Balkinization  

Thursday, September 26, 2024

Law and the Critique of Political Economy

Guest Blogger

For the Balkinization Symposium on Jeremy Kessler, Law and Historical Materialism

Talha Syed 

Jeremy Kessler’s “Law and Historical Materialism” is bracing. Bracing in its unapologetic embrace of strong explanatory ambitions for any theory of law, one that must be anchored in a broader theory of society (and even of humanity’s interaction with the natural world). And bracing also in its no-pulled-punches approach to articulating dissatisfaction with existing legal theories, critical legal studies (CLS) principally among them. Sharing both commitments—not only in the content of the views, but also in the form of their unvarnished articulation—I will use this platform of agreement as the basis for launching an unvarnished critique of the alternative theory he offers.

Kessler’s intervention has two principal aims: to present to a legal audience a robust variant of the classical Marxist theory of history and society, historical materialism; and to defend it as a theory of law against various criticisms, principally those advanced by CLS. In respect of the first aim, the version of historical materialism advanced by Kessler is indeed of classical stripe: it is a theory of history as driven by the development of the (material) forces of production, in accord with which development arise and fall different (social) relations of production, and corresponding to which production relations are superstructural political and legal institutions and ideologies.[1] In reply to the central Crit objections to this view—namely, that it fails to attend to the indeterminacy, contingency, and autonomy of law[2]—Kessler advances a two-fold answer: historical materialism can account for these “apparent” features of law “at least as well as CLS and its successors,” while also making better sense of aspects of law that “CLS and its successors have struggled” with, in particular law’s resistance to reform and its tendency to reproduce social and economic hierarchies. 

There is one aspect of Professor Kessler’s argument with which I quite agree, and this is that classical Marxism has within it the resources to handle standard Crit objections based on law. As I have stated on a previous occasion—pointing to the same work of G.A. Cohen on which Kessler heavily relies—“the reasons for classical Marxism’s flaws have little to do with Crit claims from law’s autonomy, constitutive role, and indeterminacy. In fact, classical Marxism can defend itself quite well against these criticisms—indeed, it already did, avant la lettre of CLS.” I hasten to add that, as the passage just quoted indicates, my own view is that classical Marxism does have serious—indeed, as I will discuss next, fatal—flaws. But these go less to its theory of law than to its theory of society. Or, to be more precise, the flaws in its theory of law are tributary from flaws in its theory of society, and in either case the flaws have little to do with those pointed to by CLS. Indeed, and this is the nub of the present point, it is telling that the Crit objections were in fact addressed “avant la lettre” by G.A. Cohen—i.e., based on arguments made long before the Crits—and even more telling is that the Crit responses to Cohen were perfunctory and in passing at best.[3] 

These points are telling because they go to the twin bases of shared agreement I have with Professor Kessler: namely, that any social theory of law worth the name needs to be serious about its explanatory—conceptual and empirical—claims and that, in these respects at least, CLS views were wanting. This point has been perceptively driven home by Ntina Tzouvala, who urges that  “we need a more substantive, more analytically ambitious and less aestheticised idea of [] legal theory,” while CLS is often “better understood as an attachment to certain avant-garde aesthetics.” 

Yet it is precisely as an explanatory theory—both of society and of law—that I believe Kessler’s rehabilitation of classical Marxism fails. And its failure is not accidental or arbitrary but symptomatic, in ways that have much to tell us about the way forward for a critical theory of both society and law. Put succinctly, in each of its twin component parts—namely, the “materialist conception of history” and a “critical political economy”—classical Marxism involved the naturalization of historically-specific social relations and their projection onto history as a whole, in precisely the ways that Marx himself warned against in his mature critique of political economy. That critique was a denaturalizing analysis of capitalist relations and dynamics, showing at one and the same time how such relations and dynamics were historically-specific and yet naturalized by the eternal categories of the “classical political economy” of Smith and Ricardo. The great irony of classical Marxism is that it followed in precisely these false Smithian-Ricardian footsteps. 

Given the centrality Kessler accords to “naturalism” for any plausible explanatory theory of society and law, it is important to be clear about what is and is not meant by “denaturalizing” as a central aspect of Marx’s critical analysis of capitalist relations and dynamics. What is not meant is any repudiation of “naturalism” in substantive social inquiry where that is simply taken to mean, as it primarily seems to for Kessler, a methodological commitment that substantive theorizing be continuous with the protocols and findings of scientific analysis in general. (Kessler at 7.) Rather, the point of a denaturalizing critique is to point to the ways that something that is social, and historical, is falsely imputed to asocial, or transhistorical, natural givens. Further, to be effective, any such critique must supply its own alternative, more plausible, denaturalizing explanation of the phenomena at issue—for Marx, one advanced in terms of historically-specific social relations. 

We can see the point most clearly by zeroing in on the fundamental empirical difficulty facing the classical Marxist view, as recognized by two of its stoutest defenders, the historian Eric Hobsbawm and G.A. Cohen himself.[4] As Hobsbawm and Cohen both concede—the former more forthrightly, the latter more hesitantly—a key embarrassment facing historical materialism is the fact that it is only within capitalism that the “forces of production” exhibit a systematic tendency to grow.[5] Moreover, and shifting gears from empirical to conceptual registers, it is only within capitalism that a plausible explanatory mechanism exists to account for such growth, namely the “selection” effects of compulsive market pressures.[6] And what accounts for these pressures? For the Marx of Capital, it is neither Adam Smith’s “human nature” to “truck, barter, and exchange” nor Malthusian-Ricardian demographic-environmental constraints of population and soil fertility, but, rather, the historically-specific—not transhistorically-determined nor “contingent”—socio-political institutionalization of relations of generalized commodity production, whereby all economic agents are subjected to market-dependence by virtue of producers becoming “free in the double sense,” freed of both extra-economic forms of exploitation and the means of subsistence.[7] 

To state the point in more general terms, historical materialism on Kessler’s version is a theory of history as the march of “progress”: the development of human powers vis-à-vis nature (“technology”) via their envelopment in different social forms of production of a surplus (“class”). The relations of production that obtain at a given point in time are those best suited for the further development of productive forces, in light of given geographical, demographic, and technological conditions (the “forces of production” of nature, labor, tools). This view raises two key questions: how precisely do those relations most propitious to the development of the forces become adopted at a given point in time and, in any case, why exactly is the development of the forces of production the ultimate driver of history? The standard answers consist of an implausibly transhistorical view of asocial drivers of the development of material forces, and an implausibly functionalist view of the selection of social relations to develop these. These fail both empirically and explanatorily. Empirically, because there are long stretches of history where the forces do not develop but rather “petrify”—they only systematically develop within capitalism. Explanatorily, because no plausible mechanism(s) is/are identified to select the social relations that optimally develop the forces—it is only within capitalist social relations that such a mechanism, for the selection of productive forces, exists: economic competition driven by imperatives of generalized market-dependence. And so we can now see this view for what it is: a transposition of the historically-specific social relations of capitalism and its dynamics—technological dynamism propelled by generalized markets—onto history as a whole, via a naturalizing of capitalist social relations as a kind of ahistorical materialist rationality of homo economicus (ingenuity and instrumental rationality in conditions of scarcity).[8] This explains both the empirical and explanatory gaps of the view: only once you have capitalist social relations do you get either the empirical result (sustained productivity) or the explanation (selection by generalized markets). In sum, the “forces” theory is the clearest (but not only) case of a historical materialist view that turns out, upon closer inspection, to be a naturalization of the relations and dynamics of a specific society and their projection onto all of history. 

I need to make two important clarifications. First, the empirical point being pressed here is not that there is no (incremental, jagged) growth in productive forces for much of history, only that significant, systematic development is specific to the modern—capitalist—epoch, with earlier eras marked by long periods of relative stasis. That there has been some growth—in part because once acquired, productive facilities are rarely given up, so that development is “sticky downward”[9]is no doubt true, but this provides a slender basis for any (transhistorical) explanatory theory of society.[10] To think otherwise likely owes to a projection of capitalist dynamics onto history as a whole.[11] And similar projections may fuel a possible misunderstanding of the present point, which is that it somehow vaunts “economic development” or growth in productive forces as desirable in itself, and perhaps even denigrates societies not significantly marked by it. But nothing of the sort is indicated here. In particular, two points need to be made in reply to this concern: first, whatever evaluative attitude we wish to adopt toward such growth, the issue here is about the explanatory power of a specific social theory, and for that the empirical realities of such growth need to be addressed; second the position being advanced here takes, as discussed next, a decidedly jaundiced view of capitalist growth, as a form of systematically “alienated productivity.” Indeed it is precisely the way Marx’s denaturalizing mode of analysis is able to solder an explanation of a phenomenon with its critique, that marks out his mature critique of political economy as a matter of method. 

This brings us to the second key component of the classical Marxism advocated by Kessler, going not to its theory of history—historical materialism—but to its theory of a specific society, capitalism.[12] The classical understanding of Marx’s project is as a “critical political economy,” one that joins classical political economy in its analysis of a “material” field of inquiry, but radicalizes the classicals’ surplus-based analysis of growth, distribution, and classes by refining and extending it in the vein of a labor theory of surplus-value, profits, and exploitation. This conception of Marx’s project faces two difficulties. A first is substantive deficits in its analysis of the problems it focuses on—including, principally, those afflicting a theory of class based on “the labor theory of value.” Second, an even deeper set of drawbacks concern the limited horizon of the problems themselves. 

On an alternative view, Marx’s project was less a critical political economy than a critique of political economy. On this conception, Marx’s aim was not to join classical political economy in its analysis of a naturalized field of inquiry, but to delimit the conditions of possibility of the field itself, in terms of the historically-specific social relations of capital that constitute its proper object of inquiry.[13] His focus is best understood not in terms of a Ricardian analysis of property-based distribution, but of an analysis of the social relations of production themselves. In Diane Elson’s illuminating encapsulation, we need to shift from a “labor theory of value” to a value theory of labor.[14] The first refers to an attempt to take over the surplus-based analysis of classical political economy and provide a quantitative theory of price, profit, or exploitation—an attempt ill-fated in both its explanatory and evaluative facets. The second refers to an analysis not of the “material content” of “value” in labor, but rather of the social form taken by labor (and utility) under capitalist social relations[15]—i.e., a qualitative analysis of how human powers and needs are shaped by generalized commodity production and subjected to its impersonal imperatives of ceaseless expansion of exchange-value for its own sake. The result? A systematic alienation of social powers and relations, as not only human needs and powers but also human relations and the Earth are subjected to ever-more extensive and intensive instrumental quantification. 

This critical strand of Marxian thought, long submerged under a crust of materialist overlay within the classical Marxist tradition, is currently undergoing a worldwide revival.[16] It is one that left legal scholars would do well to join. Especially since recovering and fully developing it is something that legal academics are particularly well-placed to undertake, as doing so would also involve recovering and fully developing a distinct strand of legal theory. This is a submerged aspect of Legal Realist analysis, one that fully eschews the dominant “internal” and “external” critiques of formalism associated with Realism, and advances instead a dereification critique that forms a close counterpart to the denaturalization critique of political economy. This critique takes law to be a human artifact serving human interests, with lucidity about the structure and purposes of that artifact (its forms and means) being the first step toward effectiveness in pursuit of those interests. 

This legal strand has its deepest roots in the work of Hohfeld, with the analysis of the social relations of modern law as rights being a micro-institutional counterpart to the macro-institutional component of the critique of political economy, with its analysis of the social relations of market-dependence. Such social relations, while in no way “materially” determined, are also in no way “legally constructed,” nor simply indeterminately up for grabs. It is only by understanding their architectural systematicity that they can be strategically targeted for effective transformation. What matters in law is neither “indeterminacy” (wholly misguided) nor “autonomy” (of what, from what?) but, rather, social agency.[17] Such agency can be neither assumed nor foreclosed. It is, rather, entirely variable, expanding or contracting depending on how lucid is our social understanding of the relations meriting change and how effective are our social practices of transformation.[18] 

In the debate between CLS and classical Marxism, many may be tempted to stake out a halfway position, a compromise of some sort between “some” legal indeterminacy (or autonomy) and “some” material constraint. That would be a mistake. It would be a mistake because both poles of this spectrum are simply ill-conceived. We need to fully jettison all talk of both “indeterminacy” and “materialism,” as holdovers of deeply misguided strands of both CLS and Marxism. In their stead, we need to recover submerged strands of critical traditions, both in the critique of law and of political economy. As those traditions teach, constraint comes not from material factors but from social relations, and social agency (not autonomy, much less indeterminacy) is neither foreclosed nor guaranteed but, rather, earned, through understanding and practice directed at transformation.

Talha Syed is Lecturer in Law at U.C. Berkeley. You can reach him by e-mail at tsyed@law.berkeley.edu. 



[1] As Professor Kessler acknowledges, this “forces of production” view is only one of the two main variants of the classical Marxist theory of historical materialism, the other being “class struggle” as “the motor force of history.” He suggests that, should the forces theory face infirmities that the class struggle theory can better handle, his account of historical materialism can take on the latter as a “friendly amendment.” Jeremy Kessler, Law and Historical Materialism at 6-7, fn. 18. Since, as discussed below at note 12, my argument pertains to both variants of the classical theory, I set aside this issue here.

[2] I should clarify that this is Professor Kessler’s list of the Crit objections to classical Marxism, not my own. Id. at 2, 51. I myself believe this list does not articulate the Crit view at its strongest, since by themselves, these hardly count as compelling objections: only if law is also constitutive, or shaping, of social relations does the fact that it is autonomous (indeterminate, contingent) matter, since otherwise law’s role in society is minor and hence what shapes it only a peripheral concern for a social theory. This matters because, as discussed above, I share Professor Kessler’s commitment to rigor in social analysis, while the laundry-list style of Crit objections that Professor Kessler adopts here, while a common practice, does not advance that aim.

[3] Thus, the most sustained Crit engagement with Cohen, by Mark Tushnet, offers in the course of two pages a pair of highly abstract “skepticisms” with virtually no substantiating argument. Mark Tushnet, Is there a Marxist Theory of Law?, 26 Nomos 171, 182-3 (1983). Professor Tushnet subsequently seemed to recognize the thin character of his objections, stating that “[f]or reasons that I do not understand, the challenge to cls from the traditional Left has not picked up on G.A. Cohen's rehabilitation of classical Marxist theory.” Mark Tushnet, Critical Legal Studies: A Political History, 100 Yale L. J. 1515, 1529 n. 57 (1991). The next most serious engagement, by Robert Gordon, similarly expressed doubts in passing about Cohen’s admittedly “extremely ingenious” argument, without any sustained rebuttal—and this despite his article being primarily devoted to debunking “functionalist” theories of law and Cohen’s argument already gaining traction as the most sophisticated rehabilitation of functionalist analysis. See Robert W. Gordon, Critical Legal Histories, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 57, 105-6 (1984). Roberto Unger, for his part, did take Cohen’s theory more seriously, but not in its legal aspects. See Roberto Mangabeira Unger, Social Theory: Its Situation and Its Task 93-96, 230-31 (1984). Finally, Duncan Kennedy’s one reference to Cohen took the form of a “but see” footnote appended to the following sentence: “But maybe materialist explanations for the presence or absence of property consciousness under particular material circumstances are already available, and I’m just not aware of them (I doubt it).” Duncan Kennedy, The Role of Law in Economic Thought: Essays on the Fetishism of Commodities, 34 Amer. U. L. Rev. 939, 993 (1985).

[4] Hobsbawm and Cohen both take as their touchstone text the locus classicus of the forces-of-production variant of classical Marxism: the 1859 Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. For Hobsbawm, this “presents historical materialism in its most pregnant form” and this characterization is approvingly cited by Cohen his book, the epigraph for which is provided by the central passage of the Preface. Eric J. Hobsbawm, Introduction in Karl Marx, Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations 10 (E. J. Hobsbawm, ed., Jack Cohen, trans.) (1964); G.A. Cohen, Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defense vii-viii, x (2000 2nd ed.) (1978).

[5] See Eric J. Hobsbawm, Marx and History, I/143 New Left Rev. 39, 43-44 (1984); Cohen, id. at 169-171. See also id. at 248 (“The fact that capitalism did not arise spontaneously outside of Europe is a serious problem for historical materialism.”) For relevant empirical data, see Angus Maddison, The World Economy: A Millennial Perspective (2001).

[6] For criticism of Cohen emphasizing this explanatory, as opposed to the empirical, lacuna see Erik Olin Wright & Andrew Levine, Rationality and Class Struggle, I/123 New Left Rev. 47 (1980). For a combined criticism of both gaps, see Joshua Cohen, Book Review, 79 J. Phil. 253 (1982) (reviewing Cohen). Kessler acknowledges a related—but distinct—explanatory issue, going to Cohen’s reliance on functional explanations in general, rather than the specific difficulties he faces in providing a plausible account of actual long-term historical processes. Kessler, id. at 6-7. And even here he simply acknowledges the concern without attempting to address it. As for the fundamental empirical point, he leaves it untouched. These are troubling gaps in an argument that emphasizes explanatory superiority as a key advantage of the theory it is advocating.

[7] Karl Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 874-75, 272-73 (Ben Fowkes trans., 1976) (1867). It is to be regretted that the new translation of Capital by Paul Reitter, in other respects quite excellent, has dropped this now-canonical formulation of “free in the double sense.” The fullest development of this aspect of Marx’s analysis in Capital, in contradistinction to views advanced in works such as the Manifesto and German Ideology, is found in the work of Robert Brenner, whose socio-historical investigations into “economic development” and critique of rival Smithian, Malthusian-Ricardian, middle-Marxian, and Weberian accounts, have set the terms for a worldwide debate among historians, economists, and sociologists. For critique of Smithian (commerce-driven) views, see Robert Brenner, The Origins of Capitalist Development: A Critique of Neo-Smithian Marxism, I/104 New Left Rev. 25 (1977); Robert Brenner, Property and Progress: Where Adam Smith Went Wrong, in Marxist History-writing for the Twenty-first Century 49 (Chris Wickham, ed. 2007). For critique of Malthusian-Ricardian (demographic-environmental) views, see Robert Brenner, Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Development in Pre-Industrial Europe, 70 Past & Present 30 (1976); Robert Brenner, The Agrarian Roots of European Capitalism, 97 Past & Present 16 (1982). For critique of middle-Marxian (technological-determinist) views, see Robert Brenner, The Social Basis of Economic Development, in Analytical Marxism 23 (John Roemer, ed. 1986). For critique of Weberian (culturalist) views, see Robert Brenner, From theory to history: ‘The European Dynamic’ or feudalism to capitalism? in An Anatomy of Power: The Social Theory of Michael Mann 189 (John A. Hall & Ralph Schroeder, eds.) (2006). See generally The Brenner Debate (T.H. Alston & C.H.E. Philpin, eds.) (1985); Peasants into Farmers? The Transformation of Rural Economy and Society in the Low Countries (Middle Ages - 19th Century) in Light of the Brenner Debate (P. Hoppenbrouwers & J. Luiten van Zanden eds., 2001). Neither Brenner nor the fundamental empirical and theoretical issues posed for classical Marxism by the debate catalyzed by his work are mentioned by Kessler.

[8] For this argument as applied to Hobsbawm, see Ellen Meiksins Wood, Marxism and the Course of History, I/147 New Left Rev. 95 (1984). For it as applied to Cohen, see Brenner, Social Basis, supra note 8.

[9] See Erik Olin Wright, Giddens’ Critique of Marxism, I/138 New Left Rev. 11, 26 (1983).

[10] Wood, supra note 9 at 101.

[11] For discussion of a classic case in this respect—of relative statis in Greek antiquity and mistaken projections—see Moses Finley, Technical Innovation and Economic Progress in the Ancient World, 18 Econ. Hist. Rev. 45 (1965); Moses Finley, The Ancient Economy (1973). It should hardly need adding that Professor Finley is not thereby meaning to denigrate ancient Greek society or culture.

[12] The bulk of the next two paragraphs is taken from Yochai Benkler & Talha Syed, Reconstructing Class Analysis, 4 J. L. Pol. Econ. 731, 735-40 (2024). There, we also criticize the other main variant of historical materialism, the class struggle theory of history as conflict over the production and appropriation of a “material surplus.” And we suggest that it too is likely based on a transposition of relations and dynamics particular to a specific society onto history as a whole, only now feudal ones, owing to the way a “critical political economy” approach took over from classical political economy a “materialist” model of “surplus extraction” that was likely most apt for feudalism.

[13] As such, it was a critique in the Kantian sense of delimiting the conditions of possibility of the object of critique.

[14] Diane Elson, The Value Theory of Labour, in Value: The Representation of Labour in Capitalism 115 (Diane Elson, ed. 1981). Elson is drawing upon, while deepening, the analysis of Isaak I. Rubin, Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value 62 (1928) (“The usual short formulation of this theory holds that the value of the commodity depends on the quantity of labor socially necessary for its production; or, in a general formulation […] value = ‘materialized’ labor. It is more accurate to express the theory inversely: in the commodity-capitalist economy, production-work relations among people necessarily acquire the form of the value of things[.]”).

[15] Marx, Capital, vol. 1, supra note 8 at 173-4 (“Political Economy has indeed analysed, however incompletely, value and its magnitude, and has discovered what lies beneath these forms. But it has never once asked the question why labour is represented by the value of its product and labour time by the magnitude of that value.”) (internal footnotes omitted).

[16] See, e.g., Michael Heinrich, Capital after MEGA: Discontinuities, Interruptions, and New Beginnings, 3 Crisis & Critique 63 (2016); Riccardo Bellofiore, The Multiple Meanings of Marx’s Value Theory, 69 Monthly Rev. 31 (2018); Werner Bonefeld, Critical Theory and the Critique of Political Economy (2014); Moishe Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination (2003); Patrick Murray, Critical Theory and the Critique of Political Economy: From Critical Political Economy to the Critique of Political Economy, in The SAGE Handbook of Frankfurt School Critical Theory 764 (Barbara Best, Werner Bonefield, & Chris O’Kane, eds.) (2018).

[17] In this respect, I find somewhat puzzling Professor Kessler’s suggestion that my position may somehow lead to “an overestimation of indeterminacy in law,” since the work of mine he cites could not be clearer in its complete rejection of indeterminacy views. See Syed, Legal Realism and CLS from an LPE Perspective at 17 (“the indeterminacy critique is deeply misguided and should be jettisoned in toto, be it for legal analysis of doctrine, concepts, or policy”). By contrast, Kessler adopts a “some indeterminacy” view. Kessler, id. at 29-31.

[18] On the variability of social agency to historical shifts in understanding of the structures that are its targets, see Perry Anderson, Arguments within English Marxism 19-21 (1980).




Older Posts
Newer Posts
Home