Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Law and the Critique of Political Economy
|
Thursday, September 26, 2024
Law and the Critique of Political Economy
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization Symposium on Jeremy Kessler, Law and Historical Materialism. Talha Syed Jeremy Kessler’s “Law and Historical
Materialism” is bracing. Bracing in its unapologetic embrace of strong
explanatory ambitions for any theory of law, one that must be anchored in a
broader theory of society (and even of humanity’s interaction with the natural
world). And bracing also in its no-pulled-punches approach to articulating
dissatisfaction with existing legal theories, critical legal studies (CLS)
principally among them. Sharing both commitments—not only in the
content of the views, but also in the form of their unvarnished articulation—I will
use this platform of agreement as the basis for launching an unvarnished
critique of the alternative theory he offers. Kessler’s intervention has two
principal aims: to present to a legal audience a robust variant of the
classical Marxist theory of history and society, historical materialism; and to
defend it as a theory of law against various criticisms, principally those advanced
by CLS. In respect of the first aim, the version of historical materialism
advanced by Kessler is indeed of classical stripe: it is a theory of history as
driven by the development of the (material) forces of production, in accord
with which development arise and fall different (social) relations of
production, and corresponding to which production relations are superstructural
political and legal institutions and ideologies.[1]
In reply to the central Crit objections to this view—namely, that it fails to attend
to the indeterminacy, contingency, and autonomy of law[2]—Kessler
advances a two-fold answer: historical materialism can account for these
“apparent” features of law “at least as well as CLS and its successors,” while
also making better sense of aspects of law that “CLS and its successors have
struggled” with, in particular law’s resistance to reform and its tendency to
reproduce social and economic hierarchies. There is one aspect of Professor
Kessler’s argument with which I quite agree, and this is that classical Marxism
has within it the resources to handle standard Crit objections based on law. As
I have stated on a previous occasion—pointing to the same work of G.A.
Cohen on which Kessler heavily relies—“the reasons for classical Marxism’s
flaws have little to do with Crit claims from law’s autonomy, constitutive
role, and indeterminacy. In fact, classical Marxism can defend itself quite
well against these criticisms—indeed, it already did, avant la lettre of CLS.”
I hasten to add that, as the passage just quoted indicates, my own view is that
classical Marxism does have serious—indeed, as I will discuss next, fatal—flaws.
But these go less to its theory of law than to its theory of society.
Or, to be more precise, the flaws in its theory of law are tributary from flaws
in its theory of society, and in either case the flaws have little to do with
those pointed to by CLS. Indeed, and this is the nub of the present point, it
is telling that the Crit objections were in fact addressed “avant la lettre” by
G.A. Cohen—i.e., based on arguments made long before the Crits—and even more
telling is that the Crit responses to Cohen were perfunctory and in passing at
best.[3] These points are telling because they
go to the twin bases of shared agreement I have with Professor Kessler: namely,
that any social theory of law worth the name needs to be serious about its explanatory—conceptual
and empirical—claims and that, in these respects at least, CLS views were
wanting. This point has been perceptively driven home by Ntina Tzouvala, who urges that “we need a more substantive, more analytically
ambitious and less aestheticised idea of [] legal theory,” while CLS is often
“better understood as an attachment to certain avant-garde aesthetics.” Yet it is precisely as an explanatory
theory—both of society and of law—that I believe Kessler’s rehabilitation of
classical Marxism fails. And its failure is not accidental or arbitrary but
symptomatic, in ways that have much to tell us about the way forward for a
critical theory of both society and law. Put succinctly, in each of its twin
component parts—namely, the “materialist conception of history” and a “critical
political economy”—classical Marxism involved the naturalization of
historically-specific social relations and their projection onto history as a
whole, in precisely the ways that Marx himself warned against in his mature critique
of political economy. That critique was a denaturalizing analysis of
capitalist relations and dynamics, showing at one and the same time how such
relations and dynamics were historically-specific and yet naturalized by the
eternal categories of the “classical political economy” of Smith and Ricardo.
The great irony of classical Marxism is that it followed in precisely these false
Smithian-Ricardian footsteps. Given the centrality Kessler
accords to “naturalism” for any plausible explanatory theory of society and
law, it is important to be clear about what is and is not meant by
“denaturalizing” as a central aspect of Marx’s critical analysis of capitalist
relations and dynamics. What is not meant is any repudiation of
“naturalism” in substantive social inquiry where that is simply taken to mean,
as it primarily seems to for Kessler, a methodological commitment that
substantive theorizing be continuous with the protocols and findings of
scientific analysis in general. (Kessler at 7.) Rather, the point of a
denaturalizing critique is to point to the ways that something that is
social, and historical, is falsely imputed to asocial, or
transhistorical, natural givens. Further, to be effective, any such critique
must supply its own alternative, more plausible, denaturalizing explanation
of the phenomena at issue—for Marx, one advanced in terms of
historically-specific social relations. We can see the point most clearly by zeroing
in on the fundamental empirical difficulty facing the classical Marxist view, as
recognized by two of its stoutest defenders, the historian Eric Hobsbawm and
G.A. Cohen himself.[4]
As Hobsbawm and Cohen both concede—the former more forthrightly, the latter more
hesitantly—a key embarrassment facing historical materialism is the fact that it
is only within capitalism that the “forces of production” exhibit a systematic
tendency to grow.[5]
Moreover, and shifting gears from empirical to conceptual registers, it is only
within capitalism that a plausible explanatory mechanism exists to account for
such growth, namely the “selection” effects of compulsive market pressures.[6]
And what accounts for these pressures? For the Marx of Capital, it is neither
Adam Smith’s “human nature” to “truck, barter, and exchange” nor
Malthusian-Ricardian demographic-environmental constraints of population and
soil fertility, but, rather, the historically-specific—not transhistorically-determined
nor “contingent”—socio-political institutionalization of relations of generalized
commodity production, whereby all economic agents are subjected to market-dependence
by virtue of producers becoming “free in the double sense,” freed of both extra-economic
forms of exploitation and the means of subsistence.[7] To state the point in more general
terms, historical materialism on Kessler’s version is a theory of history as the march of “progress”: the development of
human powers vis-à-vis nature (“technology”) via their envelopment in different
social forms of production of a surplus (“class”). The relations of production
that obtain at a given point in time are those best suited for the further
development of productive forces, in light of given geographical, demographic,
and technological conditions (the “forces of production” of nature, labor,
tools). This view raises two key questions: how precisely do those
relations most propitious to the development of the forces become adopted at a
given point in time and, in any case, why exactly is the development of
the forces of production the ultimate driver of history? The standard answers
consist of an implausibly transhistorical view of asocial drivers of the
development of material forces, and an implausibly functionalist view of the
selection of social relations to develop these. These fail both empirically and
explanatorily. Empirically, because there are long stretches of history where
the forces do not develop but rather “petrify”—they only systematically develop
within capitalism. Explanatorily, because no plausible mechanism(s) is/are
identified to select the social relations that optimally develop the forces—it
is only within capitalist social relations that such a mechanism, for
the selection of productive forces, exists: economic competition driven by
imperatives of generalized market-dependence. And so we can now see this view for
what it is: a transposition of the historically-specific social relations of
capitalism and its dynamics—technological dynamism propelled by generalized
markets—onto history as a whole, via a naturalizing of capitalist social
relations as a kind of ahistorical materialist rationality of homo economicus (ingenuity and instrumental
rationality in conditions of scarcity).[8] This explains both the empirical and explanatory gaps of the view:
only once you have capitalist social relations do you get either the empirical
result (sustained productivity) or the explanation (selection by generalized
markets). In sum, the “forces” theory is the clearest (but not only) case of a historical
materialist view that turns out, upon closer inspection, to be a naturalization
of the relations and dynamics of a specific society and their projection onto
all of history. I need to make two important clarifications. First,
the empirical point being pressed here is not that
there is no (incremental, jagged) growth in productive forces for much of history,
only that significant, systematic development is specific to the modern—capitalist—epoch,
with earlier eras marked by long periods of relative stasis. That there has
been some growth—in part because once acquired, productive facilities are
rarely given up, so that development is “sticky downward”[9]–is no doubt true, but this
provides a slender basis for any (transhistorical) explanatory theory of
society.[10]
To think otherwise likely owes to a projection of capitalist dynamics onto
history as a whole.[11]
And similar projections may fuel a possible misunderstanding of the present point,
which is that it somehow vaunts “economic development” or growth in productive
forces as desirable in itself, and perhaps even denigrates societies not
significantly marked by it. But nothing of the sort is indicated here. In
particular, two points need to be made in reply to this concern: first,
whatever evaluative attitude we wish to adopt toward such growth, the issue here
is about the explanatory power of a specific social theory, and for that
the empirical realities of such growth need to be addressed; second the position
being advanced here takes, as discussed next, a decidedly jaundiced view of
capitalist growth, as a form of systematically “alienated productivity.” Indeed it is precisely the way
Marx’s denaturalizing mode of analysis is able to solder an explanation
of a phenomenon with its critique, that marks out his mature critique
of political economy as a matter of method. This brings us to the second key
component of the classical Marxism advocated by Kessler, going not to its
theory of history—historical materialism—but to its theory of a specific society,
capitalism.[12] The classical understanding of Marx’s project is as a
“critical political economy,” one that joins classical
political economy in its analysis of a “material” field of inquiry, but
radicalizes the classicals’ surplus-based analysis of growth, distribution, and
classes by refining and extending it in the vein of a labor theory of
surplus-value, profits, and exploitation. This conception of Marx’s project
faces two difficulties. A first is substantive deficits in its analysis of the
problems it focuses on—including, principally,
those afflicting a
theory of class based on “the labor theory of value.” Second, an even deeper
set of drawbacks concern the limited horizon of the problems themselves. On
an alternative view,
Marx’s project was less a critical political economy than a critique
of political economy. On this conception, Marx’s aim was not to
join classical political economy in its analysis of a naturalized field of
inquiry, but to delimit the conditions of possibility of the field itself, in
terms of the historically-specific social
relations of capital that constitute its proper object of inquiry.[13]
His focus is best understood not in terms of a Ricardian analysis of property-based
distribution, but of an analysis of the social relations of production
themselves. In Diane Elson’s illuminating encapsulation, we need to shift from
a “labor theory of value” to a value theory of labor.[14] The first refers to an
attempt to take over the surplus-based analysis of classical political economy
and provide a quantitative theory of price, profit, or exploitation—an attempt
ill-fated in both its explanatory and evaluative facets. The second refers to
an analysis not of the “material content” of “value” in labor, but rather of
the social form taken by labor (and utility) under capitalist social
relations[15]—i.e., a
qualitative analysis of how human powers and needs are shaped by generalized
commodity production and subjected to its impersonal imperatives of ceaseless
expansion of exchange-value for its own sake. The result? A systematic
alienation of social powers and relations, as not only human needs and powers but also human
relations and the Earth are subjected to ever-more extensive and intensive
instrumental quantification. This critical strand of Marxian
thought, long submerged under a crust of materialist overlay within the
classical Marxist tradition, is currently undergoing a worldwide revival.[16]
It is one that left legal scholars would do well to join. Especially since recovering
and fully developing it is something that legal academics are particularly
well-placed to undertake, as doing so would also involve recovering and fully
developing a distinct strand of legal theory. This is a submerged aspect of
Legal Realist analysis, one that fully eschews the dominant “internal” and “external”
critiques of formalism associated with Realism, and advances instead a dereification critique that forms a close counterpart
to the denaturalization critique of political economy. This critique
takes law to be a human artifact serving human interests, with lucidity about
the structure and purposes of that artifact (its forms and means) being
the first step toward effectiveness in pursuit of those interests. This legal strand has its deepest
roots in the work of Hohfeld, with the analysis of the social relations of modern
law as rights being a micro-institutional counterpart to the
macro-institutional component of the critique of political economy, with its
analysis of the social relations of market-dependence. Such social
relations, while in no way “materially” determined, are also in no way “legally
constructed,” nor simply indeterminately up for grabs. It is only by understanding
their architectural systematicity that they can be strategically targeted for effective
transformation. What matters in law is neither “indeterminacy” (wholly misguided) nor “autonomy” (of what, from
what?) but, rather, social agency.[17]
Such agency can be neither assumed nor foreclosed. It is, rather, entirely variable,
expanding or contracting depending on how lucid is our social understanding of
the relations meriting change and how effective are our social practices of transformation.[18]
In the debate between CLS and classical Marxism,
many may be tempted to stake out a halfway position, a compromise of some sort between
“some” legal indeterminacy (or autonomy) and “some” material constraint. That
would be a mistake. It would be a mistake because both poles of this spectrum
are simply ill-conceived. We need to fully jettison all talk of both
“indeterminacy” and “materialism,” as holdovers of deeply misguided strands of both
CLS and Marxism. In their stead, we need to recover submerged strands of
critical traditions, both in the critique of law and of political economy. As
those traditions teach, constraint comes not from material factors but from social
relations, and social agency (not autonomy, much less indeterminacy) is
neither foreclosed nor guaranteed but, rather, earned, through
understanding and practice directed at transformation.
Talha Syed is Lecturer in Law at U.C. Berkeley. You can reach him by e-mail at tsyed@law.berkeley.edu. [1] As Professor Kessler
acknowledges, this “forces of production” view is only one of the two main
variants of the classical Marxist theory of historical materialism, the other
being “class struggle” as “the motor force of history.” He suggests that,
should the forces theory face infirmities that the class struggle
theory can better handle, his account of historical materialism can take on the
latter as a “friendly amendment.” Jeremy Kessler, Law and Historical
Materialism at 6-7, fn. 18. Since, as discussed below at note 12, my argument pertains to both
variants of the classical theory, I set aside this issue here. [2] I should clarify that this is
Professor Kessler’s list of the Crit objections to classical Marxism, not my
own. Id. at 2, 51. I myself believe this list does not articulate the
Crit view at its strongest, since by themselves, these hardly count as
compelling objections: only if law is also constitutive, or shaping, of
social relations does the fact that it is autonomous (indeterminate,
contingent) matter, since otherwise law’s role in society is minor and hence
what shapes it only a peripheral concern for a social theory. This matters
because, as discussed above, I share Professor Kessler’s commitment to rigor in
social analysis, while the laundry-list style of Crit objections that Professor
Kessler adopts here, while a common practice, does not advance that aim. [3] Thus, the most sustained Crit
engagement with Cohen, by Mark Tushnet, offers in the course of two pages a
pair of highly abstract “skepticisms” with virtually no substantiating argument.
Mark Tushnet, Is there a Marxist Theory of Law?, 26 Nomos 171, 182-3 (1983). Professor
Tushnet subsequently seemed to recognize the thin character of his objections,
stating that “[f]or reasons that I do not understand, the challenge to cls from
the traditional Left has not picked up on G.A. Cohen's rehabilitation of
classical Marxist theory.” Mark Tushnet, Critical Legal Studies: A Political
History, 100 Yale L. J. 1515, 1529 n.
57 (1991). The next most serious engagement, by Robert Gordon, similarly
expressed doubts in passing about Cohen’s admittedly “extremely ingenious” argument,
without any sustained rebuttal—and this despite his article being primarily devoted
to debunking “functionalist” theories of law and Cohen’s argument already
gaining traction as the most sophisticated rehabilitation of functionalist
analysis. See Robert W. Gordon, Critical Legal Histories, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 57, 105-6 (1984).
Roberto Unger, for his part, did take Cohen’s theory more seriously, but not in
its legal aspects. See Roberto
Mangabeira Unger, Social Theory: Its Situation and Its Task 93-96, 230-31
(1984). Finally, Duncan Kennedy’s one reference to Cohen took the form
of a “but see” footnote appended to the following sentence: “But maybe
materialist explanations for the presence or absence of property consciousness
under particular material circumstances are already available, and I’m just not
aware of them (I doubt it).” Duncan Kennedy, The Role of Law in Economic
Thought: Essays on the Fetishism of Commodities, 34 Amer. U. L. Rev. 939, 993 (1985). [4] Hobsbawm and Cohen both take as
their touchstone text the locus classicus of the forces-of-production variant
of classical Marxism: the 1859 Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of
Political Economy. For Hobsbawm, this “presents historical materialism in
its most pregnant form” and this characterization is approvingly cited by Cohen
his book, the epigraph for which is provided by the central passage of the
Preface. Eric J. Hobsbawm, Introduction in Karl Marx, Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations 10
(E. J. Hobsbawm, ed., Jack
Cohen, trans.) (1964); G.A. Cohen,
Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defense vii-viii, x (2000 2nd
ed.) (1978). [5] See Eric J. Hobsbawm, Marx
and History, I/143 New Left Rev. 39, 43-44
(1984); Cohen, id. at
169-171. See also id. at 248 (“The fact that capitalism did not arise
spontaneously outside of Europe is a serious problem for historical materialism.”)
For relevant empirical data, see Angus
Maddison, The World Economy: A Millennial Perspective (2001). [6] For criticism of Cohen
emphasizing this explanatory, as opposed to the empirical, lacuna see Erik
Olin Wright & Andrew Levine, Rationality and Class Struggle, I/123 New Left Rev. 47 (1980). For a combined
criticism of both gaps, see Joshua Cohen, Book Review, 79 J. Phil. 253 (1982) (reviewing Cohen). Kessler acknowledges a
related—but distinct—explanatory issue, going to Cohen’s reliance on functional
explanations in general, rather than the specific difficulties he faces in
providing a plausible account of actual long-term historical processes.
Kessler, id. at 6-7. And even here he simply acknowledges the concern
without attempting to address it. As for the fundamental empirical point, he leaves
it untouched. These are troubling gaps in an argument that emphasizes
explanatory superiority as a key advantage of the theory it is advocating. [7] Karl Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 874-75,
272-73 (Ben Fowkes trans., 1976) (1867). It is to be regretted that the new
translation of Capital by Paul Reitter, in other respects quite
excellent, has dropped this now-canonical formulation of “free in the double
sense.” The fullest development of this aspect of Marx’s analysis in Capital,
in contradistinction to views advanced in works such as the Manifesto
and German Ideology, is
found in the work of Robert Brenner, whose socio-historical investigations into
“economic development” and critique of rival Smithian, Malthusian-Ricardian,
middle-Marxian, and Weberian accounts, have set the terms for a worldwide
debate among historians, economists, and sociologists. For critique of Smithian
(commerce-driven) views, see Robert
Brenner, The Origins of Capitalist Development: A Critique of
Neo-Smithian Marxism, I/104 New
Left Rev. 25 (1977); Robert
Brenner, Property and Progress: Where Adam Smith Went Wrong, in Marxist History-writing for the Twenty-first
Century 49 (Chris Wickham, ed. 2007). For critique of Malthusian-Ricardian (demographic-environmental)
views, see Robert Brenner, Agrarian Class
Structure and Economic Development in Pre-Industrial Europe, 70 Past & Present 30 (1976); Robert
Brenner, The Agrarian Roots of European Capitalism, 97 Past & Present 16 (1982). For critique of middle-Marxian
(technological-determinist) views, see
Robert Brenner, The Social Basis of
Economic Development, in Analytical
Marxism 23 (John Roemer, ed. 1986). For critique of Weberian (culturalist) views, see Robert Brenner, From
theory to history: ‘The European Dynamic’ or feudalism to capitalism? in An Anatomy of Power:
The Social Theory of Michael Mann 189 (John A. Hall & Ralph Schroeder, eds.) (2006). See generally The Brenner Debate (T.H. Alston & C.H.E. Philpin, eds.)
(1985); Peasants into Farmers? The
Transformation of Rural Economy and Society in the Low Countries (Middle Ages -
19th Century) in Light of the Brenner Debate (P. Hoppenbrouwers
& J. Luiten van Zanden eds., 2001). Neither Brenner nor the fundamental
empirical and theoretical issues posed for classical Marxism by the debate catalyzed
by his work are mentioned by Kessler. [8] For this argument as applied to
Hobsbawm, see Ellen Meiksins Wood, Marxism
and the Course of History, I/147 New
Left Rev. 95 (1984). For it as applied to Cohen, see Brenner, Social
Basis, supra note 8. [9] See Erik
Olin Wright, Giddens’ Critique of Marxism, I/138 New Left Rev. 11, 26 (1983). [10] Wood, supra note 9 at 101. [11] For discussion of a classic
case in this respect—of relative statis in Greek antiquity and mistaken
projections—see Moses Finley, Technical Innovation and Economic Progress in
the Ancient World, 18 Econ. Hist.
Rev. 45 (1965); Moses Finley, The Ancient Economy (1973). It should
hardly need adding that Professor Finley is not thereby meaning to denigrate
ancient Greek society or culture. [12] The bulk of the next two
paragraphs is taken from Yochai Benkler & Talha Syed, Reconstructing
Class Analysis, 4 J. L. Pol. Econ.
731, 735-40 (2024). There, we also criticize the other main variant of
historical materialism, the class struggle theory of history as conflict over
the production and appropriation of a “material surplus.” And we suggest that
it too is likely based on a transposition of relations and dynamics particular
to a specific society onto history as a whole, only now feudal ones, owing to the
way a “critical political economy” approach took over from classical political
economy a “materialist” model of “surplus extraction” that was likely most apt
for feudalism. [13] As such, it was a critique in
the Kantian sense of delimiting the conditions of possibility of the object of
critique. [14] Diane Elson, The Value
Theory of Labour, in Value: The
Representation of Labour in Capitalism 115 (Diane Elson, ed. 1981).
Elson is drawing upon, while deepening, the analysis of Isaak I. Rubin, Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value 62 (1928) (“The
usual short formulation of this theory holds that the value of the commodity
depends on the quantity of labor socially necessary for its production; or, in
a general formulation […] value = ‘materialized’ labor. It is more accurate to
express the theory inversely: in the commodity-capitalist economy,
production-work relations among people necessarily acquire the form of the
value of things[.]”). [15] Marx,
Capital, vol. 1, supra note 8 at 173-4 (“Political Economy has indeed analysed,
however incompletely, value and its magnitude, and has discovered what lies
beneath these forms. But it has never once asked the question why labour is
represented by the value of its product and labour time by the magnitude of
that value.”) (internal footnotes omitted). [16] See, e.g., Michael Heinrich, Capital after MEGA: Discontinuities, Interruptions, and New Beginnings, 3 Crisis & Critique 63 (2016); Riccardo
Bellofiore, The Multiple Meanings of
Marx’s Value Theory, 69 Monthly Rev. 31
(2018); Werner Bonefeld, Critical
Theory and the Critique of Political Economy (2014); Moishe Postone, Time,
Labor, and Social Domination (2003); Patrick Murray, Critical Theory and the Critique of
Political Economy: From Critical Political Economy to the Critique of Political
Economy, in The SAGE Handbook of
Frankfurt School Critical Theory 764 (Barbara Best, Werner Bonefield,
& Chris O’Kane, eds.) (2018). [17] In this respect, I find somewhat
puzzling Professor Kessler’s suggestion that my position may somehow lead to
“an overestimation of indeterminacy in law,” since the work of mine he cites
could not be clearer in its complete rejection of indeterminacy views. See Syed,
Legal Realism and CLS from an LPE Perspective at 17 (“the
indeterminacy critique is deeply misguided and should be jettisoned in toto,
be it for legal analysis of doctrine, concepts, or policy”). By
contrast, Kessler adopts a “some indeterminacy” view. Kessler, id. at
29-31. [18] On the variability of social
agency to historical shifts in understanding of the structures that are its
targets, see Perry Anderson,
Arguments within English Marxism
19-21 (1980).
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |