefore allow Judge Judith Rogers’ masterful dissent (in
which she was joined only by Judge Douglas Ginsburg) to speak for me.
Abigail Alliance v. Eschenbach, 495 F.3d 695, 714 (D.C. Cir. 2007) (en banc) (Rogers, J., dissenting).
Occupational freedom.
As noted above, I specialize in occupational licensing cases.
The hardest case I ever worked on, from a personal standpoint, was a challenge to Louisiana’s florist licensing law.
Alone among the states, Louisiana requires a license to sell
floral arrangements—supposedly to protect the public from the physical
dangers of unlicensed floristry and to elevate the quality and
reputation of Louisiana’s floral industry.
This is preposterous, of course; only in infant would suppose
that Louisiana legislators were genuinely trying to protect the public
from incompetent florists instead of industry insiders from fair
competition.
But a
federal judge upheld the law anyway, partly on the basis of the specter
of infected dirt, which Louisiana’s spectacularly subjective
licensing exam (pass rate: 36%) was somehow supposed to protect people
from.
Meadows v. Odom, 360 F. Supp. 2d 811, 824 (M.D. La. 2005)
vacated as moot 198 Fed. App’x 348 (5th Cir. 2006).
(Hurricane Katrina caused all of our clients to
retire or flee the state, which is why the case was dismissed as moot on
appeal.)
The
lead client in that case, Sandy Meadows, was a widow with no vocational
skills other than the ability to create simple—but perfectly
attractive and serviceable—floral arrangements.
She tried five times to pass the licensing exam, but it was just
too subjective and (I can say this with a reasonable measure of
confidence, not only because public choice theory has won several Nobel
Prizes, but because I personally conducted exhaustive
discovery in the case) deliberately rigged to exclude newcomers.
When the Louisiana Horticulture Commission discovered that Sandy
was managing the floral department of an Albertsons grocery store
without a license, it threatened to shut it down unless the store hired a
state-licensed florist instead.
They had no choice but to let Sandy go.
Unemployed and lacking any other vocational skills, Sandy Meadows died
five months later, alone, unemployed, and in poverty because the state
of Louisiana cared nothing for her constitutional right to earn a living
and I couldn’t persuade a federal judge to
protect that right in a properly engaged manner.
That, for me, will always be the slap and the sting of judicial abdication.
I’m
honestly not sure whether I think lower-court judges who faithfully
execute the Supreme Court’s instruction to practice fake judging
in cases involving supposedly nonfundamental rights are violating their
oath of office.
But I am convinced that justices who perpetuate those doctrines are.
JB: Where does judicial engagement fit into current theories of
constitutional interpretation? Does it assume some form of originalism?
If so, what kind? Could a living constitutionalist also be in favor of
judicial engagement?
CN: I must confess that as a constitutional litigator (rather than an academic or theorist), I may well be out of my depth here.
So I’ll be brief.
Judicial engagement fits disjointedly into current theories of constitutional interpretation.
All cases involving “heightened” scrutiny (from strict scrutiny
all the way down to what has been called “rational basis with bite”)
are, at least according to my perception, examples of judicial
engagement.
But heightened scrutiny is the exception, not the rule.
The Supreme Court’s default setting—that is, the level of
scrutiny applied to non-privileged rights and non-invidious
discrimination—is rational basis review, which is the paradigmatic form
of judicial abdication.
As
for whether judicial engagement assumes some form of originalism, I
think probably it does—at least to the extent “originalism” implies
a commitment to some form of textualism and a recognition that judges
are (or should be) bound to respect external norms to which their own
preferences or convictions must yield in cases of conflict.
Finally,
I’m not sure I’ve ever met a self-avowed “living constitutionalist,” so
I don’t feel confident saying precisely what, if anything,
they stand for. That said, anyone who thinks the
government should be repudiated when it disregards the rule of law,
denied when it is false, and chastened when it usurps powers not granted
to it by the Constitution
should feel some affinity for judicial engagement.
JB: If you have never met a living constitutionalist, I suspect that you
need to get out more. You probably have and didn't know it! In any
case, take two issues that liberals care about a good deal: abortion and
gay rights. It
sounds as if you are suggesting that judges should be far more
suspicious of TRAP (targeted regulation of abortion providers)
laws whose barely concealed purpose is to make abortion difficult if not
impossible in a particular state. The same might apply to
mandatory ultrasound laws. And your approach might also call for
searching scrutiny of laws that burden gay and transgender people.
Could you say a few words about that?
CN: (It’s
probably true that I need to get out more—my wife and I are expecting
our first child in two weeks, so we’re in full nesting mode!—but just to
be clear, I said I wasn’t sure I’d ever met a
self-avowed living constitutionalist. Perhaps that’s because as a
litigator I spend most of my time in and around courts, where I suspect
living constitutionalists tend to keep a lower profile than they might
elsewhere.)
As for
your question, let me preface my answer by saying I think the issue of
abortion may be the single worst setting in which to test the
general implications of particular theories or approaches to
constitutional law. That’s because unlike, say, free speech, abortion
involves a fundamental philosophical issue over which people disagree
both passionately and reasonably. So in order to
have a coherent constitutional discussion about abortion, you
have to be very careful—far more careful than I think most people tend
to be—about the extent to which you are really having a
philosophical discussion. For example, are you disagreeing over
what is a “person” (philosophical); whether “person” is the relevant
term (philosophical and constitutional); or whether all “persons”
(whoever they may be) are covered by the Equal Protection
Clause (constitutional)?
That
said, I suppose the obvious response to your question whether judges
should be “far more suspicious of TRAP laws” is “far more suspicious”
than what? I’m not sure what the current doctrinal baseline is on that
question or whether
it is even fair to say there is one. But certainly if a state were to
pass a law that said something like, “Every person who works in a
facility where abortions are performed must be at least seven feet
tall,” then I would expect properly engaged judges to
ask the same question of that law that they are supposed to ask in all
cases: “So, what’s really going on here?” Of course, different judges
will have different takes on that in different cases, and we should not
be so naïve as to suppose that the lines they
draw between “illegitimately pretextual” (requiring abortion providers
to be at least seven feet tall) and “plausibly/sufficiently related to a
legitimate government interest” (holding abortion facilities to the
same hygienic standards as urgent care clinics)
will not be influenced at the margins by their own feelings about the
underlying policy. (Notice I said “influenced,” not controlled or
dictated.)
According to the argument for judicial engagement I try to articulate in
my book,
the bottom line is this: Laws are passed to advance particular ends;
sometimes those ends are constitutionally legitimate and sometimes they
are not; judges ought not pretend that laws that serve demonstrably
illegitimate ends—e.g., suppressing dissent, expressing animus,
avoiding accountability, discouraging fair competition, etc.—were in
fact passed to serve legitimate ones. If you as a judge believe it that
is impossible to say what ends a given law serves;
say that. If you believe it is possible to say what ends a given law
serves but you can’t say whether those ends are constitutionally
legitimate or illegitimate; say that. And if you believe that a given
law so entangles legitimate and illegitimate ends
as to render judicial review impossible in a particular case, then say
that.
My thirteen years of experience litigating
constitutional cases convinces me that doing nothing more than asking
and answering those questions honestly in
every case (and not just a favored handful, as current doctrine
calls for) would produce significant changes to the constitutional
landscape.
JB: Is judicial engagement only about what we now call judicial scrutiny,
or does it also extend to the scope of judicial power? For example,
would you call for a serious reexamination of the doctrines of standing
and justifiability?
Take the Clapper case, in which the Court followed a fairly long
practice of avoiding any serious engagement with covert government
surveillance programs. Would judicial engagement require a different
approach, if not a different result?
CN: The short
answer is yes, the call for judicial engagement—real judging in all
cases with no exceptions—most certainly does extend to various
“avoidance doctrines” such as standing, ripeness, justiciability, etc. I
have personally
experienced how standing, for example, may be employed as a tool to
avoid reaching difficult constitutional issues instead of avoiding
issuing advisory opinions, which what standing doctrine is actually
meant to do.
For instance, I helped design and litigate the Heller
gun case, where five of our six plaintiffs were found not to have
standing because they had never been personally threatened with
prosecution for violating DC’s gun ban. Well, of course they’d never
been personally threatened with prosecution: none of
them had ever broken the law! And yet, despite crystal clear Supreme
Court precedent that an individual need not risk prosecution in order to
test the constitutionality of a given law, the D.C. Circuit held
otherwise—requiring, in effect, that would-be gun
owners (but not would-be book owners, of course) first violate
the law by acquiring an illegal firearm; draw the fact of their
violation to the attention of the relevant authorities; receive a
personal threat of prosecution; and then, if they wish to
be in federal court, get their complaint on file between the time the
threat is issued and criminal proceedings are initiated in the local
court system in order to avoid
Younger abstention.
The only
reason Dick Heller was found to have standing was that a friend of his
had advised him to undertake the completely futile act of trying to
register a handgun that he had lawfully acquired in Virginia and left
behind when he
moved to DC. The denial of Heller’s sham registration application was
found to create standing. As the
D.C. Circuit explained, “The denial of a gun license is significant;
it constitutes an injury independent of the District’s prospective
enforcement of its gun laws….” So if Dick Heller hadn’t filled out a
completely meaningless form, our entire case would
have gotten bounced on standing, just like the NRA’s copycat case,
Seegars v. Gonzales (over a simple but devastating dissent by Judge Sentelle).
I think
that is a preposterous—but unfortunately all too common—application of
standing doctrine. And yes, it is inconsistent with judicial engagement
as I conceive it.
As for judicial review of covert government surveillance programs specifically, the answer is yes—notwithstanding
the uniquely (?) sensitive and challenging issues involved, I think it
is becoming increasingly
clear that America has far, far more to lose from withdrawing
meaningful judicial oversight from that area completely than from
whatever risks such oversight may entail.
JB: Similarly, there are parts of the Constitution, like the Republican
Form of Government Clause, that have effectively been made
non-enforceable through the political question doctrine. Does judicial
engagement call for a rethinking
of these doctrines?
CN: No, not unless they are based on reasoning
that is palpably intellectually dishonest, as I believe the toothless
version of the rational basis test is.
JB: What
about the President's use of military force in places like Libya? It is
widely assumed nowadays that courts will not get involved in disputes
between Congress and the President on the use of military force. Would
judicially engaged courts see things differently?
Posted 8:30 AM by JB [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |