Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Some Notes on Historical Materialism, Naturalism and Legal Theory, Part I
|
Friday, September 20, 2024
Some Notes on Historical Materialism, Naturalism and Legal Theory, Part I
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization Symposium on Jeremy Kessler, Law and Historical Materialism. Brian Leiter I very
much appreciate Jeremy Kessler’s careful and well-informed exposition of “Law
and Historical Materialism,” and I also appreciate his lucid attention to Pashukanis,
who may not have been right, but who is worth revisiting as an intellectually
serious form of genuinely left legal theory (see esp. 12-14 of Kessler’s essay for
an excellent set of questions that Pashukanis’s analysis invites). In this first post, I will focus primarily on
some technical details about Professor Kessler’s understanding of historical
materialism (hereafter HM), and functional explanation in particular. In a second post, I will discuss his
treatment of naturalism, which seems to me more problematic. I will also say a bit in that second post
about Kessler’s framing of his project in relation to Critical Legal Studies
and other “left-leaning legal thought” as he calls it. Kessler’s analysis of HM relies quite
heavily on G.A. Cohen’s seminal 1978 account in terms of functional explanation
(i.e., the distribution of property rights in a society is explained
functionally by its contribution to the development of the productive forces). Philosophically, functional explanations are
peculiar, because the thing to be explained (the explanandum) is prior in time to the explanans (the thing that explains it): e.g., that cheetahs run fast (the
explanandum) is, in evolutionary theory, explained by the fact that doing so fulfills
the function of allowing them to survive and then reproduce successfully. Surviving and reproducing, however, occur after cheetahs are able to run
fast. Ordinary causal explanations
involve an explanandum that comes temporally after the explanans: e.g.,
the window broke because the brick
was thrown through it (the brick caused the window to break). How can something that comes after “explain”
something that came before, as functional explanation would have it? In my recent book with Jaime Edwards
on Marx, we endorse a common view in philosophy of science, namely that a credible
functional explanation must really be a shorthand gloss on ordinary, causal
explanation, one which respects the temporal priority of explanans over
explanandum. Such explanations can, of
course, be complex. “Cheetahs run fast because doing so fulfills
the function of promoting reproductive success” is really shorthand for a more
complicated set of causal relations that are central to evolution by natural
selection. Early
proto-cheetahs--ancestors of the current ones, as it were-- had differing genes,
which produced different phenotypic (i.e., physically observable) traits. Some of these proto-cheetahs had, by chance,
genes conductive to running fast (the phenotype), and some did not. In the ancestral environment, being able to
run fast turned out to be a big advantage, in terms of avoiding predators and
catching food. As a result, the
fast-running proto-cheetahs (unlike their slower-running brethren) lived longer
and had more offspring that they could feed, and most of those offspring, in
turn, had the genes conducive to developing the phenotypic trait of being able
to run fast. Notice that this much more complicated
causal explanation—genes conductive to fast-running enabled their bearers to
have more offspring, most of whom have the same gene—is a causal explanation
that preserves the temporal priority of explanans
to explanandum. Having a gene conducive to the phenotypic
trait of running fast is prior to surviving and reproducing. But—and this is the crucial bit--the reason that gene becomes predominant in
a population of cheetahs is the function it performs: contributing (causally) to survival and
reproduction. The same thing is true of Marx’s actual explanation
of historical change: there is a causal
mechanism underlying the functional explanations, what Marx usually calls “class
struggle.” Marx’s texts, themselves,
make this clear. Indeed, it is striking
that the functionalist account from the 1859 Preface to A Critique of
Political Economy (on which Cohen has to rely very heavily) is not
articulated with the same theoretical clarity elsewhere: there are some hints of it in The German
Ideology of 1845-46, but it appears to be replaced by the “history is the
history of class struggle” slogan of The
Communist Manifesto, written in 1848.
Part I of The Communist Manifesto
famously begins: “The history of all
hitherto existing society is the history of class struggles. Freeman and slave, patrician and plebian,
lord and serf, guild-master and journeyman, in a word, oppressor and oppressed,
stood in constant opposition to one another, carried on an uninterrupted, now
hidden, now open fight, a fight that each time ended, either in a revolutionary
reconstitution of society at large, or in the common ruin of the contending
classes” (MECW 6: 482). Marx’s own
practice of explaining historical events (e.g., The Eighteenth Brumaire of
Louis Bonaparte) is also far closer to the “class struggle” version of
historical explanation than to the functionalism of the 1859 Preface. The
1859 Preface, then, is the functionalist shorthand or gloss on the more
elaborate causal theory of historical change which appeals to class struggle. Cheetahs run fast because doing so enables
them to survive and reproduce: that is
the functionalist gloss on the evolution of fast-running cheetahs. The real, underlying causal mechanism, as we
have seen, appeals to the fact that early proto-cheetahs with genes that
disposed them to running fast fared much better in terms of surviving and
reproducing, with the effect that those genes became predominant in the
population of cheetahs over evolutionary time.
So
too with HM: the relations of
production and ideological superstructure of a society are explained by their
fulfilling the function of developing the forces of production in that society,
and historical change occurs when the existing relations of production and
ideologies cease to fulfill that function.
There is, however, an underlying causal mechanism here, namely, class
struggle. While the functionalist says,
“Relations of production X are explained by the contribution they make to the
use and development of forces of production Y,” the causal theory of HM says, If I may be permitted, a bit of obviously
potted history: the nascent bourgeois
class of capitalist society sees the productive potential of the new industrial
technologies (e.g., the power loom), but realizes that to exploit that
productive power, it must have the legal right to purchase the labor power of
other people--people, who, under existing relations of productions, may be
serfs, peasants, or journeyman beholden to trade guilds. Thus the bourgeois class must “struggle” to
change the existing relations of production so it can take advantage of the new
technology and its productive power. Kessler
acknowledges this concern about the priority of causal explanation in terms of
class struggle, observing (correctly) that on this account “the development of
the productive forces is [still] essential to explaining the origin and outcome
of class struggle” (6 n. 18). He
worries, however, that, “Historical materialism has never achieved consensus
on…a complete causal theory, for all the reasons that causal explanations of
social phenomena are harder to specify than causal explanations of natural
phenomena” (8). The questions for his
account, however, are: (1) is there more
consensus on the “complete” functional explanation? and (2) how much dissensus
is there from the view that conflict between different classes is at the root
of historical changes? I would welcome answers
that draw on Professor Kessler’s historical expertise. Kessler
acknowledges that the preceding account of functional explanation as a gloss on
causal explanation represents a “friendly amendment” (6 n. 18) to his “minimal”
account of HM. I think it is more than
that, one that actually improves his case.
For example, the obvious reason that “law at times seem to be out of
joint with its social and economic context, sometimes even working to
destabilize rather than entrench prevailing social and economic hierarchies”
(24) is that law is a site on which classes compete for dominance (precisely
because law under capitalism is constitutive of relations of production, a point
to which I return, below). This is why,
as Kessler says, “legal relations are habitually laggard” (25): the dominant class has established “legal
relations” conducive to its rule, while ascendant classes who can make better
use of available productive power struggle to unsettle precisely those legal
relations. A major advantage of the
class struggle version of HM is that it directs our attention to the crucial
fact: what are the classes at any given
time, and how are they competing with each other? That also allows us to avoid appeal, as
Kessler surprisingly does in explaining the lag, to “cultural and other
peculiarities of a given society” (26), whose status in a materialist account
is mysterious. The
emphasis on classes in competition, including through the law, is compatible
with the quite important point Kessler makes, namely, that “legal and political
decisions function primarily as pass-throughs for non-intentional regularities”
(37). Classes seeking economic
advantage need not realize the large-scale effects of their motives, or how
they contribute to the growth of productive power and ultimately the
transformation of economic orders. Let
me conclude this first post with some quibbles about Kessler’s account of HM--quibbles
that may not matter in the end, but I’m not wholly certain. First,
human labor power is not the most important force of production, unless you
treat the outputs of mental labor power as part of the former--as Kessler
[e.g., 16] and others do. This is,
however, misleading. The development of
technology is the crucial fact for HM, because it is technology that increases
productive power. Yes, technology
results from human mental labor, but what matters is that the technology is
actually utilized to increase productive output: the technology is different than the brain
power that conceives it. Second,
I find it odd to characterize the superstructure as a matter of “social
relations” (9), as Kessler does, rather than as ideology. It is ideologies—ideas that are both false
and in the interest of the ruling class--that are to be explained in terms of
their function of sustaining the relations of production: the ideas themselves are not relations. It is true that some of these ideas, like the
legal ones, can be constitutive of the relations of production, but that
is not what Marx targets when he attacks law as an ideology: he attacks rather legal ideas (think, e.g.,
“equality under law”), just as he targets religious, moral and economic ideas
and theories. Third,
Kessler is correct that Cohen’s version of HM involves an assumption about
human nature, i.e., that human beings are always striving to increase
productive power (51). This assumption
is not needed, however, as the analogy with evolution illustrates. For natural selection to work, there must be random genetic mutations
that produce changes in the phenotypic features of organisms, features that
then affect reproductive success (e.g., making proto-cheetahs run faster). Darwinian theory does not explain why
genetic mutations occur, but it does explain what happens when certain
mutations affecting phenotypic features occur:
those that are conducive to reproductive advantage come to dominate in a
population. So, too, Marx may not be entitled to assume (if he did) that
productive forces always grow everywhere and at all times; but when
technological innovations occur that enhance productive power (the analogue of
genetic mutations in the Darwin case), Marx’s theory of historical materialism
offers an explanation of how the relations of production and ideological
superstructure will change (they will change to accommodate and support the
exploitation of those productive forces), and those changes will predominate in
the population affected by the technological advance. Brian Leiter is Karl N. Llewellyn Professor
of Jurisprudence and Director of the Center for Law, Philosophy & Human
Values at the University of Chicago. He
can be reached at bleiter@uchicago.edu
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |