Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts The Collective Action Constitution(s)
|
Thursday, August 29, 2024
The Collective Action Constitution(s)
JB
For the Balkinization Symposium on Neil S. Siegel, The Collective-Action Constitution (Oxford University Press, 2024) The basic thesis of The Collective-Action Constitution is that one should interpret the U.S. Constitution so that the national government is empowered to solve collective action problems among the various states. Siegel argues that this collective action principle also explains much of the design of the 1787 Constitution. The argument can be originalist but it need not be. It is a structuralist argument focused on contemporary solutions to contemporary problems. Many people have made arguments of this kind before in particular contexts, but no one, to my knowledge, has offered as comprehensive an account of the entire Constitution and its various provisions through the lens of collective action. It is a remarkable achievement that is unlikely to be surpassed. Siegel tries to show that much of existing doctrine in many different areas of constitutional law is consistent with collective action reasoning. Nevertheless, he is critical of some aspects of current doctrine, and he thinks that some of the Court's doctrines, for example, the economic/non-economic distinction in United States v. Lopez and United States v. Morrison, are best defended as proxies for collective action reasoning, although they are very imperfect proxies. In this blog post, I'll explain why Siegel's theory, although phrased in terms of structural reasoning, actually leads inevitably to a legal process theory. In order to work in practice, a collective action theory requires a series of complicated and contestable factual and normative judgments about the existence and extent of collective action problems, as well as the appropriate solutions. Since different people will make different judgments about these matters, the question becomes who decides-- the classic legal process question. Thus, a collective action theory quickly turns into the question of which actors in the political system are most competent or most democratically authorized to resolve these complicated and potentially unknowable factual and normative questions. The complexity of these questions, I believe, justifies Siegel's general view that courts should defer to Congressional judgments. This includes deference to Congress's construction of the administrative state, which in practice makes a large number of federal policy decisions. Nevertheless, Siegel's account of the Collective Action Constitution is not the only possible one. In fact, there are many possible Collective Action Constitutions based on his central principle. I will try to explain why that is so. I. The Problems of Collective Action Problems Siegel identifies three kinds of collective action problems that might exist in a federal republic like the United States. Coordination problems are those in which "some or all states would need to coordinate their behavior to solve a problem but there are multiple possible ways of doing so and there may be disagreements about how to do so." Coordination problems are a special case of a larger category of Pareto-optimal collective action problems. These are collective action problems in which "all states would be better off by their own estimations if collective action succeeded." However, Siegel explains, most collective action problems in American politics do not fit into this category. Most situations involve "cost-benefit" collective action problems, "in which some states would regard themselves as better off if collective action succeeded but other states would regard themselves as worse off," but the winners gain more than the losers lose. Deciding whether there is a collective action problem among the states that justifies a national solution (whether Pareto-optimal or not) requires knowing the costs and benefits of different policies for different states. But States may disagree about the payoffs from cooperation or non-cooperation. Depending on what the payoffs turn out to be, what initially looked like a Pareto-optimal result from mandated coordination may actually not be Pareto-optimal, because some states benefit at the expense of others. Moreover, depending on what the payoffs turn out to be, what appeared at first to be a collective action problem may not be a collective action problem at all, because the losers would lose more from mandated cooperation than the winners win. In that case, if cooperation is mandated, what we really have is a cartel imposed at the national level for the benefit of one group of states that imposes costs on a different group of states. The winning states will argue that without mandated coordination there is a race to the bottom, while the losing states will argue that interstate competition is a good thing and that there is actually a race to the top. All of this means that a collective action theory explains and justifies the allocation of federal power to the extent that we can know what the payoffs are for a given type of policy question or a given subject of regulation. But if the payoffs are incorrect or cannot be known, the theory does not explain or justify constitutional arrangements. This problem, in turn, is connected to familiar problems in cost-benefit analysis. First, the parties in the political system are not reliable reporters of costs and benefits. States have incentives to exaggerate the costs to them (and to other states) of national policies they oppose and the benefits of national policies they support. Second, States may claim that the costs imposed by national policies are social or cultural and not easily translated into or compared with costs and benefits in other states. A state may argue, for example, that a proposed national policy would destroy a way of life or undermine important religious, moral, and cultural values within the state. Trying to compare these costs or measure them in dollars is both unjust and futile. Historically, this kind of argument has often been inegalitarian, because it is designed to preserve existing local social status hierarchies from federal interference on the grounds that the federal government should not interfere with "inherently local" subjects like the family, employment relationships (as in Carter Coal), and local customs and mores. But the argument need not be inegalitarian if the mores protected are more egalitarian than those enforced by the national government. Third, cost-benefit collective action problems are defined as those in which the winners from the national policy could, in theory, compensate the losers. This test leads to the well-known problem of whether the baseline of measurement for compensation should be the affected states' willingness to pay to or their willingness to accept. Some states in a federal republic might be at a particular disadvantage if the test is willingness to pay. Fourth, states are collections of different people with different interests and concerns. A national policy that makes some people in a state worse off might make other people in the state better off, and vice-versa. The government of the state may not adequately represent the balance of interests in the state and therefore have a biased estimate of the costs (or benefits) to the state as a whole. Political elites within the state may choose policies that disregard or even oppress less powerful interests, so that the costs and benefits to the latter do not count in the larger calculus of what is best for the nation as a whole. This will skew the analysis of what kind of collective action problem we have, or whether there even is a collective action problem in the first place. (The earlier discussion of local elites trying to preserve status hierarchies is one example. Elites also might be beholden to capital rather than labor, and so on). Fifth, even if a national problem in general requires a national solution, the specific solution national elites choose may be far more intrusive than necessary to solve the problem. The solution may include situations where there is a genuine collective action problem as well situations where there is not. It may impose a solution that is so extensive and intrusive that the benefits to some states no longer outweigh the costs to other states. Put another way, in identifying and resolving a collective action problem, the national government may overreach and impose unnecessary and unjustified costs on some parts of the nation, while giving an unjustified subsidy to other parts. For example, the government may impose environmental rules greater than necessary to solve the collective action problem posed by pollution. It may offer detailed requirements for workplaces that do not actually solve collective action problems but instead simply impose the cultural values of national elites, and so on. Sixth, and relatedly, collective action reasoning is subject to a levels of generality problem. Even if some regulations of commerce solve collective action problems, it does not follow that a general power to regulate commerce can be justified on collective action grounds. Even if a general power to regulate in some area makes sense in the abstract, it may not make sense in a wide range of individual cases. The more general the power, the more likely it is that only some of its applications solve collective action problems and that others do not. Granting a general or abstract power to regulate a particular subject matter throws together situations where there are genuine collective action problems and sitations where there are not. For example, a general federal police power would allow the national govenrment to solve virtually all collective action problems among the states, but it would empower many other kinds of decisions as well. So the plausibility of the argument for federal power can vary depending on the level of generality at which we describe the federal power. This problem of levels of generality emerges in debates over whether national power should be read broadly or narrowly, that is, in perennial debates over loose versus strict construction. II. Deciding Who Decides Collective action arguments, in other words, often rest on controversial judgments and disputable claims about facts, values, causes, and effects. To make a Collective Action Constitution work, therefore, we have to make the kind of institutional judgments about decisionmakers that are familiar to legal process theories. We must make a decision about which actors are best equipped, and under which circumstances, to consider the relevant costs and benefits, decide whether a national solution is warranted, and the proper scope of the national solution. "Best equipped" might mean with the greatest decisional competence, with the greatest legitimacy, or some combination of both. Siegel understands these problems. In general, his solution is to defer to Congress's judgments of three kinds: (1) about whether there is a national problem, (2) about the relative costs and benefits to the states and persons within those states, and (3) about the extent and scope of the solution necessary to solve the collective action problem. Finally, he supports a broad construction of the powers granted to Congress, which means that he assumes that a broad construction of constitutional provisions articulates the scope of federal power at right level of generality. Siegel's basic approach of deferring to Congress and construing federal power broadly rather than narrowly is in most cases a sensible solution. It is the approach that I would choose most of the time, for reasons I'll describe later on. But it is not the only possible approach to collective action problems in a federal republic like the United States. Start from the book's basic claim-- that the national government is and should be empowered to identify and solve collective action problems and that the Constitution should be interpreted accordingly-- and you will discover that there are multiple ways to realize that principle in practice. You can produce different versions of the Collective Action Constitution by assigning to different parties the task of determining (1) the actual costs and benefits of collective action among the various states, (2) the existence or non-existence of a genuine collective action problem, (3) the most appropriate national solutions, and (4) the appropriate level of generality at which to describe the scope of national powers. Hence there is not a single Collective Action Constitution, but multiple possible Collective Action Constitutions, and one must have ways of deciding among them. The principle of collective action by itself cannot decide among them, because, by hypothesis, all of them are exemplars of the principle. Perhaps there are some versions that every reasonable person would agree are very poor at realizing the principle, but this leaves a large set of possible alternatives still in play. Or, to put it another way, the principle of collective action, like all principles, does not determine the scope of its own extension, but can be realized in multiple ways. To give only two examples: First, a constitutional designer might believe courts should create robust judicially enforceable federalism doctrines to prevent Congress from overreaching, given the pathologies of national policy making, the feared domination of national elites who seek to impose their values, and the tendencies of bureaucracies to expand their control over more and more subjects. Second, a constitutional designer might think that an administrative state relatively insulated from electoral competition is especially likely to overreach, engage in empire building, and impose unnecessary and non-cost-benefit justified costs on some of the states, especially those out of sync with the values of dominant national elites. Then one might want courts to create doctrines that require Congress, and not the President acting through the administrative state, to decide whether there is a need for national regulation and the precise scope of that regulation. Both of these examples show that something like comparatively limited federal power, strong judicial review, and a weak administrative state supervised by courts could also be justified under the collective action principle, depending on one's assumptions about how the world works. But those are not Siegel's choices. III. Democratic Legitimacy and Democracy Deficits Siegel's most important argument for deference and for giving Congress its choice of means-- including in the construction of an administrative state-- is democratic legitimacy. Congress represents everyone in the country and specifically represents the States in the Senate. Therefore, if there is a dispute about the nature of a problem, or about the means of solving it, or about both, these questions should be decided by majority rule of the institution that represents the nation as a whole. (In fact, in our world, these questions are actually decided by a supermajority of the Senate plus a majority of the House and subject to a veto by the President that requires a supermajority to overcome.) Courts should also defer to Congress's judgments about the scope of national power unless its judgments are unreasonable (which, Siegel points out, is not the same thing as the rational basis test.) One problem, as Siegel notes, is that Congress is an imperfect institution with collective action problems of its own. In our current era of deeply polarized politics, Congress finds it difficult to promote the public good because it is often gridlocked, which has led the President and the courts to take over a great deal of national policy making. This kind of gridlock is not a permanent condition-- we had something very similar during the First Gilded Age, as I pointed out in my book The Cycles of Constitutional Time. So perhaps Siegel's argument for deference to Congress makes the most sense viewed over the long run. Even so, the argument from democratic legitimacy cuts both ways. Alongside the expansion of national power that came with the New Deal Settlement and its principle of deference to democratic majorities in ordinary social and economic legislation was the related principle of democracy-protection. Courts should employ judicial review to prevent overreaching by majorities who pass laws that undermine democratic processes or that impose special burdens on minority groups unable to protect themselves adequately in the political process. The question, then, is whether a judicial duty of democracy-protection also applies to states and state interests. The theory of the Collective Action Constitution is consequentialist and does not treat the states has having rights. But one way of counteracting democracy deficits or threats to democracy is through creating judicially enforceable rights, privileges and immunities. So, perhaps ironically, one possible Collective Action Constitution would call for strong judicial review to protect states from overreaching by the national government and defer to Congress only in cases where, in the court's view, there was a genuine collective action problem. This would lead to something like the dual federalism approach that the New Deal Settlement jettisoned. And it might be justified in part in terms of the intangible or incommensurable traditional local values I described above. But here's the problem with this "democracy protection for states" argument. We now have over two centuries of experience with judicial protection of "states' rights" or the "dignity of the states." What we have learned from this experience is that the kinds of doctrines that courts have created to protect state interests rarely have much to do with the logic of collective action. The distinctions that courts have drawn over the years-- for example, between manufacturing and commerce, or between direct and indirect effects on commerce--are usually orthogonal to the economic analysis of collective action described in Siegel's book. Even the distinction drawn in Lopez and Morrison between economic and non-economic activities does not really correspond to this logic, since there are plenty of non-economic activities that have significant spillover effects and create collective action problems. (The same is true of the act/omission distinction that appears in NFIB v. Sebelius.) Courts may well have some role in policing state-federal boundaries in a Collective Action Constitution: judicial review in preemption and dormant commerce clause are two examples. Nevertheless, the kinds of doctrinal formalisms that courts regularly create to protect state interests from federal overreaching routinely miss the mark. In most cases they do not further the goals of the Collective Action Constitution but undermine them or at best are orthogonal to them. If history shows that courts will not create doctrines that adequately police Congress's judgments, this supports Siegel's general view that deference to Congress is the best policy.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |