Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Imagining America’s Collaborative Constitution: Part II
|
Saturday, September 28, 2024
Imagining America’s Collaborative Constitution: Part II
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Aileen Kavanagh, The Collaborative Constitution (Cambridge University Press, 2023). Aileen Kavanagh Of Norms and Forms As
Professor
Stephen Gardbaum rightly observes, The Collaborative Constitution emphasises
the fundamental importance of unwritten norms in all constitutional
systems. Even in a country with a
revered constitutional text like the United States, the normative force of that
text depends crucially on whether the key constitutional actors treat that text
as normative and binding on their behaviour. This is the signature insight of H.L.A.
Hart that all law bottoms out in non-law (i.e. in social norms), and at
that level what matters most is whether the people in power commit to the
constitutional rules of the game - aptly described by Josh
Chafetz as ‘the ethics of constitutional commitment’. Absent that commitment, the written text
becomes a hollow hope – a ‘parchment barrier’ devoid of authority and
force. Beneath the constitutional forms
lie norms; and beneath the constitutional architecture lie attitudes. Instead of embracing the formal idea of ‘constitution
as architecture’, my book explores the deeper terrain of ‘constitutionalism
as mindset’. Gardbaum
poses two key questions about this analysis.
First, if these norms are as foundational to all constitutional
systems, does this flatten out the differences between systems and make my
account ‘oblivious to context’? Second,
does my analysis overlook the consequential – and variable - impact of
constitutional design on how a system works?
In emphasising norms, do I underestimate forms? My
answer to both of those questions is ‘no’.
In drawing attention to ‘the ubiquity of
unwritten constitutionalism’, I do not underestimate the valence and
variability of constitutional design. As
Gardbaum observes, constitutional design creates different basic structures of
democratic politics. Fundamental design
choices – such as whether there is a parliamentary or presidential system -
makes a big difference to how institutions act and interact in a structured
constitutional scheme. I agree with
Gardbaum on this. Design matters - and design
differs - with myriad consequential effects for the success and sustainability
of any constitutional system. However,
Gardbaum is right to discern a degree of scepticism about the centrality of
design in contemporary constitutional scholarship. I did not make questions of constitutional
design central to The Collaborative Constitution for a number of
reasons. First, the crux of my argument
is that constitutional government goes well when all the key constitutional
actors work together to achieve just government under the Constitution. This applies to all systems, regardless
of their (significant) differences in constitutional design. As I say in the book, collaborative
constitutionalism is not inexorably tied to any particular constitutional
structure. It lives primarily in the
unwritten norms of comity, collaboration, and constrained conflict which sit at
the foundation of any constitutional order.
True, some
constitutional designs may be more conducive to effective collaboration than
others. It may be that presidential
systems lead to more conflict and gridlock than their parliamentary
counterparts. The U.S. system may be
more prone to constitutional showdowns than Westminster systems. Nonetheless, even in a presidential system,
the branches of government must work together in various ways to get things
done. It cannot be conflict all the
time; and it cannot be conflict all the way down. The art of politics is compromise and
accommodation – and this applies as much in Washington as it does in
Westminster. Even the American President
must sometimes reach across the aisle.
This is not to deny the deep differences between both systems. It is simply to say that The Collaborative
Constitution articulates an ideal which applies to them both, albeit in
different ways. Second, the
current context of democratic decay and constitutional corrosion should lead us
to be modest about what design alone can deliver. When reflecting on Poland’s constitutional
breakdown, Wojciech Sadurski
observed that when authoritarian leaders take over, ‘there is very little that
even a well-crafted constitution can do’.
Though Sadurski did not deny the importance of good design for a
well-functioning system, he was struck by ‘the
relative irrelevance of formal constitutional design’. When push comes to shove – and it’s coming to
shove in many systems around the world – no amount of beautiful design or
intricate structure can save a constitutional democracy. The ultimate question, then, is whether those
in power will commit to the constitutional rules of the game. And that commitment is ‘extra-legal’ – it
lies in the realm of the unwritten. In a system with a
codified constitutional text such as the United States, it is tempting to think
that a sacred text will save us from all evil.
And yet, Donald Trump’s most problematic behaviour was targeted not at
the written constitutional text, but at the unwritten norms which give that
text meaning and constitutional integrity.
The moral of the story is that we should decenter sacred texts and
Supreme Courts in our understanding of what makes constitutions work. In drawing attention to the fundamentality of
unwritten constitutional norms, The Collaborative Constitution contributes
to that decentering process. It enjoins
us to study constitutional texts in the context of constitutional culture. Finally, when
writing The Collaborative Constitution, my book was in conversation with
leading comparative constitutional law taxonomists - including Stephen Gardbaum
and Mark Tushnet – who distinguished between systems of ‘strong-form’
and ‘weak-form review’, on the basis of a) whether courts had the power to
strike down legislation and b) whether legislatures had the power to override
court decisions in the relative short-term.
In that taxonomy, the U.S. was regarded as a paradigm of ‘strong-form
review’ and the UK was an emblem of ‘weak-form review’. Responding to Gardbaum and Tushnet, I wrote
an article called ‘What’s so Weak
about Weak-Form Review?’, uncovering the hidden strengths of so-called
weak-form review in the UK system. Here
is not the place to revisit this debate. But my main point was this: by
leaning so heavily on the formal features of constitutional design - detached
from an appreciation of how those features worked in practice - this taxonomy
ran the risk of misjudging institutional strength and weakness across a variety
of systems. To be clear, the take-home
is not that design is irrelevant or that context doesn’t matter. It’s precisely the opposite. The key main take-home is that we should look
at constitutional design in the context of constitutional culture. We should study the norms and forms of
constitutional democracy as part of a holistic constitutional analysis. Conflict and Collaboration; showdown and
slowdown Professor
Mark Tushnet provides an illuminating analysis of the relationship between
conflict and collaboration in The Collaborative Constitution. Carving up the terrain in ways I didn’t
anticipate – but in ways I find enormously generative – Tushnet argues that my
book opens the way for us to construct an account of constitutional meaning
that integrates the quotidian and the conflictual. Tushnet’s analysis highlights three crucial
points. First, he
clarifies that collaborative constitutionalism does not preclude conflict or
contestation. Rather, it presents a picture
of constrained conflict, regulated
rivalry, and disciplined democratic competition, where conflict
is the exception not the norm. Though it
can’t be conflict all the time, or conflict all the way down, this does not
preclude pockets of conflict in a broader collaborative scheme. By aligning
collaboration with the quotidian - and conflict with the exceptional - Tushnet
usefully highlights the complex co-existence of conflict and collaboration in
any system. This opens up rich and
productive lines of inquiry. Does the
quotidian and conflictual shift over time?
What prevents the conflictual becoming the quotidian, and vice versa? How do we deal with confusion about the
quotidian? What are the dark sides of
‘collaborative equilibria’? My book
doesn’t answer these questions directly or fully, but it gives us a place to
start. Second, Tushnet
shows that in order to work out whether a system is ‘collaborative’ – and, if
so, how, and to what extent – we need to engage in a multi-level, multi-site,
and multi-institutional analysis, all viewed dynamically over time. We should beware of focusing only on the
flashpoints of friction today. We need
to situate those conflictual episodes in a longer and deeper constitutional
trajectory. Tushnet also helpfully
highlights the mundane aspect of the constitutional quotidian. When reading Tushnet’s analysis, I was
reminded of Max Weber’s insight that ‘politics
is the hard and slow boring of hard boards’. The same is true of constitutional
government. Though glamorous theories of
‘agonistic constitutionalism’ are undoubtedly alluring, they do not capture the
quotidian demands of stable constitutional democracy over time. Third, Tushnet
indirectly highlights the value of interbranch conflict in any system –
not only episodic conflicts on particularly acute issues, but also system-wide
constitutional change which may lead to enhanced constitutionalism under a
radically reconfigured constitutional regime.
Of course, if a regime is deeply dysfunctional, then a radical change is
required. However, if a system is
relatively well-functioning - albeit with significant problems and challenges -
then the calculus is different. In this
scenario, Tushnet and I may have different baselines. I would build in a strong status-quo bias,
attentive to the value of stability, and alert to the significant risks - and
possibly counterproductive effects - of radical constitutional change. In The
Collaborative Constitution, I argue that constitutional
slowdown is a preferable modus vivendi to constitutional showdown –
at least in the quotidian. By ‘constitutional
slowdown’, I mean a commitment by the key political actors to channel
proposed legal changes through the required institutional law-making
processes. Undoubtedly, this slows the
system down. As Tushnet says, it can be
an ‘impediment’ to good as well as bad policy change. And yet, we toss those impediments aside at
our peril. Particularly in an age of
political polarisation, we need the mutual assurance that regardless of who
comes to power, they must all commit to the basic ground-rules of
governance. There is no
constitutionalism with shortcuts. There
is only the long, hard, painstaking process of making law in a way which is
compliant with constitutional and democratic norms. This may impede good policy on occasion. But this is the price we pay for a stable,
well-functioning system of constitutional government where everyone is required
to respect the rules of the game in a spirit of fair play. Collaboration and Interpretation As
Professor Solum rightly observes, I have nothing to say in my book about the
debate between originalists and living constitutionalists under the U.S.
Constitution (though I have written about originalism
and living
constitutionalism in the past).
However, though The Collaborative Constitution does not speak
directly to the originalism/living
constitutionalism/constitutional supremacy debate, my book bears on it in a
number of indirect ways. For one thing, if
we situate judges within The Collaborative Constitution - locating them
in their relationship of partnership with the political branches - this has
implications for how we understand the judicial role. In particular, it forces us to grapple with
the relational dimensions of judging and the ways in which judges
interact with the political branches when adjudicating whether laws comply with
the Constitution. Once we do this,
new questions come to the fore. Are
judges agents or partners of Congress?
Should judges tell Congress what to do, or should they defer to it? What are the normative foundations of the
duty of judicial deference, if such exists? If judges should defer, when? How
much? Why? Should judges calibrate the intensity of their review, reserving
light-touch ‘rational basis’ scrutiny for some issues and hard look scrutiny
for others? Are some issues non-justiciable? Why?
When should judges use the Ashwander
doctrine and when should they strike down the law as violating the
Constitution? How should judges approach
constitutional remedies? Though these questions
are not central the originalism/living constitutionalism debate (as I
understand it), they are vitally important to decision-making by the U.S.
Supreme Court. In my book, I
grapple with these questions, reflecting on canons of construction,
presumptions of constitutionality, clear
statement rules, variable standards of review, constitutional remedies,
doctrines of deference and justiciability, constitutional
minimalism, and the so-called ’passive
virtues’ (which, I argue, are better conceived as ‘collaborative
devices’). Charting an iterative and
interactive dynamic between judges and politics – which I sometimes describe as
‘judge
as nudge’ and ‘court
as catalyst’ - I draw on the rich American literature on ‘prods
and pleas’, ‘constitutional
flares’ etc. I defend the idea of calibrated
constitutional review, where judges calibrate the intensity of review in
light of a number of substantive and institutional factors at play in the
case. Based on a judicial
role-conception which I call ‘judge
as partner’, I situate judging in a joint enterprise, drawing out its
collaborative dimensions. And I am not
alone. Professor Dan
Coenen has argued that many of these doctrines – including clear statement
rules, form-based deliberation rules, time-driven second-look rules,
constitutional sunset rules, and constitutional common law – together comprise
a Constitution
of Collaboration. My analysis
suggests two things. One: although the
originalism/living constitutionalism debate is critically important, it occupies
only a small slice of the adjudicatory action undertaken by the Supreme
Court. Two: The Collaborative
Constitution puts interpretive questions in a broader constitutional
context – looking not just at the relationship between judge and text, but between
judges and politics, courts and Congress, and even judges and the People. On the collaborative vision, we need to
situate interpretation in a broader collaborative context. Viewed in that larger landscape, judges look
less like Herculean heroes pronouncing from on high, and more like partners in
a collaborative enterprise where they have a significant, but subordinate, role
to play. Collaboration, Devolution, Disagreement In an incisive
analysis, Professor
Delaney highlights the important issue of devolved government in the UK
system. Though I didn’t discuss this
issue in my book, I believe that collaborative devolution is both
possible and desirable. Just this week,
the House
of Lords Constitution Committee published a report on The
Governance of the Union: Consultation, Co-operation and Legislative Consent,
urging the UK Government ‘to build and maintain a more effective Union,
characterised by respect for, and co-operation with, the governments and
legislatures of the devolved nations’.
Recognising the importance of a ‘cooperative
mindset’ for devolution to work, the Report emphasises the value of
‘working together on the development and implementation of policies of common
concern’ in a spirit of ‘goodwill and co-operation’. As Professor
Stephen Tierney observes, this echoes comparable principles of solidarity,
comity or Bundesteue found in other territorial and federal
constitutions. These are the norms of The
Collaborative Constitution. For
devolution to work, it must be collaborative at its core. Though Delaney
acknowledges that devolution in Scotland, Wales, and Northern Ireland is
‘latticed with frameworks, committees, and admonitions to act responsibly and
with respect’, she is nonetheless struck by the conflicts and tensions, the
disagreements and disappointments which have plagued devolution in the
post-Brexit period. Is this a
‘devolutionary fly in the collaborative ointment’? Or does it point to a deeper and broader
problem with the idea of The Collaborative Constitution? In my view,
Delaney’s analysis can be generalised across the entire UK constitutional
order. It is not that human
rights protection in the UK is cosy and collaborative, whereas devolution
provides a fierce nexus of conflict. Both
of these issues generated ongoing political controversy, especially in the
fractious post-Brexit era. Delaney
helpfully highlights that the UK is not a highly consensual constitutional
system where collaboration comes easy.
On the contrary, it is riven by the usual political, social,
ideological, geographic, and moral points of controversy that we find in other
systems. Both Larry Solum and Erin
Delaney are correct: when we look at our constitutional systems in the 21st
century, fierce conflict comes to the fore and the delicate collaborative
latticework recedes into the background.
So that begs the
question: when writing The Collaborative Constitution, did I sing myself
to sleep with a constitutional lullaby about continued collaboration in
troubled times? Was I naïve about the
depth and dynamics of political conflict in the UK and elsewhere? Was I donning the rose-tinted glasses to
inoculate myself against the rising tide of constitutional hardball, averting
my gaze from the dirty tricks of Donald Trump and Boris Johnson alike? The opposite was in fact the case. I was writing The Collaborative
Constitution during a period of intense political upheaval, both in the UK
and elsewhere around the world. As a
political observer - and someone who cares deeply about the value of
constitutional government under the rule of law - I was both alert and
appalled. I followed the daily
news-cycle – and I read the avalanche of best-selling books with titles such as
Constitutional
Democracy in Crisis, How
Democracy Ends, and How
Democracies Dies. I added
them to my already large collection of books with titles such as The Constitution in
Conflict, When
Courts and Congress Collide, and Contest
for Constitutional Authority.
Of course, as
constitutional lawyers, we must be attentive to conflict and crisis. If collaborative frameworks are put in place
– as they were for the devolution settlement in the UK – we must inquire into
whether they work and if not, why not?
But the aim of my book was not to join the long line of laments and
pronounce a ‘polycrisis’. It was to
provide a new conceptual and linguistic register in which to study
constitutional dynamics - one that sounds more in responsibility and restraint,
than in conflict and confrontation.
Whilst leading theorists foreground a conflictual narrative of
‘constitutional hardball’, my book seeks to reorient the inquiry towards more
constructive questions about how to resolve disagreements and reduce
conflicts in order to make them politically productive and constitutionally
tractable. Somebody’s got to be the
adult in the room. And that person is
typically not asking for more high-octane conflict and constitutional
showdowns. They are typically asking for
civility and respect, and a joint commitment to work together in a spirit of
fair play. In short, they’re calling for
The Collaborative Constitution. Of course, we are
all fascinated by conflict and crisis.
Conflict sells copy. It provides
good red meat for a media with an insatiable appetite for news. And constitutional lawyers are not immune
from the drama of dissensus. We sit up
and listen when the court strikes down and politicians strike back. We celebrate the blockbuster cases. And we give constitutional villains plenty of
airtime. The constitutional tragedy of
Trump may be appalling, but it’s also riveting.
We all want a piece of the action at a constitutional showdown -
or a front-row seat at least. In
comparison to this high-octane drama, the quotidian dynamics of collaborative
constitutionalism – the painstaking process of constitutional slowdown;
the ‘slow boring of hard boards’; the disciplining demands of self-restraint
and forbearance - will naturally struggle to compete. Who needs latticework when you’ve got
fireworks? The
Collaborative Constitution does not naively deny
the existence of conflict. Instead, it
discerns a duty of respect, civility, and fair play between interdependent
actors who have a shared responsibility to make constitutional democracy
work. It calls on our elected
representatives to do good and, yes, to do better. Collaboration is the goal - and getting there
is not easy. I lament the
erosion of unwritten constitutional norms across the world in recent
times. I don’t want the rot to set
in. But our laments deserve a
lodestar. Before pronouncing a
constitutional crisis where all norms have broken down, we need to pose some tough
questions: how can we combine democracy and diversity? How can we get rival political parties and
branches of government with pluralist perspectives to work together and treat
each other as adversaries not enemies?
How do we make the fundamental rules of the game part of the
constitutional quotidian? What does a
healthy body-politic look like? The
Collaborative Constitution does not provide all the
answers to these questions by any means.
It is written more in an analytical than a prescriptive register. It does not provide a blueprint. Nonetheless, I think it is pointing us in the
right direction – and maybe America is already there, at least to some degree. As I see it, collaborative constitutionalism
lies deep in the DNA of the American constitutional order. Let’s step back from the headline news and
imagine the tradition and trajectory of America’s Collaborative Constitution. Aileen
Kavanagh holds the Chair of Constitutional Governance at Trinity College
Dublin, where
she is Director of TriCON, the Trinity Centre for Constitutional
Governance. She will be speaking about The
Collaborative Constitution at Columbia University on October 23rd,
Boston College on Oct 28th, and Harvard Law School on October 30th.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |